LAWS

by Plato




Translated by Benjamin Jowett




INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.

The genuineness of the Laws is sufficiently proved (1) by more than twenty
citations of them in the writings of Aristotle, who was residing at Athens
during the last twenty years of the life of Plato, and who, having left it
after his death (B.C. 347), returned thither twelve years later (B.C. 335);
(2) by the allusion of Isocrates 

(Oratio ad Philippum missa, p.84:  To men tais paneguresin enochlein kai
pros apantas legein tous sunprechontas en autais pros oudena legein estin,
all omoios oi toioutoi ton logon (sc. speeches in the assembly) akuroi
tugchanousin ontes tois nomois kai tais politeiais tais upo ton sophiston
gegrammenais.)

--writing 346 B.C., a year after the death of Plato, and probably not more
than three or four years after the composition of the Laws--who speaks of
the Laws and Republics written by philosophers (upo ton sophiston); (3) by
the reference (Athen.) of the comic poet Alexis, a younger contemporary of
Plato (fl. B.C 356-306), to the enactment about prices, which occurs in
Laws xi., viz that the same goods should not be offered at two prices on
the same day

(Ou gegone kreitton nomothetes tou plousiou
Aristonikou tithesi gar nuni nomon,
ton ichthuopolon ostis an polon tini
ichthun upotimesas apodot elattonos
es eipe times, eis to desmoterion
euthus apagesthai touton, ina dedoikotes
tes axias agaposin, e tes esperas
saprous apantas apopherosin oikade.

Meineke, Frag. Com. Graec.);

(4) by the unanimous voice of later antiquity and the absence of any
suspicion among ancient writers worth speaking of to the contrary; for it
is not said of Philippus of Opus that he composed any part of the Laws, but
only that he copied them out of the waxen tablets, and was thought by some
to have written the Epinomis (Diog. Laert.)  That the longest and one of
the best writings bearing the name of Plato should be a forgery, even if
its genuineness were unsupported by external testimony, would be a singular
phenomenon in ancient literature; and although the critical worth of the
consensus of late writers is generally not to be compared with the express
testimony of contemporaries, yet a somewhat greater value may be attributed
to their consent in the present instance, because the admission of the Laws
is combined with doubts about the Epinomis, a spurious writing, which is a
kind of epilogue to the larger work probably of a much later date.  This
shows that the reception of the Laws was not altogether undiscriminating.

The suspicion which has attached to the Laws of Plato in the judgment of
some modern writers appears to rest partly (1) on differences in the style
and form of the work, and (2) on differences of thought and opinion which
they observe in them.  Their suspicion is increased by the fact that these
differences are accompanied by resemblances as striking to passages in
other Platonic writings.  They are sensible of a want of point in the
dialogue and a general inferiority in the ideas, plan, manners, and style. 
They miss the poetical flow, the dramatic verisimilitude, the life and
variety of the characters, the dialectic subtlety, the Attic purity, the
luminous order, the exquisite urbanity; instead of which they find
tautology, obscurity, self-sufficiency, sermonizing, rhetorical
declamation, pedantry, egotism, uncouth forms of sentences, and
peculiarities in the use of words and idioms.  They are unable to discover
any unity in the patched, irregular structure.  The speculative element
both in government and education is superseded by a narrow economical or
religious vein.  The grace and cheerfulness of Athenian life have
disappeared; and a spirit of moroseness and religious intolerance has taken
their place.  The charm of youth is no longer there; the mannerism of age
makes itself unpleasantly felt.  The connection is often imperfect; and
there is a want of arrangement, exhibited especially in the enumeration of
the laws towards the end of the work.  The Laws are full of flaws and
repetitions.  The Greek is in places very ungrammatical and intractable.  A
cynical levity is displayed in some passages, and a tone of disappointment
and lamentation over human things in others.  The critics seem also to
observe in them bad imitations of thoughts which are better expressed in
Plato's other writings.  Lastly, they wonder how the mind which conceived
the Republic could have left the Critias, Hermocrates, and Philosophus
incomplete or unwritten, and have devoted the last years of life to the
Laws.

The questions which have been thus indirectly suggested may be considered
by us under five or six heads:  I, the characters; II, the plan; III, the
style; IV, the imitations of other writings of Plato; V; the more general
relation of the Laws to the Republic and the other dialogues; and VI, to
the existing Athenian and Spartan states.

I.  Already in the Philebus the distinctive character of Socrates has
disappeared; and in the Timaeus, Sophist, and Statesman his function of
chief speaker is handed over to the Pythagorean philosopher Timaeus, and to
the Eleatic Stranger, at whose feet he sits, and is silent.  More and more
Plato seems to have felt in his later writings that the character and
method of Socrates were no longer suited to be the vehicle of his own
philosophy.  He is no longer interrogative but dogmatic; not 'a hesitating
enquirer,' but one who speaks with the authority of a legislator.  Even in
the Republic we have seen that the argument which is carried on by Socrates
in the old style with Thrasymachus in the first book, soon passes into the
form of exposition.  In the Laws he is nowhere mentioned.  Yet so
completely in the tradition of antiquity is Socrates identified with Plato,
that in the criticism of the Laws which we find in the so-called Politics
of Aristotle he is supposed by the writer still to be playing his part of
the chief speaker (compare Pol.).

The Laws are discussed by three representatives of Athens, Crete, and
Sparta.  The Athenian, as might be expected, is the protagonist or chief
speaker, while the second place is assigned to the Cretan, who, as one of
the leaders of a new colony, has a special interest in the conversation. 
At least four-fifths of the answers are put into his mouth.  The Spartan is
every inch a soldier, a man of few words himself, better at deeds than
words.  The Athenian talks to the two others, although they are his equals
in age, in the style of a master discoursing to his scholars; he frequently
praises himself; he entertains a very poor opinion of the understanding of
his companions.  Certainly the boastfulness and rudeness of the Laws is the
reverse of the refined irony and courtesy which characterize the earlier
dialogues.  We are no longer in such good company as in the Phaedrus and
Symposium.  Manners are lost sight of in the earnestness of the speakers,
and dogmatic assertions take the place of poetical fancies.

The scene is laid in Crete, and the conversation is held in the course of a
walk from Cnosus to the cave and temple of Zeus, which takes place on one
of the longest and hottest days of the year.  The companions start at dawn,
and arrive at the point in their conversation which terminates the fourth
book, about noon.  The God to whose temple they are going is the lawgiver
of Crete, and this may be supposed to be the very cave at which he gave his
oracles to Minos.  But the externals of the scene, which are briefly and
inartistically described, soon disappear, and we plunge abruptly into the
subject of the dialogue.  We are reminded by contrast of the higher art of
the Phaedrus, in which the summer's day, and the cool stream, and the
chirping of the grasshoppers, and the fragrance of the agnus castus, and
the legends of the place are present to the imagination throughout the
discourse.

The typical Athenian apologizes for the tendency of his countrymen 'to spin
a long discussion out of slender materials,' and in a similar spirit the
Lacedaemonian Megillus apologizes for the Spartan brevity (compare
Thucydid.), acknowledging at the same time that there may be occasions when
long discourses are necessary.  The family of Megillus is the proxenus of
Athens at Sparta; and he pays a beautiful compliment to the Athenian,
significant of the character of the work, which, though borrowing many
elements from Sparta, is also pervaded by an Athenian spirit.  A good
Athenian, he says, is more than ordinarily good, because he is inspired by
nature and not manufactured by law.  The love of listening which is
attributed to the Timocrat in the Republic is also exhibited in him.  The
Athenian on his side has a pleasure in speaking to the Lacedaemonian of the
struggle in which their ancestors were jointly engaged against the
Persians.  A connexion with Athens is likewise intimated by the Cretan
Cleinias.  He is the relative of Epimenides, whom, by an anachronism of a
century,--perhaps arising as Zeller suggests (Plat. Stud.) out of a
confusion of the visit of Epimenides and Diotima (Symp.),--he describes as
coming to Athens, not after the attempt of Cylon, but ten years before the
Persian war.  The Cretan and Lacedaemonian hardly contribute at all to the
argument of which the Athenian is the expounder; they only supply
information when asked about the institutions of their respective
countries.  A kind of simplicity or stupidity is ascribed to them.  At
first, they are dissatisfied with the free criticisms which the Athenian
passes upon the laws of Minos and Lycurgus, but they acquiesce in his
greater experience and knowledge of the world.  They admit that there can
be no objection to the enquiry; for in the spirit of the legislator
himself, they are discussing his laws when there are no young men present
to listen.  They are unwilling to allow that the Spartan and Cretan
lawgivers can have been mistaken in honouring courage as the first part of
virtue, and are puzzled at hearing for the first time that 'Goods are only
evil to the evil.'  Several times they are on the point of quarrelling, and
by an effort learn to restrain their natural feeling (compare Shakespeare,
Henry V, act iii. sc. 2).  In Book vii., the Lacedaemonian expresses a
momentary irritation at the accusation which the Athenian brings against
the Spartan institutions, of encouraging licentiousness in their women, but
he is reminded by the Cretan that the permission to criticize them freely
has been given, and cannot be retracted.  His only criterion of truth is
the authority of the Spartan lawgiver; he is 'interested,' in the novel
speculations of the Athenian, but inclines to prefer the ordinances of
Lycurgus.

The three interlocutors all of them speak in the character of old men,
which forms a pleasant bond of union between them.  They have the feelings
of old age about youth, about the state, about human things in general. 
Nothing in life seems to be of much importance to them; they are spectators
rather than actors, and men in general appear to the Athenian speaker to be
the playthings of the Gods and of circumstances.  Still they have a
fatherly care of the young, and are deeply impressed by sentiments of
religion.  They would give confidence to the aged by an increasing use of
wine, which, as they get older, is to unloose their tongues and make them
sing.  The prospect of the existence of the soul after death is constantly
present to them; though they can hardly be said to have the cheerful hope
and resignation which animates Socrates in the Phaedo or Cephalus in the
Republic.  Plato appears to be expressing his own feelings in remarks of
this sort.  For at the time of writing the first book of the Laws he was at
least seventy-four years of age, if we suppose him to allude to the victory
of the Syracusans under Dionysius the Younger over the Locrians, which
occurred in the year 356.  Such a sadness was the natural effect of
declining years and failing powers, which make men ask, 'After all, what
profit is there in life?'  They feel that their work is beginning to be
over, and are ready to say, 'All the world is a stage;' or, in the actual
words of Plato, 'Let us play as good plays as we can,' though 'we must be
sometimes serious, which is not agreeable, but necessary.'  These are
feelings which have crossed the minds of reflective persons in all ages,
and there is no reason to connect the Laws any more than other parts of
Plato's writings with the very uncertain narrative of his life, or to
imagine that this melancholy tone is attributable to disappointment at
having failed to convert a Sicilian tyrant into a philosopher.

II.  The plan of the Laws is more irregular and has less connexion than any
other of the writings of Plato.  As Aristotle says in the Politics, 'The
greater part consists of laws'; in Books v, vi, xi, xii the dialogue almost
entirely disappears.  Large portions of them are rather the materials for a
work than a finished composition which may rank with the other Platonic
dialogues.  To use his own image, 'Some stones are regularly inserted in
the building; others are lying on the ground ready for use.'  There is
probably truth in the tradition that the Laws were not published until
after the death of Plato.  We can easily believe that he has left
imperfections, which would have been removed if he had lived a few years
longer.  The arrangement might have been improved; the connexion of the
argument might have been made plainer, and the sentences more accurately
framed.  Something also may be attributed to the feebleness of old age. 
Even a rough sketch of the Phaedrus or Symposium would have had a very
different look.  There is, however, an interest in possessing one writing
of Plato which is in the process of creation.

We must endeavour to find a thread of order which will carry us through
this comparative disorder.  The first four books are described by Plato
himself as the preface or preamble.  Having arrived at the conclusion that
each law should have a preamble, the lucky thought occurs to him at the end
of the fourth book that the preceding discourse is the preamble of the
whole.  This preamble or introduction may be abridged as follows:--

The institutions of Sparta and Crete are admitted by the Lacedaemonian and
Cretan to have one aim only:  they were intended by the legislator to
inspire courage in war.  To this the Athenian objects that the true
lawgiver should frame his laws with a view to all the virtues and not to
one only.  Better is he who has temperance as well as courage, than he who
has courage only; better is he who is faithful in civil broils, than he who
is a good soldier only.  Better, too, is peace than war; the reconciliation
than the defeat of an enemy.  And he who would attain all virtue should be
trained amid pleasures as well as pains.  Hence there should be convivial
intercourse among the citizens, and a man's temperance should be tested in
his cups, as we test his courage amid dangers.  He should have a fear of
the right sort, as well as a courage of the right sort.

At the beginning of the second book the subject of pleasure leads to
education, which in the early years of life is wholly a discipline imparted
by the means of pleasure and pain.  The discipline of pleasure is implanted
chiefly by the practice of the song and the dance.  Of these the forms
should be fixed, and not allowed to depend on the fickle breath of the
multitude.  There will be choruses of boys, girls, and grown-up persons,
and all will be heard repeating the same strain, that 'virtue is
happiness.'  One of them will give the law to the rest; this will be the
chorus of aged minstrels, who will sing the most beautiful and the most
useful of songs.  They will require a little wine, to mellow the austerity
of age, and make them amenable to the laws.

After having laid down as the first principle of politics, that peace, and
not war, is the true aim of the legislator, and briefly discussed music and
festive intercourse, at the commencement of the third book Plato makes a
digression, in which he speaks of the origin of society.  He describes,
first of all, the family; secondly, the patriarchal stage, which is an
aggregation of families; thirdly, the founding of regular cities, like
Ilium; fourthly, the establishment of a military and political system, like
that of Sparta, with which he identifies Argos and Messene, dating from the
return of the Heraclidae.  But the aims of states should be good, or else,
like the prayer of Theseus, they may be ruinous to themselves.  This was
the case in two out of three of the Heracleid kingdoms.  They did not
understand that the powers in a state should be balanced.  The balance of
powers saved Sparta, while the excess of tyranny in Persia and the excess
of liberty at Athens have been the ruin of both...This discourse on
politics is suddenly discovered to have an immediate practical use; for
Cleinias the Cretan is about to give laws to a new colony.

At the beginning of the fourth book, after enquiring into the circumstances
and situation of the colony, the Athenian proceeds to make further
reflections.  Chance, and God, and the skill of the legislator, all co-
operate in the formation of states.  And the most favourable condition for
the foundation of a new one is when the government is in the hands of a
virtuous tyrant who has the good fortune to be the contemporary of a great
legislator.  But a virtuous tyrant is a contradiction in terms; we can at
best only hope to have magistrates who are the servants of reason and the
law.  This leads to the enquiry, what is to be the polity of our new state.
And the answer is, that we are to fear God, and honour our parents, and to
cultivate virtue and justice; these are to be our first principles.  Laws
must be definite, and we should create in the citizens a predisposition to
obey them.  The legislator will teach as well as command; and with this
view he will prefix preambles to his principal laws.

The fifth book commences in a sort of dithyramb with another and higher
preamble about the honour due to the soul, whence are deduced the duties of
a man to his parents and his friends, to the suppliant and stranger.  He
should be true and just, free from envy and excess of all sorts, forgiving
to crimes which are not incurable and are partly involuntary; and he should
have a true taste.  The noblest life has the greatest pleasures and the
fewest pains...Having finished the preamble, and touched on some other
preliminary considerations, we proceed to the Laws, beginning with the
constitution of the state.  This is not the best or ideal state, having all
things common, but only the second-best, in which the land and houses are
to be distributed among 5040 citizens divided into four classes.  There is
to be no gold or silver among them, and they are to have moderate wealth,
and to respect number and numerical order in all things.

In the first part of the sixth book, Plato completes his sketch of the
constitution by the appointment of officers.  He explains the manner in
which guardians of the law, generals, priests, wardens of town and country,
ministers of education, and other magistrates are to be appointed; and also
in what way courts of appeal are to be constituted, and omissions in the
law to be supplied.  Next--and at this point the Laws strictly speaking
begin--there follow enactments respecting marriage and the procreation of
children, respecting property in slaves as well as of other kinds,
respecting houses, married life, common tables for men and women.  The
question of age in marriage suggests the consideration of a similar
question about the time for holding offices, and for military service,
which had been previously omitted.

Resuming the order of the discussion, which was indicated in the previous
book, from marriage and birth we proceed to education in the seventh book. 
Education is to begin at or rather before birth; to be continued for a time
by mothers and nurses under the supervision of the state; finally, to
comprehend music and gymnastics.  Under music is included reading, writing,
playing on the lyre, arithmetic, geometry, and a knowledge of astronomy
sufficient to preserve the minds of the citizens from impiety in after-
life.  Gymnastics are to be practised chiefly with a view to their use in
war.  The discussion of education, which was lightly touched upon in Book
ii, is here completed.

The eighth book contains regulations for civil life, beginning with
festivals, games, and contests, military exercises and the like.  On such
occasions Plato seems to see young men and maidens meeting together, and
hence he is led into discussing the relations of the sexes, the evil
consequences which arise out of the indulgence of the passions, and the
remedies for them.  Then he proceeds to speak of agriculture, of arts and
trades, of buying and selling, and of foreign commerce.

The remaining books of the Laws, ix-xii, are chiefly concerned with
criminal offences.  In the first class are placed offences against the
Gods, especially sacrilege or robbery of temples:  next follow offences
against the state,--conspiracy, treason, theft.  The mention of thefts
suggests a distinction between voluntary and involuntary, curable and
incurable offences.  Proceeding to the greater crime of homicide, Plato
distinguishes between mere homicide, manslaughter, which is partly
voluntary and partly involuntary, and murder, which arises from avarice,
ambition, fear.  He also enumerates murders by kindred, murders by slaves,
wounds with or without intent to kill, wounds inflicted in anger, crimes of
or against slaves, insults to parents.  To these, various modes of
purification or degrees of punishment are assigned, and the terrors of
another world are also invoked against them.

At the beginning of Book x, all acts of violence, including sacrilege, are
summed up in a single law.  The law is preceded by an admonition, in which
the offenders are informed that no one ever did an unholy act or said an
unlawful word while he retained his belief in the existence of the Gods;
but either he denied their existence, or he believed that they took no care
of man, or that they might be turned from their course by sacrifices and
prayers.  The remainder of the book is devoted to the refutation of these
three classes of unbelievers, and concludes with the means to be taken for
their reformation, and the announcement of their punishments if they
continue obstinate and impenitent.

The eleventh book is taken up with laws and with admonitions relating to
individuals, which follow one another without any exact order.  There are
laws concerning deposits and the finding of treasure; concerning slaves and
freedmen; concerning retail trade, bequests, divorces, enchantments,
poisonings, magical arts, and the like.  In the twelfth book the same
subjects are continued.  Laws are passed concerning violations of military
discipline, concerning the high office of the examiners and their burial;
concerning oaths and the violation of them, and the punishments of those
who neglect their duties as citizens.  Foreign travel is then discussed,
and the permission to be accorded to citizens of journeying in foreign
parts; the strangers who may come to visit the city are also spoken of, and
the manner in which they are to be received.  Laws are added respecting
sureties, searches for property, right of possession by prescription,
abduction of witnesses, theatrical competition, waging of private warfare,
and bribery in offices.  Rules are laid down respecting taxation,
respecting economy in sacred rites, respecting judges, their duties and
sentences, and respecting sepulchral places and ceremonies.  Here the Laws
end.  Lastly, a Nocturnal Council is instituted for the preservation of the
state, consisting of older and younger members, who are to exhibit in their
lives that virtue which is the basis of the state, to know the one in many,
and to be educated in divine and every other kind of knowledge which will
enable them to fulfil their office.

III.  The style of the Laws differs in several important respects from that
of the other dialogues of Plato:  (1) in the want of character, power, and
lively illustration; (2) in the frequency of mannerisms (compare
Introduction to the Philebus); (3) in the form and rhythm of the sentences;
(4) in the use of words.  On the other hand, there are many passages (5)
which are characterized by a sort of ethical grandeur; and (6) in which,
perhaps, a greater insight into human nature, and a greater reach of
practical wisdom is shown, than in any other of Plato's writings.

1.  The discourse of the three old men is described by themselves as an old
man's game of play.  Yet there is little of the liveliness of a game in
their mode of treating the subject.  They do not throw the ball to and fro,
but two out of the three are listeners to the third, who is constantly
asserting his superior wisdom and opportunities of knowledge, and
apologizing (not without reason) for his own want of clearness of speech.
He will 'carry them over the stream;' he will answer for them when the
argument is beyond their comprehension; he is afraid of their ignorance of
mathematics, and thinks that gymnastic is likely to be more intelligible to
them;--he has repeated his words several times, and yet they cannot
understand him.  The subject did not properly take the form of dialogue,
and also the literary vigour of Plato had passed away.  The old men speak
as they might be expected to speak, and in this there is a touch of
dramatic truth.  Plato has given the Laws that form or want of form which
indicates the failure of natural power.  There is no regular plan--none of
that consciousness of what has preceded and what is to follow, which makes
a perfect style,--but there are several attempts at a plan; the argument is
'pulled up,' and frequent explanations are offered why a particular topic
was introduced.

The fictions of the Laws have no longer the verisimilitude which is
characteristic of the Phaedrus and the Timaeus, or even of the Statesman. 
We can hardly suppose that an educated Athenian would have placed the visit
of Epimenides to Athens ten years before the Persian war, or have imagined
that a war with Messene prevented the Lacedaemonians from coming to the
rescue of Hellas.  The narrative of the origin of the Dorian institutions,
which are said to have been due to a fear of the growing power of the
Assyrians, is a plausible invention, which may be compared with the tale of
the island of Atlantis and the poem of Solon, but is not accredited by
similar arts of deception.  The other statement that the Dorians were
Achaean exiles assembled by Dorieus, and the assertion that Troy was
included in the Assyrian Empire, have some foundation (compare for the
latter point, Diod. Sicul.).  Nor is there anywhere in the Laws that lively
enargeia, that vivid mise en scene, which is as characteristic of Plato as
of some modern novelists.

The old men are afraid of the ridicule which 'will fall on their heads more
than enough,' and they do not often indulge in a joke.  In one of the few
which occur, the book of the Laws, if left incomplete, is compared to a
monster wandering about without a head.  But we no longer breathe the
atmosphere of humour which pervades the Symposium and the Euthydemus, in
which we pass within a few sentences from the broadest Aristophanic joke to
the subtlest refinement of wit and fancy; instead of this, in the Laws an
impression of baldness and feebleness is often left upon our minds.  Some
of the most amusing descriptions, as, for example, of children roaring for
the first three years of life; or of the Athenians walking into the country
with fighting-cocks under their arms; or of the slave doctor who knocks
about his patients finely; and the gentleman doctor who courteously
persuades them; or of the way of keeping order in the theatre, 'by a hint
from a stick,' are narrated with a commonplace gravity; but where we find
this sort of dry humour we shall not be far wrong in thinking that the
writer intended to make us laugh.  The seriousness of age takes the place
of the jollity of youth.  Life should have holidays and festivals; yet we
rebuke ourselves when we laugh, and take our pleasures sadly.  The irony of
the earlier dialogues, of which some traces occur in the tenth book, is
replaced by a severity which hardly condescends to regard human things. 
'Let us say, if you please, that man is of some account, but I was speaking
of him in comparison with God.'

The imagery and illustrations are poor in themselves, and are not assisted
by the surrounding phraseology.  We have seen how in the Republic, and in
the earlier dialogues, figures of speech such as 'the wave,' 'the drone,'
'the chase,' 'the bride,' appear and reappear at intervals.  Notes are
struck which are repeated from time to time, as in a strain of music. 
There is none of this subtle art in the Laws.  The illustrations, such as
the two kinds of doctors, 'the three kinds of funerals,' the fear potion,
the puppet, the painter leaving a successor to restore his picture, the
'person stopping to consider where three ways meet,' the 'old laws about
water of which he will not divert the course,' can hardly be said to do
much credit to Plato's invention.  The citations from the poets have lost
that fanciful character which gave them their charm in the earlier
dialogues.  We are tired of images taken from the arts of navigation, or
archery, or weaving, or painting, or medicine, or music.  Yet the
comparisons of life to a tragedy, or of the working of mind to the
revolution of the self-moved, or of the aged parent to the image of a God
dwelling in the house, or the reflection that 'man is made to be the
plaything of God, and that this rightly considered is the best of him,'
have great beauty.

2.  The clumsiness of the style is exhibited in frequent mannerisms and
repetitions.  The perfection of the Platonic dialogue consists in the
accuracy with which the question and answer are fitted into one another,
and the regularity with which the steps of the argument succeed one
another.  This finish of style is no longer discernible in the Laws.  There
is a want of variety in the answers; nothing can be drawn out of the
respondents but 'Yes' or 'No,' 'True,' 'To be sure,' etc.; the insipid
forms, 'What do you mean?'  'To what are you referring?' are constantly
returning.  Again and again the speaker is charged, or charges himself,
with obscurity; and he repeats again and again that he will explain his
views more clearly.  The process of thought which should be latent in the
mind of the writer appears on the surface.  In several passages the
Athenian praises himself in the most unblushing manner, very unlike the
irony of the earlier dialogues, as when he declares that 'the laws are a
divine work given by some inspiration of the Gods,' and that 'youth should
commit them to memory instead of the compositions of the poets.'  The
prosopopoeia which is adopted by Plato in the Protagoras and other
dialogues is repeated until we grow weary of it.  The legislator is always
addressing the speakers or the youth of the state, and the speakers are
constantly making addresses to the legislator.  A tendency to a paradoxical
manner of statement is also observable.  'We must have drinking,' 'we must
have a virtuous tyrant'--this is too much for the duller wits of the
Lacedaemonian and Cretan, who at first start back in surprise.  More than
in any other writing of Plato the tone is hortatory; the laws are sermons
as well as laws; they are considered to have a religious sanction, and to
rest upon a religious sentiment in the mind of the citizens.  The words of
the Athenian are attributed to the Lacedaemonian and Cretan, who are
supposed to have made them their own, after the manner of the earlier
dialogues.  Resumptions of subjects which have been half disposed of in a
previous passage constantly occur:  the arrangement has neither the
clearness of art nor the freedom of nature.  Irrelevant remarks are made
here and there, or illustrations used which are not properly fitted in. 
The dialogue is generally weak and laboured, and is in the later books
fairly given up, apparently, because unsuited to the subject of the work. 
The long speeches or sermons of the Athenian, often extending over several
pages, have never the grace and harmony which are exhibited in the earlier
dialogues.  For Plato is incapable of sustained composition; his genius is
dramatic rather than oratorical; he can converse, but he cannot make a
speech.  Even the Timaeus, which is one of his most finished works, is full
of abrupt transitions.  There is the same kind of difference between the
dialogue and the continuous discourse of Plato as between the narrative and
speeches of Thucydides.

3.  The perfection of style is variety in unity, freedom, ease, clearness,
the power of saying anything, and of striking any note in the scale of
human feelings without impropriety; and such is the divine gift of language
possessed by Plato in the Symposium and Phaedrus.  From this there are many
fallings-off in the Laws:  first, in the structure of the sentences, which
are rhythmical and monotonous,--the formal and sophistical manner of the
age is superseding the natural genius of Plato:  secondly, many of them are
of enormous length, and the latter end often forgets the beginning of
them,--they seem never to have received the second thoughts of the author;
either the emphasis is wrongly placed, or there is a want of point in a
clause; or an absolute case occurs which is not properly separated from the
rest of the sentence; or words are aggregated in a manner which fails to
show their relation to one another; or the connecting particles are omitted
at the beginning of sentences; the uses of the relative and antecedent are
more indistinct, the changes of person and number more frequent, examples
of pleonasm, tautology, and periphrasis, antitheses of positive and
negative, false emphasis, and other affectations, are more numerous than in
the other writings of Plato; there is also a more common and sometimes
unmeaning use of qualifying formulae, os epos eipein, kata dunamin, and of
double expressions, pante pantos, oudame oudamos, opos kai ope--these are
too numerous to be attributed to errors in the text; again, there is an
over-curious adjustment of verb and participle, noun and epithet, and other
artificial forms of cadence and expression take the place of natural
variety:  thirdly, the absence of metaphorical language is remarkable--the
style is not devoid of ornament, but the ornament is of a debased
rhetorical kind, patched on to instead of growing out of the subject; there
is a great command of words, and a laboured use of them; forced attempts at
metaphor occur in several passages,--e.g. parocheteuein logois; ta men os
tithemena ta d os paratithemena; oinos kolazomenos upo nephontos eterou
theou; the plays on the word nomos = nou dianome, ode etara:  fourthly,
there is a foolish extravagance of language in other passages,--'the
swinish ignorance of arithmetic;' 'the justice and suitableness of the
discourse on laws;' over-emphasis; 'best of Greeks,' said of all the
Greeks, and the like:  fifthly, poor and insipid illustrations are also
common: sixthly, we may observe an excessive use of climax and hyperbole,
aischron legein chre pros autous doulon te kai doulen kai paida kai ei pos
oion te olen ten oikian:  dokei touto to epitedeuma kata phusin tas peri ta
aphrodisia edonas ou monon anthropon alla kai therion diephtharkenai.

4.  The peculiarities in the use of words which occur in the Laws have been
collected by Zeller (Platonische Studien) and Stallbaum (Legg.):  first, in
the use of nouns, such as allodemia, apeniautesis, glukuthumia, diatheter,
thrasuxenia, koros, megalonoia, paidourgia:  secondly, in the use of
adjectives, such as aistor, biodotes, echthodopos, eitheos, chronios, and
of adverbs, such as aniditi, anatei, nepoivei:  thirdly, in the use of
verbs, such as athurein, aissein (aixeien eipein), euthemoneisthai,
parapodizesthai, sebein, temelein, tetan.  These words however, as
Stallbaum remarks, are formed according to analogy, and nearly all of them
have the support of some poetical or other authority.

Zeller and Stallbaum have also collected forms of words in the Laws,
differing from the forms of the same words which occur in other places: 
e.g. blabos for blabe, abios for abiotos, acharistos for acharis, douleios
for doulikos, paidelos for paidikos, exagrio for exagriaino, ileoumai for
ilaskomai, and the Ionic word sophronistus, meaning 'correction.'  Zeller
has noted a fondness for substantives ending in -ma and -sis, such as
georgema, diapauma, epithumema, zemioma, komodema, omilema; blapsis,
loidoresis, paraggelsis, and others; also a use of substantives in the
plural, which are commonly found only in the singular, maniai, atheotetes,
phthonoi, phoboi, phuseis; also, a peculiar use of prepositions in
composition, as in eneirgo, apoblapto, dianomotheteo, dieiretai,
dieulabeisthai, and other words; also, a frequent occurrence of the Ionic
datives plural in -aisi and -oisi, perhaps used for the sake of giving an
ancient or archaic effect.

To these peculiarities of words he has added a list of peculiar expressions
and constructions.  Among the most characteristic are the following: 
athuta pallakon spermata; amorphoi edrai; osa axiomata pros archontas; oi
kata polin kairoi; muthos, used in several places of 'the discourse about
laws;' and connected with this the frequent use of paramuthion and
paramutheisthai in the general sense of 'address,' 'addressing'; aimulos
eros; ataphoi praxeis; muthos akephalos; ethos euthuporon.  He remarks also
on the frequent employment of the abstract for the concrete; e.g. uperesia
for uperetai, phugai for phugades, mechanai in the sense of 'contrivers,'
douleia for douloi, basileiai for basileis, mainomena kedeumata for ganaika
mainomenen; e chreia ton paidon in the sense of 'indigent children,' and
paidon ikanotes; to ethos tes apeirias for e eiothuia apeiria; kuparitton
upse te kai kalle thaumasia for kuparittoi mala upselai kai kalai.  He
further notes some curious uses of the genitive case, e.g. philias
omologiai, maniai orges, laimargiai edones, cheimonon anupodesiai, anosioi
plegon tolmai; and of the dative, omiliai echthrois, nomothesiai, anosioi
plegon tolmai; and of the dative omiliai echthrois, nomothesiai epitropois;
and also some rather uncommon periphrases, thremmata Neilou, xuggennetor
teknon for alochos, Mouses lexis for poiesis, zographon paides, anthropon
spermata and the like; the fondness for particles of limitation, especially
tis and ge, sun tisi charisi, tois ge dunamenois and the like; the
pleonastic use of tanun, of os, of os eros eipein, of ekastote; and the
periphrastic use of the preposition peri.  Lastly, he observes the tendency
to hyperbata or transpositions of words, and to rhythmical uniformity as
well as grammatical irregularity in the structure of the sentences.

For nearly all the expressions which are adduced by Zeller as arguments
against the genuineness of the Laws, Stallbaum finds some sort of
authority.  There is no real ground for doubting that the work was written
by Plato, merely because several words occur in it which are not found in
his other writings.  An imitator may preserve the usual phraseology of a
writer better than he would himself.  But, on the other hand, the fact that
authorities may be quoted in support of most of these uses of words, does
not show that the diction is not peculiar.  Several of them seem to be
poetical or dialectical, and exhibit an attempt to enlarge the limits of
Greek prose by the introduction of Homeric and tragic expressions.  Most of
them do not appear to have retained any hold on the later language of
Greece.  Like several experiments in language of the writers of the
Elizabethan age, they were afterwards lost; and though occasionally found
in Plutarch and imitators of Plato, they have not been accepted by
Aristotle or passed into the common dialect of Greece.

5.  Unequal as the Laws are in style, they contain a few passages which are
very grand and noble.  For example, the address to the poets:  'Best of
strangers, we also are poets of the best and noblest tragedy; for our whole
state is an imitation of the best and noblest life, which we affirm to be
indeed the very truth of tragedy.'  Or again, the sight of young men and
maidens in friendly intercourse with one another, suggesting the dangers to
which youth is liable from the violence of passion; or the eloquent
denunciation of unnatural lusts in the same passage; or the charming
thought that the best legislator 'orders war for the sake of peace and not
peace for the sake of war;' or the pleasant allusion, 'O Athenian--
inhabitant of Attica, I will not say, for you seem to me worthy to be named
after the Goddess Athene because you go back to first principles;' or the
pithy saying, 'Many a victory has been and will be suicidal to the victors,
but education is never suicidal;' or the fine expression that 'the walls of
a city should be allowed to sleep in the earth, and that we should not
attempt to disinter them;' or the remark that 'God is the measure of all
things in a sense far higher than any man can be;' or that 'a man should be
from the first a partaker of the truth, that he may live a true man as long
as possible;' or the principle repeatedly laid down, that 'the sins of the
fathers are not to be visited on the children;' or the description of the
funeral rites of those priestly sages who depart in innocence; or the noble
sentiment, that we should do more justice to slaves than to equals; or the
curious observation, founded, perhaps, on his own experience, that there
are a few 'divine men in every state however corrupt, whose conversation is
of inestimable value;' or the acute remark, that public opinion is to be
respected, because the judgments of mankind about virtue are better than
their practice; or the deep religious and also modern feeling which
pervades the tenth book (whatever may be thought of the arguments); the
sense of the duty of living as a part of a whole, and in dependence on the
will of God, who takes care of the least things as well as the greatest;
and the picture of parents praying for their children--not as we may say,
slightly altering the words of Plato, as if there were no truth or reality
in the Gentile religions, but as if there were the greatest--are very
striking to us.  We must remember that the Laws, unlike the Republic, do
not exhibit an ideal state, but are supposed to be on the level of human
motives and feelings; they are also on the level of the popular religion,
though elevated and purified:  hence there is an attempt made to show that
the pleasant is also just.  But, on the other hand, the priority of the
soul to the body, and of God to the soul, is always insisted upon as the
true incentive to virtue; especially with great force and eloquence at the
commencement of Book v.  And the work of legislation is carried back to the
first principles of morals.

6.  No other writing of Plato shows so profound an insight into the world
and into human nature as the Laws.  That 'cities will never cease from ill
until they are better governed,' is the text of the Laws as well as of the
Statesman and Republic.  The principle that the balance of power preserves
states; the reflection that no one ever passed his whole life in disbelief
of the Gods; the remark that the characters of men are best seen in
convivial intercourse; the observation that the people must be allowed to
share not only in the government, but in the administration of justice; the
desire to make laws, not with a view to courage only, but to all virtue;
the clear perception that education begins with birth, or even, as he would
say, before birth; the attempt to purify religion; the modern reflections,
that punishment is not vindictive, and that limits must be set to the power
of bequest; the impossibility of undeceiving the victims of quacks and
jugglers; the provision for water, and for other requirements of health,
and for concealing the bodies of the dead with as little hurt as possible
to the living; above all, perhaps, the distinct consciousness that under
the actual circumstances of mankind the ideal cannot be carried out, and
yet may be a guiding principle--will appear to us, if we remember that we
are still in the dawn of politics, to show a great depth of political
wisdom.

IV.  The Laws of Plato contain numerous passages which closely resemble
other passages in his writings.  And at first sight a suspicion arises that
the repetition shows the unequal hand of the imitator.  For why should a
writer say over again, in a more imperfect form, what he had already said
in his most finished style and manner?  And yet it may be urged on the
other side that an author whose original powers are beginning to decay will
be very liable to repeat himself, as in conversation, so in books.  He may
have forgotten what he had written before; he may be unconscious of the
decline of his own powers.  Hence arises a question of great interest,
bearing on the genuineness of ancient writers.  Is there any criterion by
which we can distinguish the genuine resemblance from the spurious, or, in
other words, the repetition of a thought or passage by an author himself
from the appropriation of it by another?  The question has, perhaps, never
been fully discussed; and, though a real one, does not admit of a precise
answer.  A few general considerations on the subject may be offered:--

(a) Is the difference such as might be expected to arise at different times
of life or under different circumstances?--There would be nothing
surprising in a writer, as he grew older, losing something of his own
originality, and falling more and more under the spirit of his age.  'What
a genius I had when I wrote that book!' was the pathetic exclamation of a
famous English author, when in old age he chanced to take up one of his
early works.  There would be nothing surprising again in his losing
somewhat of his powers of expression, and becoming less capable of framing
language into a harmonious whole.  There would also be a strong presumption
that if the variation of style was uniform, it was attributable to some
natural cause, and not to the arts of the imitator.  The inferiority might
be the result of feebleness and of want of activity of mind.  But the
natural weakness of a great author would commonly be different from the
artificial weakness of an imitator; it would be continuous and uniform. 
The latter would be apt to fill his work with irregular patches, sometimes
taken verbally from the writings of the author whom he personated, but
rarely acquiring his spirit.  His imitation would be obvious, irregular,
superficial.  The patches of purple would be easily detected among his
threadbare and tattered garments.  He would rarely take the pains to put
the same thought into other words.  There were many forgeries in English
literature which attained a considerable degree of success 50 or 100 years
ago; but it is doubtful whether attempts such as these could now escape
detection, if there were any writings of the same author or of the same age
to be compared with them.  And ancient forgers were much less skilful than
modern; they were far from being masters in the art of deception, and had
rarely any motive for being so.

(b) But, secondly, the imitator will commonly be least capable of
understanding or imitating that part of a great writer which is most
characteristic of him.  In every man's writings there is something like
himself and unlike others, which gives individuality.  To appreciate this
latent quality would require a kindred mind, and minute study and
observation.  There are a class of similarities which may be called
undesigned coincidences, which are so remote as to be incapable of being
borrowed from one another, and yet, when they are compared, find a natural
explanation in their being the work of the same mind.  The imitator might
copy the turns of style--he might repeat images or illustrations, but he
could not enter into the inner circle of Platonic philosophy.  He would
understand that part of it which became popular in the next generation, as
for example, the doctrine of ideas or of numbers:  he might approve of
communism.  But the higher flights of Plato about the science of dialectic,
or the unity of virtue, or a person who is above the law, would be
unintelligible to him.

(c) The argument from imitation assumes a different character when the
supposed imitations are associated with other passages having the impress
of original genius.  The strength of the argument from undesigned
coincidences of style is much increased when they are found side by side
with thoughts and expressions which can only have come from a great
original writer.  The great excellence, not only of the whole, but even of
the parts of writings, is a strong proof of their genuineness--for although
the great writer may fall below, the forger or imitator cannot rise much
above himself.  Whether we can attribute the worst parts of a work to a
forger and the best to a great writer,--as for example, in the case of some
of Shakespeare's plays,--depends upon the probability that they have been
interpolated, or have been the joint work of two writers; and this can only
be established either by express evidence or by a comparison of other
writings of the same class.  If the interpolation or double authorship of
Greek writings in the time of Plato could be shown to be common, then a
question, perhaps insoluble, would arise, not whether the whole, but
whether parts of the Platonic dialogues are genuine, and, if parts only,
which parts.  Hebrew prophecies and Homeric poems and Laws of Manu may have
grown together in early times, but there is no reason to think that any of
the dialogues of Plato is the result of a similar process of accumulation.
It is therefore rash to say with Oncken (Die Staatslehre des Aristoteles)
that the form in which Aristotle knew the Laws of Plato must have been
different from that in which they have come down to us.

It must be admitted that these principles are difficult of application. 
Yet a criticism may be worth making which rests only on probabilities or
impressions.  Great disputes will arise about the merits of different
passages, about what is truly characteristic and original or trivial and
borrowed.  Many have thought the Laws to be one of the greatest of Platonic
writings, while in the judgment of Mr. Grote they hardly rise above the
level of the forged epistles.  The manner in which a writer would or would
not have written at a particular time of life must be acknowledged to be a
matter of conjecture.  But enough has been said to show that similarities
of a certain kind, whether criticism is able to detect them or not, may be
such as must be attributed to an original writer, and not to a mere
imitator.

(d) Applying these principles to the case of the Laws, we have now to point
out that they contain the class of refined or unconscious similarities
which are indicative of genuineness.  The parallelisms are like the
repetitions of favourite thoughts into which every one is apt to fall
unawares in conversation or in writing.  They are found in a work which
contains many beautiful and remarkable passages.  We may therefore begin by
claiming this presumption in their favour.  Such undesigned coincidences,
as we may venture to call them, are the following.  The conception of
justice as the union of temperance, wisdom, courage (Laws; Republic):  the
latent idea of dialectic implied in the notion of dividing laws after the
kinds of virtue (Laws); the approval of the method of looking at one idea
gathered from many things, 'than which a truer was never discovered by any
man' (compare Republic):  or again the description of the Laws as parents
(Laws; Republic):  the assumption that religion has been already settled by
the oracle of Delphi (Laws; Republic), to which an appeal is also made in
special cases (Laws):  the notion of the battle with self, a paradox for
which Plato in a manner apologizes both in the Laws and the Republic:  the
remark (Laws) that just men, even when they are deformed in body, may still
be perfectly beautiful in respect of the excellent justice of their minds
(compare Republic):  the argument that ideals are none the worse because
they cannot be carried out (Laws; Republic):  the near approach to the idea
of good in 'the principle which is common to all the four virtues,' a truth
which the guardians must be compelled to recognize (Laws; compare
Republic):  or again the recognition by reason of the right pleasure and
pain, which had previously been matter of habit (Laws; Republic):  or the
blasphemy of saying that the excellency of music is to give pleasure (Laws;
Republic):  again the story of the Sidonian Cadmus (Laws), which is a
variation of the Phoenician tale of the earth-born men (Republic):  the
comparison of philosophy to a yelping she-dog, both in the Republic and in
the Laws:  the remark that no man can practise two trades (Laws; Republic): 
or the advantage of the middle condition (Laws; Republic):  the tendency to
speak of principles as moulds or forms; compare the ekmageia of song
(Laws), and the tupoi of religion (Republic):  or the remark (Laws) that
'the relaxation of justice makes many cities out of one,' which may be
compared with the Republic:  or the description of lawlessness 'creeping in
little by little in the fashions of music and overturning all things,'--to
us a paradox, but to Plato's mind a fixed idea, which is found in the Laws
as well as in the Republic:  or the figure of the parts of the human body
under which the parts of the state are described (Laws; Republic):  the
apology for delay and diffuseness, which occurs not unfrequently in the
Republic, is carried to an excess in the Laws (compare Theaet.):  the
remarkable thought (Laws) that the soul of the sun is better than the sun,
agrees with the relation in which the idea of good stands to the sun in the
Republic, and with the substitution of mind for the idea of good in the
Philebus:  the passage about the tragic poets (Laws) agrees generally with
the treatment of them in the Republic, but is more finely conceived, and
worked out in a nobler spirit.  Some lesser similarities of thought and
manner should not be omitted, such as the mention of the thirty years' old
students in the Republic, and the fifty years' old choristers in the Laws;
or the making of the citizens out of wax (Laws) compared with the other
image (Republic); or the number of the tyrant (729), which is NEARLY equal
with the number of days and nights in the year (730), compared with the
'slight correction' of the sacred number 5040, which is divisible by all
the numbers from 1 to 12 except 11, and divisible by 11, if two families be
deducted; or once more, we may compare the ignorance of solid geometry of
which he complains in the Republic and the puzzle about fractions with the
difficulty in the Laws about commensurable and incommensurable quantities--
and the malicious emphasis on the word gunaikeios (Laws) with the use of
the same word (Republic).  These and similar passages tend to show that the
author of the Republic is also the author of the Laws.  They are echoes of
the same voice, expressions of the same mind, coincidences too subtle to
have been invented by the ingenuity of any imitator.  The force of the
argument is increased, if we remember that no passage in the Laws is
exactly copied,--nowhere do five or six words occur together which are
found together elsewhere in Plato's writings.

In other dialogues of Plato, as well as in the Republic, there are to be
found parallels with the Laws.  Such resemblances, as we might expect,
occur chiefly (but not exclusively) in the dialogues which, on other
grounds, we may suppose to be of later date.  The punishment of evil is to
be like evil men (Laws), as he says also in the Theaetetus.  Compare again
the dependence of tragedy and comedy on one another, of which he gives the
reason in the Laws--'For serious things cannot be understood without
laughable, nor opposites at all without opposites, if a man is really to
have intelligence of either'; here he puts forward the principle which is
the groundwork of the thesis of Socrates in the Symposium, 'that the genius
of tragedy is the same as that of comedy, and that the writer of comedy
ought to be a writer of tragedy also.'  There is a truth and right which is
above Law (Laws), as we learn also from the Statesman.  That men are the
possession of the Gods (Laws), is a reflection which likewise occurs in the
Phaedo.  The remark, whether serious or ironical (Laws), that 'the sons of
the Gods naturally believed in the Gods, because they had the means of
knowing about them,' is found in the Timaeus.  The reign of Cronos, who is
the divine ruler (Laws), is a reminiscence of the Statesman.  It is
remarkable that in the Sophist and Statesman (Soph.), Plato, speaking in
the character of the Eleatic Stranger, has already put on the old man.  The
madness of the poets, again, is a favourite notion of Plato's, which occurs
also in the Laws, as well as in the Phaedrus, Ion, and elsewhere.  There
are traces in the Laws of the same desire to base speculation upon history
which we find in the Critias.  Once more, there is a striking parallel with
the paradox of the Gorgias, that 'if you do evil, it is better to be
punished than to be unpunished,' in the Laws:  'To live having all goods
without justice and virtue is the greatest of evils if life be immortal,
but not so great if the bad man lives but a short time.'

The point to be considered is whether these are the kind of parallels which
would be the work of an imitator.  Would a forger have had the wit to
select the most peculiar and characteristic thoughts of Plato; would he
have caught the spirit of his philosophy; would he, instead of openly
borrowing, have half concealed his favourite ideas; would he have formed
them into a whole such as the Laws; would he have given another the credit
which he might have obtained for himself; would he have remembered and made
use of other passages of the Platonic writings and have never deviated into
the phraseology of them?  Without pressing such arguments as absolutely
certain, we must acknowledge that such a comparison affords a new ground of
real weight for believing the Laws to be a genuine writing of Plato.

V.  The relation of the Republic to the Laws is clearly set forth by Plato
in the Laws.  The Republic is the best state, the Laws is the best possible
under the existing conditions of the Greek world.  The Republic is the
ideal, in which no man calls anything his own, which may or may not have
existed in some remote clime, under the rule of some God, or son of a God
(who can say?), but is, at any rate, the pattern of all other states and
the exemplar of human life.  The Laws distinctly acknowledge what the
Republic partly admits, that the ideal is inimitable by us, but that we
should 'lift up our eyes to the heavens' and try to regulate our lives
according to the divine image.  The citizens are no longer to have wives
and children in common, and are no longer to be under the government of
philosophers.  But the spirit of communism or communion is to continue
among them, though reverence for the sacredness of the family, and respect
of children for parents, not promiscuous hymeneals, are now the foundation
of the state; the sexes are to be as nearly on an equality as possible;
they are to meet at common tables, and to share warlike pursuits (if the
women will consent), and to have a common education.  The legislator has
taken the place of the philosopher, but a council of elders is retained,
who are to fulfil the duties of the legislator when he has passed out of
life.  The addition of younger persons to this council by co-optation is an
improvement on the governing body of the Republic.  The scheme of education
in the Laws is of a far lower kind than that which Plato had conceived in
the Republic.  There he would have his rulers trained in all knowledge
meeting in the idea of good, of which the different branches of
mathematical science are but the hand-maidens or ministers; here he treats
chiefly of popular education, stopping short with the preliminary
sciences,--these are to be studied partly with a view to their practical
usefulness, which in the Republic he holds cheap, and even more with a view
to avoiding impiety, of which in the Republic he says nothing; he touches
very lightly on dialectic, which is still to be retained for the rulers. 
Yet in the Laws there remain traces of the old educational ideas.  He is
still for banishing the poets; and as he finds the works of prose writers
equally dangerous, he would substitute for them the study of his own laws. 
He insists strongly on the importance of mathematics as an educational
instrument.  He is no more reconciled to the Greek mythology than in the
Republic, though he would rather say nothing about it out of a reverence
for antiquity; and he is equally willing to have recourse to fictions, if
they have a moral tendency.  His thoughts recur to a golden age in which
the sanctity of oaths was respected and in which men living nearer the Gods
were more disposed to believe in them; but we must legislate for the world
as it is, now that the old beliefs have passed away.  Though he is no
longer fired with dialectical enthusiasm, he would compel the guardians to
'look at one idea gathered from many things,' and to 'perceive the
principle which is the same in all the four virtues.'  He still recognizes
the enormous influence of music, in which every youth is to be trained for
three years; and he seems to attribute the existing degeneracy of the
Athenian state and the laxity of morals partly to musical innovation,
manifested in the unnatural divorce of the instrument and the voice, of the
rhythm from the words, and partly to the influence of the mob who ruled at
the theatres.  He assimilates the education of the two sexes, as far as
possible, both in music and gymnastic, and, as in the Republic, he would
give to gymnastic a purely military character.  In marriage, his object is
still to produce the finest children for the state.  As in the Statesman,
he would unite in wedlock dissimilar natures--the passionate with the dull,
the courageous with the gentle.  And the virtuous tyrant of the Statesman,
who has no place in the Republic, again appears.  In this, as in all his
writings, he has the strongest sense of the degeneracy and incapacity of
the rulers of his own time.

In the Laws, the philosophers, if not banished, like the poets, are at
least ignored; and religion takes the place of philosophy in the regulation
of human life.  It must however be remembered that the religion of Plato is
co-extensive with morality, and is that purified religion and mythology of
which he speaks in the second book of the Republic.  There is no real
discrepancy in the two works.  In a practical treatise, he speaks of
religion rather than of philosophy; just as he appears to identify virtue
with pleasure, and rather seeks to find the common element of the virtues
than to maintain his old paradoxical theses that they are one, or that they
are identical with knowledge.  The dialectic and the idea of good, which
even Glaucon in the Republic could not understand, would be out of place in
a less ideal work.  There may also be a change in his own mind, the purely
intellectual aspect of philosophy having a diminishing interest to him in
his old age.

Some confusion occurs in the passage in which Plato speaks of the Republic,
occasioned by his reference to a third state, which he proposes (D.V.) 
hereafter to expound.  Like many other thoughts in the Laws, the allusion
is obscure from not being worked out.  Aristotle (Polit.) speaks of a state
which is neither the best absolutely, nor the best under existing
conditions, but an imaginary state, inferior to either, destitute, as he
supposes, of the necessaries of life--apparently such a beginning of
primitive society as is described in Laws iii.  But it is not clear that by
this the third state of Plato is intended.  It is possible that Plato may
have meant by his third state an historical sketch, bearing the same
relation to the Laws which the unfinished Critias would have borne to the
Republic; or he may, perhaps, have intended to describe a state more nearly
approximating than the Laws to existing Greek states.

The Statesman is a mere fragment when compared with the Laws, yet combining
a second interest of dialectic as well as politics, which is wanting in the
larger work.  Several points of similarity and contrast may be observed
between them.  In some respects the Statesman is even more ideal than the
Republic, looking back to a former state of paradisiacal life, in which the
Gods ruled over mankind, as the Republic looks forward to a coming kingdom
of philosophers.  Of this kingdom of Cronos there is also mention in the
Laws.  Again, in the Statesman, the Eleatic Stranger rises above law to the
conception of the living voice of the lawgiver, who is able to provide for
individual cases.  A similar thought is repeated in the Laws:  'If in the
order of nature, and by divine destiny, a man were able to apprehend the
truth about these things, he would have no need of laws to rule over him;
for there is no law or order above knowledge, nor can mind without impiety
be deemed the subject or slave of any, but rather the lord of all.'  The
union of opposite natures, who form the warp and the woof of the political
web, is a favourite thought which occurs in both dialogues (Laws;
Statesman).

The Laws are confessedly a Second-best, an inferior Ideal, to which Plato
has recourse, when he finds that the city of Philosophers is no longer
'within the horizon of practical politics.'  But it is curious to observe
that the higher Ideal is always returning (compare Arist. Polit.), and that
he is not much nearer the actual fact, nor more on the level of ordinary
life in the Laws than in the Republic.  It is also interesting to remark
that the new Ideal is always falling away, and that he hardly supposes the
one to be more capable of being realized than the other.  Human beings are
troublesome to manage; and the legislator cannot adapt his enactments to
the infinite variety of circumstances; after all he must leave the
administration of them to his successors; and though he would have liked to
make them as permanent as they are in Egypt, he cannot escape from the
necessity of change.  At length Plato is obliged to institute a Nocturnal
Council which is supposed to retain the mind of the legislator, and of
which some of the members are even supposed to go abroad and inspect the
institutions of foreign countries, as a foundation for changes in their
own.  The spirit of such changes, though avoiding the extravagance of a
popular assembly, being only so much change as the conservative temper of
old members is likely to allow, is nevertheless inconsistent with the
fixedness of Egypt which Plato wishes to impress upon Hellenic
institutions.  He is inconsistent with himself as the truth begins to dawn
upon him that 'in the execution things for the most part fall short of our
conception of them' (Republic).

And is not this true of ideals of government in general?  We are always
disappointed in them.  Nothing great can be accomplished in the short space
of human life; wherefore also we look forward to another (Republic).  As we
grow old, we are sensible that we have no power actively to pursue our
ideals any longer.  We have had our opportunity and do not aspire to be
more than men:  we have received our 'wages and are going home.'  Neither
do we despair of the future of mankind, because we have been able to do so
little in comparison of the whole.  We look in vain for consistency either
in men or things.  But we have seen enough of improvement in our own time
to justify us in the belief that the world is worth working for and that a
good man's life is not thrown away.  Such reflections may help us to bring
home to ourselves by inward sympathy the language of Plato in the Laws, and
to combine into something like a whole his various and at first sight
inconsistent utterances.

VI.  The Republic may be described as the Spartan constitution appended to
a government of philosophers.  But in the Laws an Athenian element is also
introduced.  Many enactments are taken from the Athenian; the four classes
are borrowed from the constitution of Cleisthenes, which Plato regards as
the best form of Athenian government, and the guardians of the law bear a
certain resemblance to the archons.  In the constitution of the Laws nearly
all officers are elected by a vote more or less popular and by lot.  But
the assembly only exists for the purposes of election, and has no
legislative or executive powers.  The Nocturnal Council, which is the
highest body in the state, has several of the functions of the ancient
Athenian Areopagus, after which it appears to be modelled.  Life is to
wear, as at Athens, a joyous and festive look; there are to be Bacchic
choruses, and men of mature age are encouraged in moderate potations.  On
the other hand, the common meals, the public education, the crypteia are
borrowed from Sparta and not from Athens, and the superintendence of
private life, which was to be practised by the governors, has also its
prototype in Sparta.  The extravagant dislike which Plato shows both to a
naval power and to extreme democracy is the reverse of Athenian.

The best-governed Hellenic states traced the origin of their laws to
individual lawgivers.  These were real persons, though we are uncertain how
far they originated or only modified the institutions which are ascribed to
them.  But the lawgiver, though not a myth, was a fixed idea in the mind of
the Greek,--as fixed as the Trojan war or the earth-born Cadmus.  'This was
what Solon meant or said'--was the form in which the Athenian expressed his
own conception of right and justice, or argued a disputed point of law. 
And the constant reference in the Laws of Plato to the lawgiver is
altogether in accordance with Greek modes of thinking and speaking.

There is also, as in the Republic, a Pythagorean element.  The highest
branch of education is arithmetic; to know the order of the heavenly
bodies, and to reconcile the apparent contradiction of their movements, is
an important part of religion; the lives of the citizens are to have a
common measure, as also their vessels and coins; the great blessing of the
state is the number 5040.  Plato is deeply impressed by the antiquity of
Egypt, and the unchangeableness of her ancient forms of song and dance. 
And he is also struck by the progress which the Egyptians had made in the
mathematical sciences--in comparison of them the Greeks appeared to him to
be little better than swine.  Yet he censures the Egyptian meanness and
inhospitality to strangers.  He has traced the growth of states from their
rude beginnings in a philosophical spirit; but of any life or growth of the
Hellenic world in future ages he is silent.  He has made the reflection
that past time is the maker of states (Book iii.); but he does not argue
from the past to the future, that the process is always going on, or that
the institutions of nations are relative to their stage of civilization. 
If he could have stamped indelibly upon Hellenic states the will of the
legislator, he would have been satisfied.  The utmost which he expects of
future generations is that they should supply the omissions, or correct the
errors which younger statesmen detect in his enactments.  When institutions
have been once subjected to this process of criticism, he would have them
fixed for ever.

THE PREAMBLE.

BOOK I.  Strangers, let me ask a question of you--Was a God or a man the
author of your laws?  'A God, Stranger.  In Crete, Zeus is said to have
been the author of them; in Sparta, as Megillus will tell you, Apollo.' 
You Cretans believe, as Homer says, that Minos went every ninth year to
converse with his Olympian sire, and gave you laws which he brought from
him.  'Yes; and there was Rhadamanthus, his brother, who is reputed among
us to have been a most righteous judge.'  That is a reputation worthy of
the son of Zeus.  And as you and Megillus have been trained under these
laws, I may ask you to give me an account of them.  We can talk about them
in our walk from Cnosus to the cave and temple of Zeus.  I am told that the
distance is considerable, but probably there are shady places under the
trees, where, being no longer young, we may often rest and converse.  'Yes,
Stranger, a little onward there are beautiful groves of cypresses, and
green meadows in which we may repose.'

My first question is, Why has the law ordained that you should have common
meals, and practise gymnastics, and bear arms?  'My answer is, that all our
institutions are of a military character.  We lead the life of the camp
even in time of peace, keeping up the organization of an army, and having
meals in common; and as our country, owing to its ruggedness, is ill-suited
for heavy-armed cavalry or infantry, our soldiers are archers, equipped
with bows and arrows.  The legislator was under the idea that war was the
natural state of all mankind, and that peace is only a pretence; he thought
that no possessions had any value which were not secured against enemies.' 
And do you think that superiority in war is the proper aim of government? 
'Certainly I do, and my Spartan friend will agree with me.'  And are there
wars, not only of state against state, but of village against village, of
family against family, of individual against individual?  'Yes.'  And is a
man his own enemy?  'There you come to first principles, like a true votary
of the goddess Athene; and this is all the better, for you will the sooner
recognize the truth of what I am saying--that all men everywhere are the
enemies of all, and each individual of every other and of himself; and,
further, that there is a victory and defeat--the best and the worst--which
each man sustains, not at the hands of another, but of himself.'  And does
this extend to states and villages as well as to individuals?  'Certainly;
there is a better in them which conquers or is conquered by the worse.' 
Whether the worse ever really conquers the better, is a question which may
be left for the present; but your meaning is, that bad citizens do
sometimes overcome the good, and that the state is then conquered by
herself, and that when they are defeated the state is victorious over
herself.  Or, again, in a family there may be several brothers, and the bad
may be a majority; and when the bad majority conquer the good minority, the
family are worse than themselves.  The use of the terms 'better or worse
than himself or themselves' may be doubtful, but about the thing meant
there can be no dispute.  'Very true.'  Such a struggle might be determined
by a judge.  And which will be the better judge--he who destroys the worse
and lets the better rule, or he who lets the better rule and makes the
others voluntarily obey; or, thirdly, he who destroys no one, but
reconciles the two parties?  'The last, clearly.'  But the object of such a
judge or legislator would not be war.  'True.'  And as there are two kinds
of war, one without and one within a state, of which the internal is by far
the worse, will not the legislator chiefly direct his attention to this
latter?  He will reconcile the contending factions, and unite them against
their external enemies.  'Certainly.'  Every legislator will aim at the
greatest good, and the greatest good is not victory in war, whether civil
or external, but mutual peace and good-will, as in the body health is
preferable to the purgation of disease.  He who makes war his object
instead of peace, or who pursues war except for the sake of peace, is not a
true statesman.  'And yet, Stranger, the laws both of Crete and Sparta aim
entirely at war.'  Perhaps so; but do not let us quarrel about your
legislators--let us be gentle; they were in earnest quite as much as we
are, and we must try to discover their meaning.  The poet Tyrtaeus (you
know his poems in Crete, and my Lacedaemonian friend is only too familiar
with them)--he was an Athenian by birth, and a Spartan citizen:--'Well,' he
says, 'I sing not, I care not about any man, however rich or happy, unless
he is brave in war.'  Now I should like, in the name of us all, to ask the
poet a question.  Oh Tyrtaeus, I would say to him, we agree with you in
praising those who excel in war, but which kind of war do you mean?--that
dreadful war which is termed civil, or the milder sort which is waged
against foreign enemies?  You say that you abominate 'those who are not
eager to taste their enemies' blood,' and you seem to mean chiefly their
foreign enemies.  'Certainly he does.'  But we contend that there are men
better far than your heroes, Tyrtaeus, concerning whom another poet,
Theognis the Sicilian, says that 'in a civil broil they are worth their
weight in gold and silver.'  For in a civil war, not only courage, but
justice and temperance and wisdom are required, and all virtue is better
than a part.  The mercenary soldier is ready to die at his post; yet he is
commonly a violent, senseless creature.  And the legislator, whether
inspired or uninspired, will make laws with a view to the highest virtue;
and this is not brute courage, but loyalty in the hour of danger.  The
virtue of Tyrtaeus, although needful enough in his own time, is really of a
fourth-rate description.  'You are degrading our legislator to a very low
level.'  Nay, we degrade not him, but ourselves, if we believe that the
laws of Lycurgus and Minos had a view to war only.  A divine lawgiver would
have had regard to all the different kinds of virtue, and have arranged his
laws in corresponding classes, and not in the modern fashion, which only
makes them after the want of them is felt,--about inheritances and
heiresses and assaults, and the like.  As you truly said, virtue is the
business of the legislator; but you went wrong when you referred all
legislation to a part of virtue, and to an inferior part.  For the object
of laws, whether the Cretan or any other, is to make men happy.  Now
happiness or good is of two kinds--there are divine and there are human
goods.  He who has the divine has the human added to him; but he who has
lost the greater is deprived of both.  The lesser goods are health, beauty,
strength, and, lastly, wealth; not the blind God, Pluto, but one who has
eyes to see and follow wisdom.  For mind or wisdom is the most divine of
all goods; and next comes temperance, and justice springs from the union of
wisdom and temperance with courage, which is the fourth or last.  These
four precede other goods, and the legislator will arrange all his
ordinances accordingly, the human going back to the divine, and the divine
to their leader mind.  There will be enactments about marriage, about
education, about all the states and feelings and experiences of men and
women, at every age, in weal and woe, in war and peace; upon all the law
will fix a stamp of praise and blame.  There will also be regulations about
property and expenditure, about contracts, about rewards and punishments,
and finally about funeral rites and honours of the dead.  The lawgiver will
appoint guardians to preside over these things; and mind will harmonize his
ordinances, and show them to be in agreement with temperance and justice. 
Now I want to know whether the same principles are observed in the laws of
Lycurgus and Minos, or, as I should rather say, of Apollo and Zeus.  We
must go through the virtues, beginning with courage, and then we will show
that what has preceded has relation to virtue.

'I wish,' says the Lacedaemonian, 'that you, Stranger, would first
criticize Cleinias and the Cretan laws.'  Yes, is the reply, and I will
criticize you and myself, as well as him.  Tell me, Megillus, were not the
common meals and gymnastic training instituted by your legislator with a
view to war?  'Yes; and next in the order of importance comes hunting, and
fourth the endurance of pain in boxing contests, and in the beatings which
are the punishment of theft.  There is, too, the so-called Crypteia or
secret service, in which our youth wander about the country night and day
unattended, and even in winter go unshod and have no beds to lie on. 
Moreover they wrestle and exercise under a blazing sun, and they have many
similar customs.'  Well, but is courage only a combat against fear and
pain, and not against pleasure and flattery?  'Against both, I should say.' 
And which is worse,--to be overcome by pain, or by pleasure?  'The latter.' 
But did the lawgivers of Crete and Sparta legislate for a courage which is
lame of one leg,--able to meet the attacks of pain but not those of
pleasure, or for one which can meet both?  'For a courage which can meet
both, I should say.'  But if so, where are the institutions which train
your citizens to be equally brave against pleasure and pain, and superior
to enemies within as well as without?  'We confess that we have no
institutions worth mentioning which are of this character.'  I am not
surprised, and will therefore only request forbearance on the part of us
all, in case the love of truth should lead any of us to censure the laws of
the others.  Remember that I am more in the way of hearing criticisms of
your laws than you can be; for in well-ordered states like Crete and
Sparta, although an old man may sometimes speak of them in private to a
ruler or elder, a similar liberty is not allowed to the young.  But now
being alone we shall not offend your legislator by a friendly examination
of his laws. 'Take any freedom which you like.'

My first observation is, that your lawgiver ordered you to endure
hardships, because he thought that those who had not this discipline would
run away from those who had.  But he ought to have considered further, that
those who had never learned to resist pleasure would be equally at the
mercy of those who had, and these are often among the worst of mankind. 
Pleasure, like fear, would overcome them and take away their courage and
freedom.  'Perhaps; but I must not be hasty in giving my assent.'

Next as to temperance:  what institutions have you which are adapted to
promote temperance?  'There are the common meals and gymnastic exercises.' 
These are partly good and partly bad, and, as in medicine, what is good at
one time and for one person, is bad at another time and for another person.
Now although gymnastics and common meals do good, they are also a cause of
evil in civil troubles, and they appear to encourage unnatural love, as has
been shown at Miletus, in Boeotia, and at Thurii.  And the Cretans are said
to have invented the tale of Zeus and Ganymede in order to justify their
evil practices by the example of the God who was their lawgiver.  Leaving
the story, we may observe that all law has to do with pleasure and pain;
these are two fountains which are ever flowing in human nature, and he who
drinks of them when and as much as he ought, is happy, and he who indulges
in them to excess, is miserable.  'You may be right, but I still incline to
think that the Lacedaemonian lawgiver did well in forbidding pleasure, if I
may judge from the result.  For there is no drunken revelry in Sparta, and
any one found in a state of intoxication is severely punished; he is not
excused as an Athenian would be at Athens on account of a festival.  I
myself have seen the Athenians drunk at the Dionysia--and at our colony,
Tarentum, on a similar occasion, I have beheld the whole city in a state of
intoxication.'  I admit that these festivals should be properly regulated. 
Yet I might reply, 'Yes, Spartans, that is not your vice; but look at home
and remember the licentiousness of your women.'  And to all such
accusations every one of us may reply in turn:--'Wonder not, Stranger;
there are different customs in different countries.'  Now this may be a
sufficient answer; but we are speaking about the wisdom of lawgivers and
not about the customs of men.  To return to the question of drinking: 
shall we have total abstinence, as you have, or hard drinking, like the
Scythians and Thracians, or moderate potations like the Persians?  'Give us
arms, and we send all these nations flying before us.'  My good friend, be
modest; victories and defeats often arise from unknown causes, and afford
no proof of the goodness or badness of institutions.  The stronger
overcomes the weaker, as the Athenians have overcome the Ceans, or the
Syracusans the Locrians, who are, perhaps, the best governed state in that
part of the world.  People are apt to praise or censure practices without
enquiring into the nature of them.  This is the way with drink:  one person
brings many witnesses, who sing the praises of wine; another declares that
sober men defeat drunkards in battle; and he again is refuted in turn.  I
should like to conduct the argument on some other method; for if you regard
numbers, there are two cities on one side, and ten thousand on the other. 
'I am ready to pursue any method which is likely to lead us to the truth.' 
Let me put the matter thus:  Somebody praises the useful qualities of a
goat; another has seen goats running about wild in a garden, and blames a
goat or any other animal which happens to be without a keeper.  'How
absurd!'  Would a pilot who is sea-sick be a good pilot?  'No.'  Or a
general who is sick and drunk with fear and ignorant of war a good general? 
'A general of old women he ought to be.'  But can any one form an estimate
of any society, which is intended to have a ruler, and which he only sees
in an unruly and lawless state?  'No.'  There is a convivial form of
society--is there not?  'Yes.'  And has this convivial society ever been
rightly ordered?  Of course you Spartans and Cretans have never seen
anything of the kind, but I have had wide experience, and made many
enquiries about such societies, and have hardly ever found anything right
or good in them.  'We acknowledge our want of experience, and desire to
learn of you.'  Will you admit that in all societies there must be a
leader?  'Yes.'  And in time of war he must be a man of courage and
absolutely devoid of fear, if this be possible?  'Certainly.'  But we are
talking now of a general who shall preside at meetings of friends--and as
these have a tendency to be uproarious, they ought above all others to have
a governor.  'Very good.'  He should be a sober man and a man of the world,
who will keep, make, and increase the peace of the society; a drunkard in
charge of drunkards would be singularly fortunate if he avoided doing a
serious mischief.  'Indeed he would.'  Suppose a person to censure such
meetings--he may be right, but also he may have known them only in their
disorderly state, under a drunken master of the feast; and a drunken
general or pilot cannot save his army or his ships.  'True; but although I
see the advantage of an army having a good general, I do not equally see
the good of a feast being well managed.'  If you mean to ask what good
accrues to the state from the right training of a single youth or a single
chorus, I should reply, 'Not much'; but if you ask what is the good of
education in general, I answer, that education makes good men, and that
good men act nobly and overcome their enemies in battle.  Victory is often
suicidal to the victors, because it creates forgetfulness of education, but
education itself is never suicidal.  'You imply that the regulation of
convivial meetings is a part of education; how will you prove this?'  I
will tell you.  But first let me offer a word of apology.  We Athenians are
always thought to be fond of talking, whereas the Lacedaemonian is
celebrated for brevity, and the Cretan is considered to be sagacious and
reserved.  Now I fear that I may be charged with spinning a long discourse
out of slender materials.  For drinking cannot be rightly ordered without
correct principles of music, and music runs up into education generally,
and to discuss all these matters may be tedious; if you like, therefore, we
will pass on to another part of our subject.  'Are you aware, Athenian,
that our family is your proxenus at Sparta, and that from my boyhood I have
regarded Athens as a second country, and having often fought your battles
in my youth, I have become attached to you, and love the sound of the Attic
dialect?  The saying is true, that the best Athenians are more than
ordinarily good, because they are good by nature; therefore, be assured
that I shall be glad to hear you talk as much as you please.'  'I, too,'
adds Cleinias, 'have a tie which binds me to you.  You know that
Epimenides, the Cretan prophet, came and offered sacrifices in your city by
the command of an oracle ten years before the Persian war.  He told the
Athenians that the Persian host would not come for ten years, and would go
away again, having suffered more harm than they had inflicted.  Now
Epimenides was of my family, and when he visited Athens he entered into
friendship with your forefathers.'  I see that you are willing to listen,
and I have the will to speak, if I had only the ability.  But, first, I
must define the nature and power of education, and by this road we will
travel on to the God Dionysus.  The man who is to be good at anything must
have early training;--the future builder must play at building, and the
husbandman at digging; the soldier must learn to ride, and the carpenter to
measure and use the rule,--all the thoughts and pleasures of children
should bear on their after-profession.--Do you agree with me?  'Certainly.' 
And we must remember further that we are speaking of the education, not of
a trainer, or of the captain of a ship, but of a perfect citizen who knows
how to rule and how to obey; and such an education aims at virtue, and not
at wealth or strength or mere cleverness.  To the good man, education is of
all things the most precious, and is also in constant need of renovation. 
'We agree.'  And we have before agreed that good men are those who are able
to control themselves, and bad men are those who are not.  Let me offer you
an illustration which will assist our argument.  Man is one; but in one and
the same man are two foolish counsellors who contend within him--pleasure
and pain, and of either he has expectations which we call hope and fear;
and he is able to reason about good and evil, and reason, when affirmed by
the state, becomes law.  'We cannot follow you.'  Let me put the matter in
another way:  Every creature is a puppet of the Gods--whether he is a mere
plaything or has any serious use we do not know; but this we do know, that
he is drawn different ways by cords and strings.  There is a soft golden
cord which draws him towards virtue--this is the law of the state; and
there are other cords made of iron and hard materials drawing him other
ways.  The golden reasoning influence has nothing of the nature of force,
and therefore requires ministers in order to vanquish the other principles. 
This explains the doctrine that cities and citizens both conquer and are
conquered by themselves.  The individual follows reason, and the city law,
which is embodied reason, either derived from the Gods or from the
legislator.  When virtue and vice are thus distinguished, education will be
better understood, and in particular the relation of education to convivial
intercourse.  And now let us set wine before the puppet.  You admit that
wine stimulates the passions?  'Yes.'  And does wine equally stimulate the
reasoning faculties?  'No; it brings the soul back to a state of
childhood.'  In such a state a man has the least control over himself, and
is, therefore, worst.  'Very true.'  Then how can we believe that drinking
should be encouraged?  'You seem to think that it ought to be.'  And I am
ready to maintain my position.  'We should like to hear you prove that a
man ought to make a beast of himself.'  You are speaking of the degradation
of the soul:  but how about the body?  Would any man willingly degrade or
weaken that?  'Certainly not.'  And yet if he goes to a doctor or a
gymnastic master, does he not make himself ill in the hope of getting well?
for no one would like to be always taking medicine, or always to be in
training.  'True.'  And may not convivial meetings have a similar remedial
use?  And if so, are they not to be preferred to other modes of training
because they are painless?  'But have they any such use?'  Let us see:  Are
there not two kinds of fear--fear of evil and fear of an evil reputation? 
'There are.'  The latter kind of fear is opposed both to the fear of pain
and to the love of pleasure.  This is called by the legislator reverence,
and is greatly honoured by him and by every good man; whereas confidence,
which is the opposite quality, is the worst fault both of individuals and
of states.  This sort of fear or reverence is one of the two chief causes
of victory in war, fearlessness of enemies being the other.  'True.'  Then
every one should be both fearful and fearless?  'Yes.'  The right sort of
fear is infused into a man when he comes face to face with shame, or
cowardice, or the temptations of pleasure, and has to conquer them.  He
must learn by many trials to win the victory over himself, if he is ever to
be made perfect.  'That is reasonable enough.'  And now, suppose that the
Gods had given mankind a drug, of which the effect was to exaggerate every
sort of evil and danger, so that the bravest man entirely lost his presence
of mind and became a coward for a time:--would such a drug have any value? 
'But is there such a drug?'  No; but suppose that there were; might not the
legislator use such a mode of testing courage and cowardice?  'To be sure.' 
The legislator would induce fear in order to implant fearlessness; and
would give rewards or punishments to those who behaved well or the reverse,
under the influence of the drug?  'Certainly.'  And this mode of training,
whether practised in the case of one or many, whether in solitude or in the
presence of a large company--if a man have sufficient confidence in himself
to drink the potion amid his boon companions, leaving off in time and not
taking too much,--would be an equally good test of temperance?  'Very
true.'  Let us return to the lawgiver and say to him, 'Well, lawgiver, no
such fear-producing potion has been given by God or invented by man, but
there is a potion which will make men fearless.'  'You mean wine.'  Yes;
has not wine an effect the contrary of that which I was just now
describing,--first mellowing and humanizing a man, and then filling him
with confidence, making him ready to say or do anything?  'Certainly.'  Let
us not forget that there are two qualities which should be cultivated in
the soul--first, the greatest fearlessness, and, secondly, the greatest
fear, which are both parts of reverence.  Courage and fearlessness are
trained amid dangers; but we have still to consider how fear is to be
trained.  We desire to attain fearlessness and confidence without the
insolence and boldness which commonly attend them.  For do not love,
ignorance, avarice, wealth, beauty, strength, while they stimulate courage,
also madden and intoxicate the soul?  What better and more innocent test of
character is there than festive intercourse?  Would you make a bargain with
a man in order to try whether he is honest?  Or would you ascertain whether
he is licentious by putting your wife or daughter into his hands?  No one
would deny that the test proposed is fairer, speedier, and safer than any
other.  And such a test will be particularly useful in the political
science, which desires to know human natures and characters.  'Very true.'

BOOK II.  And are there any other uses of well-ordered potations?  There
are; but in order to explain them, I must repeat what I mean by right
education; which, if I am not mistaken, depends on the due regulation of
convivial intercourse.  'A high assumption.'  I believe that virtue and
vice are originally present to the mind of children in the form of pleasure
and pain; reason and fixed principles come later, and happy is he who
acquires them even in declining years; for he who possesses them is the
perfect man.  When pleasure and pain, and love and hate, are rightly
implanted in the yet unconscious soul, and after the attainment of reason
are discovered to be in harmony with her, this harmony of the soul is
virtue, and the preparatory stage, anticipating reason, I call education. 
But the finer sense of pleasure and pain is apt to be impaired in the
course of life; and therefore the Gods, pitying the toils and sorrows of
mortals, have allowed them to have holidays, and given them the Muses and
Apollo and Dionysus for leaders and playfellows.  All young creatures love
motion and frolic, and utter sounds of delight; but man only is capable of
taking pleasure in rhythmical and harmonious movements.  With these
education begins; and the uneducated is he who has never known the
discipline of the chorus, and the educated is he who has.  The chorus is
partly dance and partly song, and therefore the well-educated must sing and
dance well.  But when we say, 'He sings and dances well,' we mean that he
sings and dances what is good.  And if he thinks that to be good which is
really good, he will have a much higher music and harmony in him, and be a
far greater master of imitation in sound and gesture than he who is not of
this opinion.  'True.'  Then, if we know what is good and bad in song and
dance, we shall know what education is?  'Very true.'  Let us now consider
the beauty of figure, melody, song, and dance.  Will the same figures or
sounds be equally well adapted to the manly and the cowardly when they are
in trouble?  'How can they be, when the very colours of their faces are
different?'  Figures and melodies have a rhythm and harmony which are
adapted to the expression of different feelings (I may remark, by the way,
that the term 'colour,' which is a favourite word of music-masters, is not
really applicable to music).  And one class of harmonies is akin to courage
and all virtue, the other to cowardice and all vice.  'We agree.'  And do
all men equally like all dances?  'Far otherwise.'  Do some figures, then,
appear to be beautiful which are not?  For no one will admit that the forms
of vice are more beautiful than the forms of virtue, or that he prefers the
first kind to the second.  And yet most persons say that the merit of music
is to give pleasure.  But this is impiety.  There is, however, a more
plausible account of the matter given by others, who make their likes or
dislikes the criterion of excellence.  Sometimes nature crosses habit, or
conversely, and then they say that such and such fashions or gestures are
pleasant, but they do not like to exhibit them before men of sense,
although they enjoy them in private.  'Very true.'  And do vicious measures
and strains do any harm, or good measures any good to the lovers of them? 
'Probably.'  Say, rather 'Certainly':  for the gentle indulgence which we
often show to vicious men inevitably makes us become like them.  And what
can be worse than this?  'Nothing.'  Then in a well-administered city, the
poet will not be allowed to make the songs of the people just as he
pleases, or to train his choruses without regard to virtue and vice. 
'Certainly not.'  And yet he may do this anywhere except in Egypt; for
there ages ago they discovered the great truth which I am now asserting,
that the young should be educated in forms and strains of virtue.  These
they fixed and consecrated in their temples; and no artist or musician is
allowed to deviate from them.  They are literally the same which they were
ten thousand years ago.  And this practice of theirs suggests the
reflection that legislation about music is not an impossible thing.  But
the particular enactments must be the work of God or of some God-inspired
man, as in Egypt their ancient chants are said to be the composition of the
goddess Isis.  The melodies which have a natural truth and correctness
should be embodied in a law, and then the desire of novelty is not strong
enough to change the old fashions.  Is not the origin of music as follows? 
We rejoice when we think that we prosper, and we think that we prosper when
we rejoice, and at such times we cannot rest, but our young men dance
dances and sing songs, and our old men, who have lost the elasticity of
youth, regale themselves with the memory of the past, while they
contemplate the life and activity of the young.  'Most true.'  People say
that he who gives us most pleasure at such festivals is to win the palm: 
are they right?  'Possibly.'  Let us not be hasty in deciding, but first
imagine a festival at which the lord of the festival, having assembled the
citizens, makes a proclamation that he shall be crowned victor who gives
the most pleasure, from whatever source derived.  We will further suppose
that there are exhibitions of rhapsodists and musicians, tragic and comic
poets, and even marionette-players--which of the pleasure-makers will win? 
Shall I answer for you?--the marionette-players will please the children;
youths will decide for comedy; young men, educated women, and people in
general will prefer tragedy; we old men are lovers of Homer and Hesiod. 
Now which of them is right?  If you and I are asked, we shall certainly say
that the old men's way of thinking ought to prevail.  'Very true.'  So far
I agree with the many that the excellence of music is to be measured by
pleasure; but then the pleasure must be that of the good and educated, or
better still, of one supremely virtuous and educated man.  The true judge
must have both wisdom and courage.  For he must lead the multitude and not
be led by them, and must not weakly yield to the uproar of the theatre, nor
give false judgment out of that mouth which has just appealed to the Gods. 
The ancient custom of Hellas, which still prevails in Italy and Sicily,
left the judgment to the spectators, but this custom has been the ruin of
the poets, who seek only to please their patrons, and has degraded the
audience by the representation of inferior characters.  What is the
inference?  The same which we have often drawn, that education is the
training of the young idea in what the law affirms and the elders approve. 
And as the soul of a child is too young to be trained in earnest, a kind of
education has been invented which tempts him with plays and songs, as the
sick are tempted by pleasant meats and drinks.  And the wise legislator
will compel the poet to express in his poems noble thoughts in fitting
words and rhythms.  'But is this the practice elsewhere than in Crete and
Lacedaemon?  In other states, as far as I know, dances and music are
constantly changed at the pleasure of the hearers.'  I am afraid that I
misled you; not liking to be always finding fault with mankind as they are,
I described them as they ought to be.  But let me understand:  you say that
such customs exist among the Cretans and Lacedaemonians, and that the rest
of the world would be improved by adopting them?  'Much improved.'  And you
compel your poets to declare that the righteous are happy, and that the
wicked man, even if he be as rich as Midas, is unhappy?  Or, in the words
of Tyrtaeus, 'I sing not, I care not about him' who is a great warrior not
having justice; if he be unjust, 'I would not have him look calmly upon
death or be swifter than the wind'; and may he be deprived of every good--
that is, of every true good.  For even if he have the goods which men
regard, these are not really goods:  first health; beauty next; thirdly
wealth; and there are others.  A man may have every sense purged and
improved; he may be a tyrant, and do what he likes, and live for ever:  but
you and I will maintain that all these things are goods to the just, but to
the unjust the greatest of evils, if life be immortal; not so great if he
live for a short time only.  If a man had health and wealth, and power, and
was insolent and unjust, his life would still be miserable; he might be
fair and rich, and do what he liked, but he would live basely, and if
basely evilly, and if evilly painfully.  'There I cannot agree with you.' 
Then may heaven give us the spirit of agreement, for I am as convinced of
the truth of what I say as that Crete is an island; and, if I were a
lawgiver, I would exercise a censorship over the poets, and I would punish
them if they said that the wicked are happy, or that injustice is
profitable.  And these are not the only matters in which I should make my
citizens talk in a different way to the world in general.  If I asked Zeus
and Apollo, the divine legislators of Crete and Sparta,--'Are the just and
pleasant life the same or not the same'?--and they replied,--'Not the
same'; and I asked again--'Which is the happier'?  And they said'--'The
pleasant life,' this is an answer not fit for a God to utter, and therefore
I ought rather to put the same question to some legislator.  And if he
replies 'The pleasant,' then I should say to him, 'O my father, did you not
tell me that I should live as justly as possible'? and if to be just is to
be happy, what is that principle of happiness or good which is superior to
pleasure?  Is the approval of gods and men to be deemed good and
honourable, but unpleasant, and their disapproval the reverse?  Or is the
neither doing nor suffering evil good and honourable, although not
pleasant?  But you cannot make men like what is not pleasant, and therefore
you must make them believe that the just is pleasant.  The business of the
legislator is to clear up this confusion.  He will show that the just and
the unjust are identical with the pleasurable and the painful, from the
point of view of the just man, of the unjust the reverse.  And which is the
truer judgment?  Surely that of the better soul.  For if not the truth, it
is the best and most moral of fictions; and the legislator who desires to
propagate this useful lie, may be encouraged by remarking that mankind have
believed the story of Cadmus and the dragon's teeth, and therefore he may
be assured that he can make them believe anything, and need only consider
what fiction will do the greatest good.  That the happiest is also the
holiest, this shall be our strain, which shall be sung by all three
choruses alike.  First will enter the choir of children, who will lift up
their voices on high; and after them the young men, who will pray the God
Paean to be gracious to the youth, and to testify to the truth of their
words; then will come the chorus of elder men, between thirty and sixty;
and, lastly, there will be the old men, and they will tell stories
enforcing the same virtues, as with the voice of an oracle.  'Whom do you
mean by the third chorus?'  You remember how I spoke at first of the
restless nature of young creatures, who jumped about and called out in a
disorderly manner, and I said that no other animal attained any perception
of rhythm; but that to us the Gods gave Apollo and the Muses and Dionysus
to be our playfellows.  Of the two first choruses I have already spoken,
and I have now to speak of the third, or Dionysian chorus, which is
composed of those who are between thirty and sixty years old.  'Let us
hear.'  We are agreed (are we not?) that men, women, and children should be
always charming themselves with strains of virtue, and that there should be
a variety in the strains, that they may not weary of them?  Now the fairest
and most useful of strains will be uttered by the elder men, and therefore
we cannot let them off.  But how can we make them sing?  For a discreet
elderly man is ashamed to hear the sound of his own voice in private, and
still more in public.  The only way is to give them drink; this will mellow
the sourness of age.  No one should be allowed to taste wine until they are
eighteen; from eighteen to thirty they may take a little; but when they
have reached forty years, they may be initiated into the mystery of
drinking.  Thus they will become softer and more impressible; and when a
man's heart is warm within him, he will be more ready to charm himself and
others with song.  And what songs shall he sing?  'At Crete and Lacedaemon
we only know choral songs.'  Yes; that is because your way of life is
military.  Your young men are like wild colts feeding in a herd together;
no one takes the individual colt and trains him apart, and tries to give
him the qualities of a statesman as well as of a soldier.  He who was thus
trained would be a greater warrior than those of whom Tyrtaeus speaks, for
he would be courageous, and yet he would know that courage was only fourth
in the scale of virtue.  'Once more, I must say, Stranger, that you run
down our lawgivers.'  Not intentionally, my good friend, but whither the
argument leads I follow; and I am trying to find some style of poetry
suitable for those who dislike the common sort.  'Very good.'  In all
things which have a charm, either this charm is their good, or they have
some accompanying truth or advantage.  For example, in eating and drinking
there is pleasure and also profit, that is to say, health; and in learning
there is a pleasure and also truth.  There is a pleasure or charm, too, in
the imitative arts, as well as a law of proportion or equality; but the
pleasure which they afford, however innocent, is not the criterion of their
truth.  The test of pleasure cannot be applied except to that which has no
other good or evil, no truth or falsehood.  But that which has truth must
be judged of by the standard of truth, and therefore imitation and
proportion are to be judged of by their truth alone.  'Certainly.'  And as
music is imitative, it is not to be judged by the criterion of pleasure,
and the Muse whom we seek is the muse not of pleasure but of truth, for
imitation has a truth.  'Doubtless.'  And if so, the judge must know what
is being imitated before he decides on the quality of the imitation, and he
who does not know what is true will not know what is good.  'He will not.' 
Will any one be able to imitate the human body, if he does not know the
number, proportion, colour, or figure of the limbs?  'How can he?'  But
suppose we know some picture or figure to be an exact resemblance of a man,
should we not also require to know whether the picture is beautiful or not? 
'Quite right.'  The judge of the imitation is required to know, therefore,
first the original, secondly the truth, and thirdly the merit of the
execution?  'True.'  Then let us not weary in the attempt to bring music to
the standard of the Muses and of truth.  The Muses are not like human
poets; they never spoil or mix rhythms or scales, or mingle instruments and
human voices, or confuse the manners and strains of men and women, or of
freemen and slaves, or of rational beings and brute animals.  They do not
practise the baser sorts of musical arts, such as the 'matured judgments,'
of whom Orpheus speaks, would ridicule.  But modern poets separate metre
from music, and melody and rhythm from words, and use the instrument alone
without the voice.  The consequence is, that the meaning of the rhythm and
of the time are not understood.  I am endeavouring to show how our fifty-
year-old choristers are to be trained, and what they are to avoid.  The
opinion of the multitude about these matters is worthless; they who are
only made to step in time by sheer force cannot be critics of music. 
'Impossible.'  Then our newly-appointed minstrels must be trained in music
sufficiently to understand the nature of rhythms and systems; and they
should select such as are suitable to men of their age, and will enable
them to give and receive innocent pleasure.  This is a knowledge which goes
beyond that either of the poets or of their auditors in general.  For
although the poet must understand rhythm and music, he need not necessarily
know whether the imitation is good or not, which was the third point
required in a judge; but our chorus of elders must know all three, if they
are to be the instructors of youth.

And now we will resume the original argument, which may be summed up as
follows:  A convivial meeting is apt to grow tumultuous as the drinking
proceeds; every man becomes light-headed, and fancies that he can rule the
whole world.  'Doubtless.'  And did we not say that the souls of the
drinkers, when subdued by wine, are made softer and more malleable at the
hand of the legislator? the docility of childhood returns to them.  At
times however they become too valiant and disorderly, drinking out of their
turn, and interrupting one another.  And the business of the legislator is
to infuse into them that divine fear, which we call shame, in opposition to
this disorderly boldness.  But in order to discipline them there must be
guardians of the law of drinking, and sober generals who shall take charge
of the private soldiers; they are as necessary in drinking as in fighting,
and he who disobeys these Dionysiac commanders will be equally disgraced. 
'Very good.'  If a drinking festival were well regulated, men would go
away, not as they now do, greater enemies, but better friends.  Of the
greatest gift of Dionysus I hardly like to speak, lest I should be
misunderstood.  'What is that?'  According to tradition Dionysus was driven
mad by his stepmother Here, and in order to revenge himself he inspired
mankind with Bacchic madness.  But these are stories which I would rather
not repeat.  However I do acknowledge that all men are born in an imperfect
state, and are at first restless, irrational creatures:  this, as you will
remember, has been already said by us.  'I remember.'  And that Apollo and
the Muses and Dionysus gave us harmony and rhythm?  'Very true.'  The other
story implies that wine was given to punish us and make us mad; but we
contend that wine is a balm and a cure; a spring of modesty in the soul,
and of health and strength in the body.  Again, the work of the chorus is
co-extensive with the work of education; rhythm and melody answer to the
voice, and the motions of the body correspond to all three, and the sound
enters in and educates the soul in virtue.  'Yes.'  And the movement which,
when pursued as an amusement, is termed dancing, when studied with a view
to the improvement of the body, becomes gymnastic.  Shall we now proceed to
speak of this?  'What Cretan or Lacedaemonian would approve of your
omitting gymnastic?'  Your question implies assent; and you will easily
understand a subject which is familiar to you.  Gymnastic is based on the
natural tendency of every animal to rapid motion; and man adds a sense of
rhythm, which is awakened by music; music and dancing together form the
choral art.  But before proceeding I must add a crowning word about
drinking.  Like other pleasures, it has a lawful use; but if a state or an
individual is inclined to drink at will, I cannot allow them.  I would go
further than Crete or Lacedaemon and have the law of the Carthaginians,
that no slave of either sex should drink wine at all, and no soldier while
he is on a campaign, and no magistrate or officer while he is on duty, and
that no one should drink by daylight or on a bridal night.  And there are
so many other occasions on which wine ought to be prohibited, that there
will not be many vines grown or vineyards required in the state.

BOOK III.  If a man wants to know the origin of states and societies, he
should behold them from the point of view of time.  Thousands of cities
have come into being and have passed away again in infinite ages, every one
of them having had endless forms of government; and if we can ascertain the
cause of these changes in states, that will probably explain their origin.
What do you think of ancient traditions about deluges and destructions of
mankind, and the preservation of a remnant?  'Every one believes in them.' 
Then let us suppose the world to have been destroyed by a deluge.  The
survivors would be hill-shepherds, small sparks of the human race, dwelling
in isolation, and unacquainted with the arts and vices of civilization.  We
may further suppose that the cities on the plain and on the coast have been
swept away, and that all inventions, and every sort of knowledge, have
perished.  'Why, if all things were as they now are, nothing would have
ever been invented.  All our famous discoveries have been made within the
last thousand years, and many of them are but of yesterday.'  Yes,
Cleinias, and you must not forget Epimenides, who was really of yesterday;
he practised the lesson of moderation and abstinence which Hesiod only
preached.  'True.'  After the great destruction we may imagine that the
earth was a desert, in which there were a herd or two of oxen and a few
goats, hardly enough to support those who tended them; while of politics
and governments the survivors would know nothing.  And out of this state of
things have arisen arts and laws, and a great deal of virtue and a great
deal of vice; little by little the world has come to be what it is.  At
first, the few inhabitants would have had a natural fear of descending into
the plains; although they would want to have intercourse with one another,
they would have a difficulty in getting about, having lost the arts, and
having no means of extracting metals from the earth, or of felling timber;
for even if they had saved any tools, these would soon have been worn out,
and they could get no more until the art of metallurgy had been again
revived.  Faction and war would be extinguished among them, for being
solitary they would incline to be friendly; and having abundance of pasture
and plenty of milk and flesh, they would have nothing to quarrel about.  We
may assume that they had also dwellings, clothes, pottery, for the weaving
and plastic arts do not require the use of metals.  In those days they were
neither poor nor rich, and there was no insolence or injustice among them;
for they were of noble natures, and lived up to their principles, and
believed what they were told; knowing nothing of land or naval warfare, or
of legal practices or party conflicts, they were simpler and more
temperate, and also more just than the men of our day.  'Very true.'  I am
showing whence the need of lawgivers arises, for in primitive ages they
neither had nor wanted them.  Men lived according to the customs of their
fathers, in a simple manner, under a patriarchal government, such as still
exists both among Hellenes and barbarians, and is described in Homer as
prevailing among the Cyclopes:--

'They have no laws, and they dwell in rocks or on the tops of mountains,
and every one is the judge of his wife and children, and they do not
trouble themselves about one another.'

'That is a charming poet of yours, though I know little of him, for in
Crete foreign poets are not much read.'  'But he is well known in Sparta,
though he describes Ionian rather than Dorian manners, and he seems to take
your view of primitive society.'  May we not suppose that government arose
out of the union of single families who survived the destruction, and were
under the rule of patriarchs, because they had originally descended from a
single father and mother?  'That is very probable.'  As time went on, men
increased in number, and tilled the ground, living in a common habitation,
which they protected by walls against wild beasts; but the several families
retained the laws and customs which they separately received from their
first parents.  They would naturally like their own laws better than any
others, and would be already formed by them when they met in a common
society:  thus legislation imperceptibly began among them.  For in the next
stage the associated families would appoint plenipotentiaries, who would
select and present to the chiefs those of all their laws which they thought
best.  The chiefs in turn would make a further selection, and would thus
become the lawgivers of the state, which they would form into an
aristocracy or a monarchy.  'Probably.'  In the third stage various other
forms of government would arise.  This state of society is described by
Homer in speaking of the foundation of Dardania, which, he says,

'was built at the foot of many-fountained Ida, for Ilium, the city of the
plain, as yet was not.'

Here, as also in the account of the Cyclopes, the poet by some divine
inspiration has attained truth.  But to proceed with our tale.  Ilium was
built in a wide plain, on a low hill, which was surrounded by streams
descending from Ida.  This shows that many ages must have passed; for the
men who remembered the deluge would never have placed their city at the
mercy of the waters.  When mankind began to multiply, many other cities
were built in similar situations.  These cities carried on a ten years' war
against Troy, by sea as well as land, for men were ceasing to be afraid of
the sea, and, in the meantime, while the chiefs of the army were at Troy,
their homes fell into confusion.  The youth revolted and refused to receive
their own fathers; deaths, murders, exiles ensued.  Under the new name of
Dorians, which they received from their chief Dorieus, the exiles returned: 
the rest of the story is part of the history of Sparta.

Thus, after digressing from the subject of laws into music and drinking, we
return to the settlement of Sparta, which in laws and institutions is the
sister of Crete.  We have seen the rise of a first, second, and third
state, during the lapse of ages; and now we arrive at a fourth state, and
out of the comparison of all four we propose to gather the nature of laws
and governments, and the changes which may be desirable in them.  'If,'
replies the Spartan, 'our new discussion is likely to be as good as the
last, I would think the longest day too short for such an employment.'

Let us imagine the time when Lacedaemon, and Argos, and Messene were all
subject, Megillus, to your ancestors.  Afterwards, they distributed the
army into three portions, and made three cities--Argos, Messene,
Lacedaemon.  'Yes.'  Temenus was the king of Argos, Cresphontes of Messene,
Procles and Eurysthenes ruled at Lacedaemon.  'Just so.'  And they all
swore to assist any one of their number whose kingdom was subverted. 
'Yes.'  But did we not say that kingdoms or governments can only be
subverted by themselves?  'That is true.'  Yes, and the truth is now proved
by facts:  there were certain conditions upon which the three kingdoms were
to assist one another; the government was to be mild and the people
obedient, and the kings and people were to unite in assisting either of the
two others when they were wronged.  This latter condition was a great
security.  'Clearly.'  Such a provision is in opposition to the common
notion that the lawgiver should make only such laws as the people like; but
we say that he should rather be like a physician, prepared to effect a cure
even at the cost of considerable suffering.  'Very true.'  The early
lawgivers had another great advantage--they were saved from the reproach
which attends a division of land and the abolition of debts.  No one could
quarrel with the Dorians for dividing the territory, and they had no debts
of long standing.  'They had not.'  Then what was the reason why their
legislation signally failed?  For there were three kingdoms, two of them
quickly lost their original constitution.  That is a question which we
cannot refuse to answer, if we mean to proceed with our old man's game of
enquiring into laws and institutions.  And the Dorian institutions are more
worthy of consideration than any other, having been evidently intended to
be a protection not only to the Peloponnese, but to all the Hellenes
against the Barbarians.  For the capture of Troy by the Achaeans had given
great offence to the Assyrians, of whose empire it then formed part, and
they were likely to retaliate.  Accordingly the royal Heraclid brothers
devised their military constitution, which was organised on a far better
plan than the old Trojan expedition; and the Dorians themselves were far
superior to the Achaeans, who had taken part in that expedition, and had
been conquered by them.  Such a scheme, undertaken by men who had shared
with one another toils and dangers, sanctioned by the Delphian oracle,
under the guidance of the Heraclidae, seemed to have a promise of
permanence.  'Naturally.'  Yet this has not proved to be the case.  Instead
of the three being one, they have always been at war; had they been united,
in accordance with the original intention, they would have been invincible.

And what caused their ruin?  Did you ever observe that there are beautiful
things of which men often say, 'What wonders they would have effected if
rightly used?' and yet, after all, this may be a mistake.  And so I say of
the Heraclidae and their expedition, which I may perhaps have been
justified in admiring, but which nevertheless suggests to me the general
reflection,--'What wonders might not strength and military resources have
accomplished, if the possessor had only known how to use them!'  For
consider:  if the generals of the army had only known how to arrange their
forces, might they not have given their subjects everlasting freedom, and
the power of doing what they would in all the world?  'Very true.'  Suppose
a person to express his admiration of wealth or rank, does he not do so
under the idea that by the help of these he can attain his desires?  All
men wish to obtain the control of all things, and they are always praying
for what they desire.  'Certainly.'  And we ask for our friends what they
ask for themselves.  'Yes.'  Dear is the son to the father, and yet the
son, if he is young and foolish, will often pray to obtain what the father
will pray that he may not obtain.  'True.'  And when the father, in the
heat of youth or the dotage of age, makes some rash prayer, the son, like
Hippolytus, may have reason to pray that the word of his father may be
ineffectual.  'You mean that a man should pray to have right desires,
before he prays that his desires may be fulfilled; and that wisdom should
be the first object of our prayers?'  Yes; and you will remember my saying
that wisdom should be the principal aim of the legislator; but you said
that defence in war came first.  And I replied, that there were four
virtues, whereas you acknowledged one only--courage, and not wisdom which
is the guide of all the rest.  And I repeat--in jest if you like, but I am
willing that you should receive my words in earnest--that 'the prayer of a
fool is full of danger.'  I will prove to you, if you will allow me, that
the ruin of those states was not caused by cowardice or ignorance in war,
but by ignorance of human affairs.  'Pray proceed:  our attention will show
better than compliments that we prize your words.'  I maintain that
ignorance is, and always has been, the ruin of states; wherefore the
legislator should seek to banish it from the state; and the greatest
ignorance is the love of what is known to be evil, and the hatred of what
is known to be good; this is the last and greatest conflict of pleasure and
reason in the soul.  I say the greatest, because affecting the greater part
of the soul; for the passions are in the individual what the people are in
a state.  And when they become opposed to reason or law, and instruction no
longer avails--that is the last and greatest ignorance of states and men. 
'I agree.'  Let this, then, be our first principle:--That the citizen who
does not know how to choose between good and evil must not have authority,
although he possess great mental gifts, and many accomplishments; for he is
really a fool.  On the other hand, he who has this knowledge may be unable
either to read or swim; nevertheless, he shall be counted wise and
permitted to rule.  For how can there be wisdom where there is no harmony?-
-the wise man is the saviour, and he who is devoid of wisdom is the
destroyer of states and households.  There are rulers and there are
subjects in states.  And the first claim to rule is that of parents to rule
over their children; the second, that of the noble to rule over the
ignoble; thirdly, the elder must govern the younger; in the fourth place,
the slave must obey his master; fifthly, there is the power of the
stronger, which the poet Pindar declares to be according to nature;
sixthly, there is the rule of the wiser, which is also according to nature,
as I must inform Pindar, if he does not know, and is the rule of law over
obedient subjects.  'Most true.'  And there is a seventh kind of rule which
the Gods love,--in this the ruler is elected by lot.

Then, now, we playfully say to him who fancies that it is easy to make
laws:--You see, legislator, the many and inconsistent claims to authority;
here is a spring of troubles which you must stay.  And first of all you
must help us to consider how the kings of Argos and Messene in olden days
destroyed their famous empire--did they forget the saying of Hesiod, that
'the half is better than the whole'?  And do we suppose that the ignorance
of this truth is less fatal to kings than to peoples?  'Probably the evil
is increased by their way of life.'  The kings of those days transgressed
the laws and violated their oaths.  Their deeds were not in harmony with
their words, and their folly, which seemed to them wisdom, was the ruin of
the state.  And how could the legislator have prevented this evil?--the
remedy is easy to see now, but was not easy to foresee at the time.  'What
is the remedy?'  The institutions of Sparta may teach you, Megillus. 
Wherever there is excess, whether the vessel has too large a sail, or the
body too much food, or the mind too much power, there destruction is
certain.  And similarly, a man who possesses arbitrary power is soon
corrupted, and grows hateful to his dearest friends.  In order to guard
against this evil, the God who watched over Sparta gave you two kings
instead of one, that they might balance one another; and further to lower
the pulse of your body politic, some human wisdom, mingled with divine
power, tempered the strength and self-sufficiency of youth with the
moderation of age in the institution of your senate.  A third saviour
bridled your rising and swelling power by ephors, whom he assimilated to
officers elected by lot:  and thus the kingly power was preserved, and
became the preserver of all the rest.  Had the constitution been arranged
by the original legislators, not even the portion of Aristodemus would have
been saved; for they had no political experience, and imagined that a
youthful spirit invested with power could be restrained by oaths.  Now that
God has instructed us in the arts of legislation, there is no merit in
seeing all this, or in learning wisdom after the event.  But if the coming
danger could have been foreseen, and the union preserved, then no Persian
or other enemy would have dared to attack Hellas; and indeed there was not
so much credit to us in defeating the enemy, as discredit in our disloyalty
to one another.  For of the three cities one only fought on behalf of
Hellas; and of the two others, Argos refused her aid; and Messenia was
actually at war with Sparta:  and if the Lacedaemonians and Athenians had
not united, the Hellenes would have been absorbed in the Persian empire,
and dispersed among the barbarians.  We make these reflections upon past
and present legislators because we desire to find out what other course
could have been followed.  We were saying just now, that a state can only
be free and wise and harmonious when there is a balance of powers.  There
are many words by which we express the aims of the legislator,--temperance,
wisdom, friendship; but we need not be disturbed by the variety of
expression,--these words have all the same meaning.  'I should like to know
at what in your opinion the legislator should aim.'  Hear me, then.  There
are two mother forms of states--one monarchy, and the other democracy:  the
Persians have the first in the highest form, and the Athenians the second;
and no government can be well administered which does not include both. 
There was a time when both the Persians and Athenians had more the
character of a constitutional state than they now have.  In the days of
Cyrus the Persians were freemen as well as lords of others, and their
soldiers were free and equal, and the kings used and honoured all the
talent which they could find, and so the nation waxed great, because there
was freedom and friendship and communion of soul.  But Cyrus, though a wise
general, never troubled himself about the education of his family.  He was
a soldier from his youth upward, and left his children who were born in the
purple to be educated by women, who humoured and spoilt them.  'A rare
education, truly!'  Yes, such an education as princesses who had recently
grown rich might be expected to give them in a country where the men were
solely occupied with warlike pursuits.  'Likely enough.'  Their father had
possessions of men and animals, and never considered that the race to whom
he was about to make them over had been educated in a very different
school, not like the Persian shepherd, who was well able to take care of
himself and his own.  He did not see that his children had been brought up
in the Median fashion, by women and eunuchs.  The end was that one of the
sons of Cyrus slew the other, and lost the kingdom by his own folly. 
Observe, again, that Darius, who restored the kingdom, had not received a
royal education.  He was one of the seven chiefs, and when he came to the
throne he divided the empire into seven provinces; and he made equal laws,
and implanted friendship among the people.  Hence his subjects were greatly
attached to him, and cheerfully helped him to extend his empire.  Next
followed Xerxes, who had received the same royal education as Cambyses, and
met with a similar fate.  The reflection naturally occurs to us--How could
Darius, with all his experience, have made such a mistake!  The ruin of
Xerxes was not a mere accident, but the evil life which is generally led by
the sons of very rich and royal persons; and this is what the legislator
has seriously to consider.  Justly may the Lacedaemonians be praised for
not giving special honour to birth or wealth; for such advantages are not
to be highly esteemed without virtue, and not even virtue is to be esteemed
unless it be accompanied by temperance.  'Explain.'  No one would like to
live in the same house with a courageous man who had no control over
himself, nor with a clever artist who was a rogue.  Nor can justice and
wisdom ever be separated from temperance.  But considering these qualities
with reference to the honour and dishonour which is to be assigned to them
in states, would you say, on the other hand, that temperance, if existing
without the other virtues in the soul, is worth anything or nothing?  'I
cannot tell.'  You have answered well.  It would be absurd to speak of
temperance as belonging to the class of honourable or of dishonourable
qualities, because all other virtues in their various classes require
temperance to be added to them; having the addition, they are honoured not
in proportion to that, but to their own excellence.  And ought not the
legislator to determine these classes?  'Certainly.'  Suppose then that,
without going into details, we make three great classes of them.  Most
honourable are the goods of the soul, always assuming temperance as a
condition of them; secondly, those of the body; thirdly, external
possessions.  The legislator who puts them in another order is doing an
unholy and unpatriotic thing.

These remarks were suggested by the history of the Persian kings; and to
them I will now return.  The ruin of their empire was caused by the loss of
freedom and the growth of despotism; all community of feeling disappeared.
Hatred and spoliation took the place of friendship; the people no longer
fought heartily for their masters; the rulers, finding their myriads
useless on the field of battle, resorted to mercenaries as their only
salvation, and were thus compelled by their circumstances to proclaim the
stupidest of falsehoods--that virtue is a trifle in comparison of money.

But enough of the Persians:  a different lesson is taught by the Athenians,
whose example shows that a limited freedom is far better than an unlimited. 
Ancient Athens, at the time of the Persian invasion, had such a limited
freedom.  The people were divided into four classes, according to the
amount of their property, and the universal love of order, as well as the
fear of the approaching host, made them obedient and willing citizens.  For
Darius had sent Datis and Artaphernes, commanding them under pain of death
to subjugate the Eretrians and Athenians.  A report, whether true or not,
came to Athens that all the Eretrians had been 'netted'; and the Athenians
in terror sent all over Hellas for assistance.  None came to their relief
except the Lacedaemonians, and they arrived a day too late, when the battle
of Marathon had been already fought.  In process of time Xerxes came to the
throne, and the Athenians heard of nothing but the bridge over the
Hellespont, and the canal of Athos, and the innumerable host and fleet. 
They knew that these were intended to avenge the defeat of Marathon.  Their
case seemed desperate, for there was no Hellene likely to assist them by
land, and at sea they were attacked by more than a thousand vessels;--their
only hope, however slender, was in victory; so they relied upon themselves
and upon the Gods.  Their common danger, and the influence of their ancient
constitution, greatly tended to promote harmony among them.  Reverence and
fear--that fear which the coward never knows--made them fight for their
altars and their homes, and saved them from being dispersed all over the
world.  'Your words, Athenian, are worthy of your country.'  And you
Megillus, who have inherited the virtues of your ancestors, are worthy to
hear them.  Let me ask you to take the moral of my tale.  The Persians have
lost their liberty in absolute slavery, and we in absolute freedom.  In
ancient times the Athenian people were not the masters, but the servants of
the laws.  'Of what laws?'  In the first place, there were laws about
music, and the music was of various kinds:  there was one kind which
consisted of hymns, another of lamentations; there was also the paean and
the dithyramb, and the so-called 'laws' (nomoi) or strains, which were
played upon the harp.  The regulation of such matters was not left to the
whistling and clapping of the crowd; there was silence while the judges
decided, and the boys, and the audience in general, were kept in order by
raps of a stick.  But after a while there arose a new race of poets, men of
genius certainly, however careless of musical truth and propriety, who made
pleasure the only criterion of excellence.  That was a test which the
spectators could apply for themselves; the whole audience, instead of being
mute, became vociferous, and a theatrocracy took the place of an
aristocracy.  Could the judges have been free, there would have been no
great harm done; a musical democracy would have been well enough--but
conceit has been our ruin.  Everybody knows everything, and is ready to say
anything; the age of reverence is gone, and the age of irreverence and
licentiousness has succeeded.  'Most true.'  And with this freedom comes
disobedience to rulers, parents, elders,--in the latter days to the law
also; the end returns to the beginning, and the old Titanic nature
reappears--men have no regard for the Gods or for oaths; and the evils of
the human race seem as if they would never cease.  Whither are we running
away?  Once more we must pull up the argument with bit and curb, lest, as
the proverb says, we should fall off our ass.  'Good.'  Our purpose in what
we have been saying is to prove that the legislator ought to aim at
securing for a state three things--freedom, friendship, wisdom.  And we
chose two states;--one was the type of freedom, and the other of despotism;
and we showed that when in a mean they attained their highest perfection. 
In a similar spirit we spoke of the Dorian expedition, and of the
settlement on the hills and in the plains of Troy; and of music, and the
use of wine, and of all that preceded.

And now, has our discussion been of any use?  'Yes, stranger; for by a
singular coincidence the Cretans are about to send out a colony, of which
the settlement has been confided to the Cnosians.  Ten commissioners, of
whom I am one, are to give laws to the colonists, and we may give any which
we please--Cretan or foreign.  And therefore let us make a selection from
what has been said, and then proceed with the construction of the state.' 
Very good:  I am quite at your service.  'And I too,' says Megillus.

BOOK IV.  And now, what is this city?  I do not want to know what is to be
the name of the place (for some accident,--a river or a local deity, will
determine that), but what the situation is, whether maritime or inland. 
'The city will be about eleven miles from the sea.'  Are there harbours? 
'Excellent.'  And is the surrounding country self-supporting?  'Almost.' 
Any neighbouring states?  'No; and that is the reason for choosing the
place, which has been deserted from time immemorial.'  And is there a fair
proportion of hill and plain and wood?  'Like Crete in general, more hill
than plain.'  Then there is some hope for your citizens; had the city been
on the sea, and dependent for support on other countries, no human power
could have preserved you from corruption.  Even the distance of eleven
miles is hardly enough.  For the sea, although an agreeable, is a dangerous
companion, and a highway of strange morals and manners as well as of
commerce.  But as the country is only moderately fertile there will be no
great export trade and no great returns of gold and silver, which are the
ruin of states.  Is there timber for ship-building?  'There is no pine, nor
much cypress; and very little stone-pine or plane wood for the interior of
ships.'  That is good.  'Why?'  Because the city will not be able to
imitate the bad ways of her enemies.  'What is the bearing of that remark?' 
To explain my meaning, I would ask you to remember what we said about the
Cretan laws, that they had an eye to war only; whereas I maintained that
they ought to have included all virtue.  And I hope that you in your turn
will retaliate upon me if I am false to my own principle.  For I consider
that the lawgiver should go straight to the mark of virtue and justice, and
disregard wealth and every other good when separated from virtue.  What
further I mean, when I speak of the imitation of enemies, I will illustrate
by the story of Minos, if our Cretan friend will allow me to mention it. 
Minos, who was a great sea-king, imposed upon the Athenians a cruel
tribute, for in those days they were not a maritime power; they had no
timber for ship-building, and therefore they could not 'imitate their
enemies'; and better far, as I maintain, would it have been for them to
have lost many times over the lives which they devoted to the tribute than
to have turned soldiers into sailors.  Naval warfare is not a very
praiseworthy art; men should not be taught to leap on shore, and then again
to hurry back to their ships, or to find specious excuses for throwing away
their arms; bad customs ought not to be gilded with fine words.  And
retreat is always bad, as we are taught in Homer, when he introduces
Odysseus, setting forth to Agamemnon the danger of ships being at hand when
soldiers are disposed to fly.  An army of lions trained in such ways would
fly before a herd of deer.  Further, a city which owes its preservation to
a crowd of pilots and oarsmen and other undeserving persons, cannot bestow
rewards of honour properly; and this is the ruin of states.  'Still, in
Crete we say that the battle of Salamis was the salvation of Hellas.'  Such
is the prevailing opinion.  But I and Megillus say that the battle of
Marathon began the deliverance, and that the battle of Plataea completed
it; for these battles made men better, whereas the battles of Salamis and
Artemisium made them no better.  And we further affirm that mere existence
is not the great political good of individuals or states, but the
continuance of the best existence.  'Certainly.'  Let us then endeavour to
follow this principle in colonization and legislation.

And first, let me ask you who are to be the colonists?  May any one come
from any city of Crete?  For you would surely not send a general invitation
to all Hellas.  Yet I observe that in Crete there are people who have come
from Argos and Aegina and other places.  'Our recruits will be drawn from
all Crete, and of other Hellenes we should prefer Peloponnesians.  As you
observe, there are Argives among the Cretans; moreover the Gortynians, who
are the best of all Cretans, have come from Gortys in Peloponnesus.'

Colonization is in some ways easier when the colony goes out in a swarm
from one country, owing to the pressure of population, or revolution, or
war.  In this case there is the advantage that the new colonists have a
community of race, language, and laws.  But then again, they are less
obedient to the legislator; and often they are anxious to keep the very
laws and customs which caused their ruin at home.  A mixed multitude, on
the other hand, is more tractable, although there is a difficulty in making
them pull together.  There is nothing, however, which perfects men's virtue
more than legislation and colonization.  And yet I have a word to say which
may seem to be depreciatory of legislators.  'What is that?'

I was going to make the saddening reflection, that accidents of all sorts
are the true legislators,--wars and pestilences and famines and the
frequent recurrence of bad seasons.  The observer will be inclined to say
that almost all human things are chance; and this is certainly true about
navigation and medicine, and the art of the general.  But there is another
thing which may equally be said.  'What is it?'  That God governs all
things, and that chance and opportunity co-operate with Him.  And according
to yet a third view, art has part with them, for surely in a storm it is
well to have a pilot?  And the same is true of legislation:  even if
circumstances are favourable, a skilful lawgiver is still necessary.  'Most
true.'  All artists would pray for certain conditions under which to
exercise their art:  and would not the legislator do the same? 
'Certainly?'  Come, legislator, let us say to him, and what are the
conditions which you would have?  He will answer, Grant me a city which is
ruled by a tyrant; and let the tyrant be young, mindful, teachable,
courageous, magnanimous; and let him have the inseparable condition of all
virtue, which is temperance--not prudence, but that natural temperance
which is the gift of children and animals, and is hardly reckoned among
goods--with this he must be endowed, if the state is to acquire the form
most conducive to happiness in the speediest manner.  And I must add one
other condition:  the tyrant must be fortunate, and his good fortune must
consist in his having the co-operation of a great legislator.  When God has
done all this, He has done the best which He can for a state; not so well
if He has given them two legislators instead of one, and less and less well
if He has given them a great many.  An orderly tyranny most easily passes
into the perfect state; in the second degree, a monarchy; in the third
degree, a democracy; an oligarchy is worst of all.  'I do not understand.' 
I suppose that you have never seen a city which is subject to a tyranny? 
'I have no desire to see one.'  You would have seen what I am describing,
if you ever had.  The tyrant can speedily change the manners of a state,
and affix the stamp of praise or blame on any action which he pleases; for
the citizens readily follow the example which he sets.  There is no quicker
way of making changes; but there is a counterbalancing difficulty.  It is
hard to find the divine love of temperance and justice existing in any
powerful form of government, whether in a monarchy or an oligarchy.  In
olden days there were chiefs like Nestor, who was the most eloquent and
temperate of mankind, but there is no one his equal now.  If such an one
ever arises among us, blessed will he be, and blessed they who listen to
his words.  For where power and wisdom and temperance meet in one, there
are the best laws and constitutions.  I am endeavouring to show you how
easy under the conditions supposed, and how difficult under any other, is
the task of giving a city good laws.  'How do you mean?'  Let us old men
attempt to mould in words a constitution for your new state, as children
make figures out of wax.  'Proceed.  What constitution shall we give--
democracy, oligarchy, or aristocracy?'  To which of these classes,
Megillus, do you refer your own state?  'The Spartan constitution seems to
me to contain all these elements.  Our state is a democracy and also an
aristocracy; the power of the Ephors is tyrannical, and we have an ancient
monarchy.'  'Much the same,' adds Cleinias, 'may be said of Cnosus.'  The
reason is that you have polities, but other states are mere aggregations of
men dwelling together, which are named after their several ruling powers;
whereas a state, if an 'ocracy' at all, should be called a theocracy.  A
tale of old will explain my meaning.  There is a tradition of a golden age,
in which all things were spontaneous and abundant.  Cronos, then lord of
the world, knew that no mortal nature could endure the temptations of
power, and therefore he appointed demons or demi-gods, who are of a
superior race, to have dominion over man, as man has dominion over the
animals.  They took care of us with great ease and pleasure to themselves,
and no less to us; and the tradition says that only when God, and not man,
is the ruler, can the human race cease from ill.  This was the manner of
life which prevailed under Cronos, and which we must strive to follow so
far as the principle of immortality still abides in us and we live
according to law and the dictates of right reason.  But in an oligarchy or
democracy, when the governing principle is athirst for pleasure, the laws
are trampled under foot, and there is no possibility of salvation.  Is it
not often said that there are as many forms of laws as there are
governments, and that they have no concern either with any one virtue or
with all virtue, but are relative to the will of the government?  Which is
as much as to say that 'might makes right.'  'What do you mean?'  I mean
that governments enact their own laws, and that every government makes
self-preservation its principal aim.  He who transgresses the laws is
regarded as an evil-doer, and punished accordingly.  This was one of the
unjust principles of government which we mentioned when speaking of the
different claims to rule.  We were agreed that parents should rule their
children, the elder the younger, the noble the ignoble.  But there were
also several other principles, and among them Pindar's 'law of violence.' 
To whom then is our state to be entrusted?  For many a government is only a
victorious faction which has a monopoly of power, and refuses any share to
the conquered, lest when they get into office they should remember their
wrongs.  Such governments are not polities, but parties; nor are any laws
good which are made in the interest of particular classes only, and not of
the whole.  And in our state I mean to protest against making any man a
ruler because he is rich, or strong, or noble.  But those who are obedient
to the laws, and who win the victory of obedience, shall be promoted to the
service of the Gods according to the degree of their obedience.  When I
call the ruler the servant or minister of the law, this is not a mere
paradox, but I mean to say that upon a willingness to obey the law the
existence of the state depends.  'Truly, Stranger, you have a keen vision.' 
Why, yes; every man when he is old has his intellectual vision most keen. 
And now shall we call in our colonists and make a speech to them?  Friends,
we say to them, God holds in His hand the beginning, middle, and end of all
things, and He moves in a straight line towards the accomplishment of His
will.  Justice always bears Him company, and punishes those who fall short
of His laws.  He who would be happy follows humbly in her train; but he who
is lifted up with pride, or wealth, or honour, or beauty, is soon deserted
by God, and, being deserted, he lives in confusion and disorder.  To many
he seems a great man; but in a short time he comes to utter destruction. 
Wherefore, seeing these things, what ought we to do or think?  'Every man
ought to follow God.'  What life, then, is pleasing to God?  There is an
old saying that 'like agrees with like, measure with measure,' and God
ought to be our measure in all things.  The temperate man is the friend of
God because he is like Him, and the intemperate man is not His friend,
because he is not like Him.  And the conclusion is, that the best of all
things for a good man is to pray and sacrifice to the Gods; but the bad man
has a polluted soul; and therefore his service is wasted upon the Gods,
while the good are accepted of them.  I have told you the mark at which we
ought to aim.  You will say, How, and with what weapons?  In the first
place we affirm, that after the Olympian Gods and the Gods of the state,
honour should be given to the Gods below, and to them should be offered
everything in even numbers and of the second choice; the auspicious odd
numbers and everything of the first choice are reserved for the Gods above. 
Next demi-gods or spirits must be honoured, and then heroes, and after them
family gods, who will be worshipped at their local seats according to law. 
Further, the honour due to parents should not be forgotten; children owe
all that they have to them, and the debt must be repaid by kindness and
attention in old age.  No unbecoming word must be uttered before them; for
there is an avenging angel who hears them when they are angry, and the
child should consider that the parent when he has been wronged has a right
to be angry.  After their death let them have a moderate funeral, such as
their fathers have had before them; and there shall be an annual
commemoration of them.  Living on this wise, we shall be accepted of the
Gods, and shall pass our days in good hope.  The law will determine all our
various duties towards relatives and friends and other citizens, and the
whole state will be happy and prosperous.  But if the legislator would
persuade as well as command, he will add prefaces to his laws which will
predispose the citizens to virtue.  Even a little accomplished in the way
of gaining the hearts of men is of great value.  For most men are in no
particular haste to become good.  As Hesiod says:

'Long and steep is the first half of the way to virtue,
But when you have reached the top the rest is easy.'

'Those are excellent words.'  Yes; but may I tell you the effect which the
preceding discourse has had upon me?  I will express my meaning in an
address to the lawgiver:--O lawgiver, if you know what we ought to do and
say, you can surely tell us;--you are not like the poet, who, as you were
just now saying, does not know the effect of his own words.  And the poet
may reply, that when he sits down on the tripod of the Muses he is not in
his right mind, and that being a mere imitator he may be allowed to say all
sorts of opposite things, and cannot tell which of them is true.  But this
licence cannot be allowed to the lawgiver.  For example, there are three
kinds of funerals; one of them is excessive, another mean, a third
moderate, and you say that the last is right.  Now if I had a rich wife,
and she told me to bury her, and I were to sing of her burial, I should
praise the extravagant kind; a poor man would commend a funeral of the
meaner sort, and a man of moderate means would prefer a moderate funeral. 
But you, as legislator, would have to say exactly what you meant by
'moderate.'  'Very true.'  And is our lawgiver to have no preamble or
interpretation of his laws, never offering a word of advice to his
subjects, after the manner of some doctors?  For of doctors are there not
two kinds?  The one gentle and the other rough, doctors who are freemen and
learn themselves and teach their pupils scientifically, and doctor's
assistants who get their knowledge empirically by attending on their
masters?  'Of course there are.'  And did you ever observe that the
gentlemen doctors practise upon freemen, and that slave doctors confine
themselves to slaves?  The latter go about the country or wait for the
slaves at the dispensaries.  They hold no parley with their patients about
their diseases or the remedies of them; they practise by the rule of thumb,
and give their decrees in the most arbitrary manner.  When they have
doctored one patient they run off to another, whom they treat with equal
assurance, their duty being to relieve the master of the care of his sick
slaves.  But the other doctor, who practises on freemen, proceeds in quite
a different way.  He takes counsel with his patient and learns from him,
and never does anything until he has persuaded him of what he is doing.  He
trusts to influence rather than force.  Now is not the use of both methods
far better than the use of either alone?  And both together may be
advantageously employed by us in legislation.

We may illustrate our proposal by an example.  The laws relating to
marriage naturally come first, and therefore we may begin with them.  The
simple law would be as follows:--A man shall marry between the ages of
thirty and thirty-five; if he do not, he shall be fined or deprived of
certain privileges.  The double law would add the reason why:  Forasmuch as
man desires immortality, which he attains by the procreation of children,
no one should deprive himself of his share in this good.  He who obeys the
law is blameless, but he who disobeys must not be a gainer by his celibacy;
and therefore he shall pay a yearly fine, and shall not be allowed to
receive honour from the young.  That is an example of what I call the
double law, which may enable us to judge how far the addition of persuasion
to threats is desirable.  'Lacedaemonians in general, Stranger, are in
favour of brevity; in this case, however, I prefer length.  But Cleinias is
the real lawgiver, and he ought to be first consulted.'  'Thank you,
Megillus.'  Whether words are to be many or few, is a foolish question:--
the best and not the shortest forms are always to be approved.  And
legislators have never thought of the advantages which they might gain by
using persuasion as well as force, but trust to force only.  And I have
something else to say about the matter.  Here have we been from early dawn
until noon, discoursing about laws, and all that we have been saying is
only the preamble of the laws which we are about to give.  I tell you this,
because I want you to observe that songs and strains have all of them
preludes, but that laws, though called by the same name (nomoi), have never
any prelude.  Now I am disposed to give preludes to laws, dividing them
into two parts--one containing the despotic command, which I described
under the image of the slave doctor--the other the persuasive part, which I
term the preamble.  The legislator should give preludes or preambles to his
laws.  'That shall be the way in my colony.'  I am glad that you agree with
me; this is a matter which it is important to remember.  A preamble is not
always necessary to a law:  the lawgiver must determine when it is needed,
as the musician determines when there is to be a prelude to a song.  'Most
true:  and now, having a preamble, let us recommence our discourse.' 
Enough has been said of Gods and parents, and we may proceed to consider
what relates to the citizens--their souls, bodies, properties,--their
occupations and amusements; and so arrive at the nature of education.

The first word of the Laws somewhat abruptly introduces the thought which
is present to the mind of Plato throughout the work, namely, that Law is of
divine origin.  In the words of a great English writer--'Her seat is the
bosom of God, her voice the harmony of the world.'  Though the particular
laws of Sparta and Crete had a narrow and imperfect aim, this is not true
of divine laws, which are based upon the principles of human nature, and
not framed to meet the exigencies of the moment.  They have their natural
divisions, too, answering to the kinds of virtue; very unlike the
discordant enactments of an Athenian assembly or of an English Parliament.
Yet we may observe two inconsistencies in Plato's treatment of the subject: 
first, a lesser, inasmuch as he does not clearly distinguish the Cretan and
Spartan laws, of which the exclusive aim is war, from those other laws of
Zeus and Apollo which are said to be divine, and to comprehend all virtue.
Secondly, we may retort on him his own complaint against Sparta and Crete,
that he has himself given us a code of laws, which for the most part have a
military character; and that we cannot point to 'obvious examples of
similar institutions which are concerned with pleasure;' at least there is
only one such, that which relates to the regulation of convivial
intercourse.  The military spirit which is condemned by him in the
beginning of the Laws, reappears in the seventh and eighth books.

The mention of Minos the great lawgiver, and of Rhadamanthus the righteous
administrator of the law, suggests the two divisions of the laws into
enactments and appointments of officers.  The legislator and the judge
stand side by side, and their functions cannot be wholly distinguished. 
For the judge is in some sort a legislator, at any rate in small matters;
and his decisions growing into precedents, must determine the innumerable
details which arise out of the conflict of circumstances.  These Plato
proposes to leave to a younger generation of legislators.  The action of
courts of law in making law seems to have escaped him, probably because the
Athenian law-courts were popular assemblies; and, except in a mythical
form, he can hardly be said to have had before his eyes the ideal of a
judge.  In reading the Laws of Plato, or any other ancient writing about
Laws, we should consider how gradual the process is by which not only a
legal system, but the administration of a court of law, becomes perfected.

There are other subjects on which Plato breaks ground, as his manner is,
early in the work.  First, he gives a sketch of the subject of laws; they
are to comprehend the whole of human life, from infancy to age, and from
birth to death, although the proposed plan is far from being regularly
executed in the books which follow, partly owing to the necessity of
describing the constitution as well as the laws of his new colony. 
Secondly, he touches on the power of music, which may exercise so great an
influence on the character of men for good or evil; he refers especially to
the great offence--which he mentions again, and which he had condemned in
the Republic--of varying the modes and rhythms, as well as to that of
separating the words from the music.  Thirdly, he reprobates the prevalence
of unnatural loves in Sparta and Crete, which he attributes to the practice
of syssitia and gymnastic exercises, and considers to be almost inseparable
from them.  To this subject he again returns in the eighth book.  Fourthly,
the virtues are affirmed to be inseparable from one another, even if not
absolutely one; this, too, is a principle which he reasserts at the
conclusion of the work.  As in the beginnings of Plato's other writings, we
have here several 'notes' struck, which form the preludes of longer
discussions, although the hint is less ingeniously given, and the promise
more imperfectly fulfilled than in the earlier dialogues.

The distinction between ethics and politics has not yet dawned upon Plato's
mind.  To him, law is still floating in a region between the two.  He would
have desired that all the acts and laws of a state should have regard to
all virtue.  But he did not see that politics and law are subject to their
own conditions, and are distinguished from ethics by natural differences. 
The actions of which politics take cognisance are necessarily collective or
representative; and law is limited to external acts which affect others as
well as the agents.  Ethics, on the other hand, include the whole duty of
man in relation both to himself and others.  But Plato has never reflected
on these differences.  He fancies that the life of the state can be as
easily fashioned as that of the individual.  He is favourable to a balance
of power, but never seems to have considered that power might be so
balanced as to produce an absolute immobility in the state.  Nor is he
alive to the evils of confounding vice and crime; or to the necessity of
governments abstaining from excessive interference with their subjects.

Yet this confusion of ethics and politics has also a better and a truer
side.  If unable to grasp some important distinctions, Plato is at any rate
seeking to elevate the lower to the higher; he does not pull down the
principles of men to their practice, or narrow the conception of the state
to the immediate necessities of politics.  Political ideals of freedom and
equality, of a divine government which has been or will be in some other
age or country, have greatly tended to educate and ennoble the human race.
And if not the first author of such ideals (for they are as old as Hesiod),
Plato has done more than any other writer to impress them on the world.  To
those who censure his idealism we may reply in his own words--'He is not
the worse painter who draws a perfectly beautiful figure, because no such
figure of a man could ever have existed' (Republic).

A new thought about education suddenly occurs to him, and for a time
exercises a sort of fascination over his mind, though in the later books of
the Laws it is forgotten or overlooked.  As true courage is allied to
temperance, so there must be an education which shall train mankind to
resist pleasure as well as to endure pain.  No one can be on his guard
against that of which he has no experience.  The perfectly trained citizen
should have been accustomed to look his enemy in the face, and to measure
his strength against her.  This education in pleasure is to be given,
partly by festive intercourse, but chiefly by the song and dance.  Youth
are to learn music and gymnastics; their elders are to be trained and
tested at drinking parties.  According to the old proverb, in vino veritas,
they will then be open and visible to the world in their true characters;
and also they will be more amenable to the laws, and more easily moulded by
the hand of the legislator.  The first reason is curious enough, though not
important; the second can hardly be thought deserving of much attention. 
Yet if Plato means to say that society is one of the principal instruments
of education in after-life, he has expressed in an obscure fashion a
principle which is true, and to his contemporaries was also new.  That at a
banquet a degree of moral discipline might be exercised is an original
thought, but Plato has not yet learnt to express his meaning in an abstract
form.  He is sensible that moderation is better than total abstinence, and
that asceticism is but a one-sided training.  He makes the sagacious
remark, that 'those who are able to resist pleasure may often be among the
worst of mankind.'  He is as much aware as any modern utilitarian that the
love of pleasure is the great motive of human action.  This cannot be
eradicated, and must therefore be regulated,--the pleasure must be of the
right sort.  Such reflections seem to be the real, though imperfectly
expressed, groundwork of the discussion.  As in the juxtaposition of the
Bacchic madness and the great gift of Dionysus, or where he speaks of the
different senses in which pleasure is and is not the object of imitative
art, or in the illustration of the failure of the Dorian institutions from
the prayer of Theseus, we have to gather his meaning as well as we can from
the connexion.

The feeling of old age is discernible in this as well as in several other
passages of the Laws.  Plato has arrived at the time when men sit still and
look on at life; and he is willing to allow himself and others the few
pleasures which remain to them.  Wine is to cheer them now that their limbs
are old and their blood runs cold.  They are the best critics of dancing
and music, but cannot be induced to join in song unless they have been
enlivened by drinking.  Youth has no need of the stimulus of wine, but age
can only be made young again by its invigorating influence.  Total
abstinence for the young, moderate and increasing potations for the old, is
Plato's principle.  The fire, of which there is too much in the one, has to
be brought to the other.  Drunkenness, like madness, had a sacredness and
mystery to the Greek; if, on the one hand, as in the case of the
Tarentines, it degraded a whole population, it was also a mode of
worshipping the god Dionysus, which was to be practised on certain
occasions.  Moreover, the intoxication produced by the fruit of the vine
was very different from the grosser forms of drunkenness which prevail
among some modern nations.

The physician in modern times would restrict the old man's use of wine
within narrow limits.  He would tell us that you cannot restore strength by
a stimulus.  Wine may call back the vital powers in disease, but cannot
reinvigorate old age.  In his maxims of health and longevity, though aware
of the importance of a simple diet, Plato has omitted to dwell on the
perfect rule of moderation.  His commendation of wine is probably a passing
fancy, and may have arisen out of his own habits or tastes.  If so, he is
not the only philosopher whose theory has been based upon his practice.

Plato's denial of wine to the young and his approval of it for their elders
has some points of view which may be illustrated by the temperance
controversy of our own times.  Wine may be allowed to have a religious as
well as a festive use; it is commended both in the Old and New Testament;
it has been sung of by nearly all poets; and it may be truly said to have a
healing influence both on body and mind.  Yet it is also very liable to
excess and abuse, and for this reason is prohibited by Mahometans, as well
as of late years by many Christians, no less than by the ancient Spartans;
and to sound its praises seriously seems to partake of the nature of a
paradox.  But we may rejoin with Plato that the abuse of a good thing does
not take away the use of it.  Total abstinence, as we often say, is not the
best rule, but moderate indulgence; and it is probably true that a
temperate use of wine may contribute some elements of character to social
life which we can ill afford to lose.  It draws men out of their reserve;
it helps them to forget themselves and to appear as they by nature are when
not on their guard, and therefore to make them more human and greater
friends to their fellow-men.  It gives them a new experience; it teaches
them to combine self-control with a measure of indulgence; it may sometimes
restore to them the simplicity of childhood.  We entirely agree with Plato
in forbidding the use of wine to the young; but when we are of mature age
there are occasions on which we derive refreshment and strength from
moderate potations.  It is well to make abstinence the rule, but the rule
may sometimes admit of an exception.  We are in a higher, as well as in a
lower sense, the better for the use of wine.  The question runs up into
wider ones--What is the general effect of asceticism on human nature? and,
Must there not be a certain proportion between the aspirations of man and
his powers?--questions which have been often discussed both by ancient and
modern philosophers.  So by comparing things old and new we may sometimes
help to realize to ourselves the meaning of Plato in the altered
circumstances of our own life.

Like the importance which he attaches to festive entertainments, his
depreciation of courage to the fourth place in the scale of virtue appears
to be somewhat rhetorical and exaggerated.  But he is speaking of courage
in the lower sense of the term, not as including loyalty or temperance.  He
does not insist in this passage, as in the Protagoras, on the unity of the
virtues; or, as in the Laches, on the identity of wisdom and courage.  But
he says that they all depend upon their leader mind, and that, out of the
union of wisdom and temperance with courage, springs justice.  Elsewhere he
is disposed to regard temperance rather as a condition of all virtue than
as a particular virtue.  He generalizes temperance, as in the Republic he
generalizes justice.  The nature of the virtues is to run up into one
another, and in many passages Plato makes but a faint effort to distinguish
them.  He still quotes the poets, somewhat enlarging, as his manner is, or
playing with their meaning.  The martial poet Tyrtaeus, and the oligarch
Theognis, furnish him with happy illustrations of the two sorts of courage. 
The fear of fear, the division of goods into human and divine, the
acknowledgment that peace and reconciliation are better than the appeal to
the sword, the analysis of temperance into resistance of pleasure as well
as endurance of pain, the distinction between the education which is
suitable for a trade or profession, and for the whole of life, are
important and probably new ethical conceptions.  Nor has Plato forgotten
his old paradox (Gorgias) that to be punished is better than to be
unpunished, when he says, that to the bad man death is the only mitigation
of his evil.  He is not less ideal in many passages of the Laws than in the
Gorgias or Republic.  But his wings are heavy, and he is unequal to any
sustained flight.

There is more attempt at dramatic effect in the first book than in the
later parts of the work.  The outburst of martial spirit in the
Lacedaemonian, 'O best of men'; the protest which the Cretan makes against
the supposed insult to his lawgiver; the cordial acknowledgment on the part
of both of them that laws should not be discussed publicly by those who
live under their rule; the difficulty which they alike experience in
following the speculations of the Athenian, are highly characteristic.

In the second book, Plato pursues further his notion of educating by a
right use of pleasure.  He begins by conceiving an endless power of
youthful life, which is to be reduced to rule and measure by harmony and
rhythm.  Men differ from the lower animals in that they are capable of
musical discipline.  But music, like all art, must be truly imitative, and
imitative of what is true and good.  Art and morality agree in rejecting
pleasure as the criterion of good.  True art is inseparable from the
highest and most ennobling ideas.  Plato only recognizes the identity of
pleasure and good when the pleasure is of the higher kind.  He is the enemy
of 'songs without words,' which he supposes to have some confusing or
enervating effect on the mind of the hearer; and he is also opposed to the
modern degeneracy of the drama, which he would probably have illustrated,
like Aristophanes, from Euripides and Agathon.  From this passage may be
gathered a more perfect conception of art than from any other of Plato's
writings.  He understands that art is at once imitative and ideal, an exact
representation of truth, and also a representation of the highest truth. 
The same double view of art may be gathered from a comparison of the third
and tenth books of the Republic, but is here more clearly and pointedly
expressed.

We are inclined to suspect that both here and in the Republic Plato
exaggerates the influence really exercised by the song and the dance.  But
we must remember also the susceptible nature of the Greek, and the
perfection to which these arts were carried by him.  Further, the music had
a sacred and Pythagorean character; the dance too was part of a religious
festival.  And only at such festivals the sexes mingled in public, and the
youths passed under the eyes of their elders.

At the beginning of the third book, Plato abruptly asks the question, What
is the origin of states?  The answer is, Infinite time.  We have already
seen--in the Theaetetus, where he supposes that in the course of ages every
man has had numberless progenitors, kings and slaves, Greeks and
barbarians; and in the Critias, where he says that nine thousand years have
elapsed since the island of Atlantis fought with Athens--that Plato is no
stranger to the conception of long periods of time.  He imagines human
society to have been interrupted by natural convulsions; and beginning from
the last of these, he traces the steps by which the family has grown into
the state, and the original scattered society, becoming more and more
civilised, has finally passed into military organizations like those of
Crete and Sparta.  His conception of the origin of states is far truer in
the Laws than in the Republic; but it must be remembered that here he is
giving an historical, there an ideal picture of the growth of society.

Modern enquirers, like Plato, have found in infinite ages the explanation
not only of states, but of languages, men, animals, the world itself; like
him, also, they have detected in later institutions the vestiges of a
patriarchal state still surviving.  Thus far Plato speaks as 'the spectator
of all time and all existence,' who may be thought by some divine instinct
to have guessed at truths which were hereafter to be revealed.  He is far
above the vulgar notion that Hellas is the civilized world (Statesman), or
that civilization only began when the Hellenes appeared on the scene.  But
he has no special knowledge of 'the days before the flood'; and when he
approaches more historical times, in preparing the way for his own theory
of mixed government, he argues partially and erroneously.  He is desirous
of showing that unlimited power is ruinous to any state, and hence he is
led to attribute a tyrannical spirit to the first Dorian kings.  The decay
of Argos and the destruction of Messene are adduced by him as a manifest
proof of their failure; and Sparta, he thinks, was only preserved by the
limitations which the wisdom of successive legislators introduced into the
government.  But there is no more reason to suppose that the Dorian rule of
life which was followed at Sparta ever prevailed in Argos and Messene, than
to assume that Dorian institutions were framed to protect the Greeks
against the power of Assyria; or that the empire of Assyria was in any way
affected by the Trojan war; or that the return of the Heraclidae was only
the return of Achaean exiles, who received a new name from their leader
Dorieus.  Such fancies were chiefly based, as far as they had any
foundation, on the use of analogy, which played a great part in the dawn of
historical and geographical research.  Because there was a Persian empire
which was the natural enemy of the Greek, there must also have been an
Assyrian empire, which had a similar hostility; and not only the fable of
the island of Atlantis, but the Trojan war, in Plato's mind derived some
features from the Persian struggle.  So Herodotus makes the Nile answer to
the Ister, and the valley of the Nile to the Red Sea.  In the Republic,
Plato is flying in the air regardless of fact and possibility--in the Laws,
he is making history by analogy.  In the former, he appears to be like some
modern philosophers, absolutely devoid of historical sense; in the latter,
he is on a level, not with Thucydides, or the critical historians of
Greece, but with Herodotus, or even with Ctesias.

The chief object of Plato in tracing the origin of society is to show the
point at which regular government superseded the patriarchical authority,
and the separate customs of different families were systematized by
legislators, and took the form of laws consented to by them all.  According
to Plato, the only sound principle on which any government could be based
was a mixture or balance of power.  The balance of power saved Sparta, when
the two other Heraclid states fell into disorder.  Here is probably the
first trace of a political idea, which has exercised a vast influence both
in ancient and modern times.  And yet we might fairly ask, a little
parodying the language of Plato--O legislator, is unanimity only 'the
struggle for existence'; or is the balance of powers in a state better than
the harmony of them?

In the fourth book we approach the realities of politics, and Plato begins
to ascend to the height of his great argument.  The reign of Cronos has
passed away, and various forms of government have succeeded, which are all
based on self-interest and self-preservation.  Right and wrong, instead of
being measured by the will of God, are created by the law of the state. 
The strongest assertions are made of the purely spiritual nature of
religion--'Without holiness no man is accepted of God'; and of the duty of
filial obedience,--'Honour thy parents.'  The legislator must teach these
precepts as well as command them.  He is to be the educator as well as the
lawgiver of future ages, and his laws are themselves to form a part of the
education of the state.  Unlike the poet, he must be definite and rational;
he cannot be allowed to say one thing at one time, and another thing at
another--he must know what he is about.  And yet legislation has a poetical
or rhetorical element, and must find words which will wing their way to the
hearts of men.  Laws must be promulgated before they are put in execution,
and mankind must be reasoned with before they are punished.  The
legislator, when he promulgates a particular law, will courteously entreat
those who are willing to hear his voice.  Upon the rebellious only does the
heavy blow descend.  A sermon and a law in one, blending the secular
punishment with the religious sanction, appeared to Plato a new idea which
might have a great result in reforming the world.  The experiment had never
been tried of reasoning with mankind; the laws of others had never had any
preambles, and Plato seems to have great pleasure in contemplating his
discovery.

In these quaint forms of thought and language, great principles of morals
and legislation are enunciated by him for the first time.  They all go back
to mind and God, who holds the beginning, middle, and end of all things in
His hand.  The adjustment of the divine and human elements in the world is
conceived in the spirit of modern popular philosophy, differing not much in
the mode of expression.  At first sight the legislator appears to be
impotent, for all things are the sport of chance.  But we admit also that
God governs all things, and that chance and opportunity co-operate with Him
(compare the saying, that chance is the name of the unknown cause). 
Lastly, while we acknowledge that God and chance govern mankind and provide
the conditions of human action, experience will not allow us to deny a
place to art.  We know that there is a use in having a pilot, though the
storm may overwhelm him; and a legislator is required to provide for the
happiness of a state, although he will pray for favourable conditions under
which he may exercise his art.

BOOK V.  Hear now, all ye who heard the laws about Gods and ancestors:  Of
all human possessions the soul is most divine, and most truly a man's own.
For in every man there are two parts--a better which rules, and an inferior
which serves; and the ruler is to be preferred to the servant.  Wherefore I
bid every one next after the Gods to honour his own soul, and he can only
honour her by making her better.  A man does not honour his soul by
flattery, or gifts, or self-indulgence, or conceit of knowledge, nor when
he blames others for his own errors; nor when he indulges in pleasure or
refuses to bear pain; nor when he thinks that life at any price is a good,
because he fears the world below, which, far from being an evil, may be the
greatest good; nor when he prefers beauty to virtue--not reflecting that
the soul, which came from heaven, is more honourable than the body, which
is earth-born; nor when he covets dishonest gains, of which no amount is
equal in value to virtue;--in a word, when he counts that which the
legislator pronounces evil to be good, he degrades his soul, which is the
divinest part of him.  He does not consider that the real punishment of
evil-doing is to grow like evil men, and to shun the conversation of the
good:  and that he who is joined to such men must do and suffer what they
by nature do and say to one another, which suffering is not justice but
retribution.  For justice is noble, but retribution is only the companion
of injustice.  And whether a man escapes punishment or not, he is equally
miserable; for in the one case he is not cured, and in the other case he
perishes that the rest may be saved.

The glory of man is to follow the better and improve the inferior.  And the
soul is that part of man which is most inclined to avoid the evil and dwell
with the good.  Wherefore also the soul is second only to the Gods in
honour, and in the third place the body is to be esteemed, which often has
a false honour.  For honour is not to be given to the fair or the strong,
or the swift or the tall, or to the healthy, any more than to their
opposites, but to the mean states of all these habits; and so of property
and external goods.  No man should heap up riches that he may leave them to
his children.  The best condition for them as for the state is a middle
one, in which there is a freedom without luxury.  And the best inheritance
of children is modesty.  But modesty cannot be implanted by admonition
only--the elders must set the example.  He who would train the young must
first train himself.

He who honours his kindred and family may fairly expect that the Gods will
give him children.  He who would have friends must think much of their
favours to him, and little of his to them.  He who prefers to an Olympic,
or any other victory, to win the palm of obedience to the laws, serves best
both the state and his fellow-citizens.  Engagements with strangers are to
be deemed most sacred, because the stranger, having neither kindred nor
friends, is immediately under the protection of Zeus, the God of strangers.
A prudent man will not sin against the stranger; and still more carefully
will he avoid sinning against the suppliant, which is an offence never
passed over by the Gods.

I will now speak of those particulars which are matters of praise and blame
only, and which, although not enforced by the law, greatly affect the
disposition to obey the law.  Truth has the first place among the gifts of
Gods and men, for truth begets trust; but he is not to be trusted who loves
voluntary falsehood, and he who loves involuntary falsehood is a fool. 
Neither the ignorant nor the untrustworthy man is happy; for they have no
friends in life, and die unlamented and untended.  Good is he who does no
injustice--better who prevents others from doing any--best of all who joins
the rulers in punishing injustice.  And this is true of goods and virtues
in general; he who has and communicates them to others is the man of men;
he who would, if he could, is second-best; he who has them and is jealous
of imparting them to others is to be blamed, but the good or virtue which
he has is to be valued still. Let every man contend in the race without
envy; for the unenvious man increases the strength of the city; himself
foremost in the race, he harms no one with calumny.  Whereas the envious
man is weak himself, and drives his rivals to despair with his slanders,
thus depriving the whole city of incentives to the exercise of virtue, and
tarnishing her glory.  Every man should be gentle, but also passionate; for
he must have the spirit to fight against incurable and malignant evil.  But
the evil which is remediable should be dealt with more in sorrow than
anger.  He who is unjust is to be pitied in any case; for no man
voluntarily does evil or allows evil to exist in his soul.  And therefore
he who deals with the curable sort must be long-suffering and forbearing;
but the incurable shall have the vials of our wrath poured out upon him. 
The greatest of all evils is self-love, which is thought to be natural and
excusable, and is enforced as a duty, and yet is the cause of many errors. 
The lover is blinded about the beloved, and prefers his own interests to
truth and right; but the truly great man seeks justice before all things. 
Self-love is the source of that ignorant conceit of knowledge which is
always doing and never succeeding.  Wherefore let every man avoid self-
love, and follow the guidance of those who are better than himself.  There
are lesser matters which a man should recall to mind; for wisdom is like a
stream, ever flowing in and out, and recollection flows in when knowledge
is failing.  Let no man either laugh or grieve overmuch; but let him
control his feelings in the day of good- or ill-fortune, believing that the
Gods will diminish the evils and increase the blessings of the righteous. 
These are thoughts which should ever occupy a good man's mind; he should
remember them both in lighter and in more serious hours, and remind others
of them.

So much of divine matters and the relation of man to God.  But man is man,
and dependent on pleasure and pain; and therefore to acquire a true taste
respecting either is a great matter.  And what is a true taste?  This can
only be explained by a comparison of one life with another.  Pleasure is an
object of desire, pain of avoidance; and the absence of pain is to be
preferred to pain, but not to pleasure.  There are infinite kinds and
degrees of both of them, and we choose the life which has more pleasure and
avoid that which has less; but we do not choose that life in which the
elements of pleasure are either feeble or equally balanced with pain.  All
the lives which we desire are pleasant; the choice of any others is due to
inexperience.

Now there are four lives--the temperate, the rational, the courageous, the
healthful; and to these let us oppose four others--the intemperate, the
foolish, the cowardly, the diseased.  The temperate life has gentle pains
and pleasures and placid desires, the intemperate life has violent
delights, and still more violent desires.  And the pleasures of the
temperate exceed the pains, while the pains of the intemperate exceed the
pleasures.  But if this is true, none are voluntarily intemperate, but all
who lack temperance are either ignorant or wanting in self-control:  for
men always choose the life which (as they think) exceeds in pleasure.  The
wise, the healthful, the courageous life have a similar advantage--they
also exceed their opposites in pleasure.  And, generally speaking, the life
of virtue is far more pleasurable and honourable, fairer and happier far,
than the life of vice.  Let this be the preamble of our laws; the strain
will follow.

As in a web the warp is stronger than the woof, so should the rulers be
stronger than their half-educated subjects.  Let us suppose, then, that in
the constitution of a state there are two parts, the appointment of the
rulers, and the laws which they have to administer.  But, before going
further, there are some preliminary matters which have to be considered.

As of animals, so also of men, a selection must be made; the bad breed must
be got rid of, and the good retained.  The legislator must purify them, and
if he be not a despot he will find this task to be a difficult one.  The
severer kinds of purification are practised when great offenders are
punished by death or exile, but there is a milder process which is
necessary when the poor show a disposition to attack the property of the
rich, for then the legislator will send them off to another land, under the
name of a colony.  In our case, however, we shall only need to purify the
streams before they meet.  This is often a troublesome business, but in
theory we may suppose the operation performed, and the desired purity
attained.  Evil men we will hinder from coming, and receive the good as
friends.

Like the old Heraclid colony, we are fortunate in escaping the abolition of
debts and the distribution of land, which are difficult and dangerous
questions.  But, perhaps, now that we are speaking of the subject, we ought
to say how, if the danger existed, the legislator should try to avert it. 
He would have recourse to prayers, and trust to the healing influence of
time.  He would create a kindly spirit between creditors and debtors: 
those who have should give to those who have not, and poverty should be
held to be rather the increase of a man's desires than the diminution of
his property.  Good-will is the only safe and enduring foundation of the
political society; and upon this our city shall be built.  The lawgiver, if
he is wise, will not proceed with the arrangement of the state until all
disputes about property are settled.  And for him to introduce fresh
grounds of quarrel would be madness.

Let us now proceed to the distribution of our state, and determine the size
of the territory and the number of the allotments.  The territory should be
sufficient to maintain the citizens in moderation, and the population
should be numerous enough to defend themselves, and sometimes to aid their
neighbours.  We will fix the number of citizens at 5040, to which the
number of houses and portions of land shall correspond.  Let the number be
divided into two parts and then into three; for it is very convenient for
the purposes of distribution, and is capable of fifty-nine divisions, ten
of which proceed without interval from one to ten.  Here are numbers enough
for war and peace, and for all contracts and dealings.  These properties of
numbers are true, and should be ascertained with a view to use.

In carrying out the distribution of the land, a prudent legislator will be
careful to respect any provision for religious worship which has been
sanctioned by ancient tradition or by the oracles of Delphi, Dodona, or
Ammon.  All sacrifices, and altars, and temples, whatever may be their
origin, should remain as they are.  Every division should have a patron God
or hero; to these a portion of the domain should be appropriated, and at
their temples the inhabitants of the districts should meet together from
time to time, for the sake of mutual help and friendship.  All the citizens
of a state should be known to one another; for where men are in the dark
about each other's characters, there can be no justice or right
administration.  Every man should be true and single-minded, and should not
allow himself to be deceived by others.

And now the game opens, and we begin to move the pieces.  At first sight,
our constitution may appear singular and ill-adapted to a legislator who
has not despotic power; but on second thoughts will be deemed to be, if not
the very best, the second best.  For there are three forms of government, a
first, a second, and a third best, out of which Cleinias has now to choose.
The first and highest form is that in which friends have all things in
common, including wives and property,--in which they have common fears,
hopes, desires, and do not even call their eyes or their hands their own. 
This is the ideal state; than which there never can be a truer or better--a
state, whether inhabited by Gods or sons of Gods, which will make the
dwellers therein blessed.  Here is the pattern on which we must ever fix
our eyes; but we are now concerned with another, which comes next to it,
and we will afterwards proceed to a third.

Inasmuch as our citizens are not fitted either by nature or education to
receive the saying, Friends have all things in common, let them retain
their houses and private property, but use them in the service of their
country, who is their God and parent, and of the Gods and demigods of the
land.  Their first care should be to preserve the number of their lots. 
This may be secured in the following manner:  when the possessor of a lot
dies, he shall leave his lot to his best-beloved child, who will become the
heir of all duties and interests, and will minister to the Gods and to the
family, to the living and to the dead.  Of the remaining children, the
females must be given in marriage according to the law to be hereafter
enacted; the males may be assigned to citizens who have no children of
their own.  How to equalize families and allotments will be one of the
chief cares of the guardians of the laws.  When parents have too many
children they may give to those who have none, or couples may abstain from
having children, or, if there is a want of offspring, special care may be
taken to obtain them; or if the number of citizens becomes excessive, we
may send away the surplus to found a colony.  If, on the other hand, a war
or plague diminishes the number of inhabitants, new citizens must be
introduced; and these ought not, if possible, to be men of low birth or
inferior training; but even God, it is said, cannot always fight against
necessity.

Wherefore we will thus address our citizens:--Good friends, honour order
and equality, and above all the number 5040.  Secondly, respect the
original division of the lots, which must not be infringed by buying and
selling, for the law says that the land which a man has is sacred and is
given to him by God.  And priests and priestesses will offer frequent
sacrifices and pray that he who alienates either house or lot may receive
the punishment which he deserves, and their prayers shall be inscribed on
tablets of cypress-wood for the instruction of posterity.  The guardians
will keep a vigilant watch over the citizens, and they will punish those
who disobey God and the law.

To appreciate the benefit of such an institution a man requires to be well
educated; for he certainly will not make a fortune in our state, in which
all illiberal occupations are forbidden to freemen.  The law also provides
that no private person shall have gold or silver, except a little coin for
daily use, which will not pass current in other countries.  The state must
also possess a common Hellenic currency, but this is only to be used in
defraying the expenses of expeditions, or of embassies, or while a man is
on foreign travels; but in the latter case he must deliver up what is over,
when he comes back, to the treasury in return for an equal amount of local
currency, on pain of losing the sum in question; and he who does not inform
against an offender is to be mulcted in a like sum.  No money is to be
given or taken as a dowry, or to be lent on interest.  The law will not
protect a man in recovering either interest or principal.  All these
regulations imply that the aim of the legislator is not to make the city as
rich or as mighty as possible, but the best and happiest.  Now men can
hardly be at the same time very virtuous and very rich.  And why?  Because
he who makes twice as much and saves twice as much as he ought, receiving
where he ought not and not spending where he ought, will be at least twice
as rich as he who makes money where he ought, and spends where he ought. 
On the other hand, an utterly bad man is generally profligate and poor,
while he who acquires honestly, and spends what he acquires on noble
objects, can hardly be very rich.  A very rich man is therefore not a good
man, and therefore not a happy one.  But the object of our laws is to make
the citizens as friendly and happy as possible, which they cannot be if
they are always at law and injuring each other in the pursuit of gain.  And
therefore we say that there is to be no silver or gold in the state, nor
usury, nor the rearing of the meaner kinds of live-stock, but only
agriculture, and only so much of this as will not lead men to neglect that
for the sake of which money is made, first the soul and afterwards the
body; neither of which are good for much without music and gymnastic. 
Money is to be held in honour last or third; the highest interests being
those of the soul, and in the second class are to be ranked those of the
body.  This is the true order of legislation, which would be inverted by
placing health before temperance, and wealth before health.

It might be well if every man could come to the colony having equal
property; but equality is impossible, and therefore we must avoid causes of
offence by having property valued and by equalizing taxation.  To this end,
let us make four classes in which the citizens may be placed according to
the measure of their original property, and the changes of their fortune. 
The greatest of evils is revolution; and this, as the law will say, is
caused by extremes of poverty or wealth.  The limit of poverty shall be the
lot, which must not be diminished, and may be increased fivefold, but not
more.  He who exceeds the limit must give up the excess to the state; but
if he does not, and is informed against, the surplus shall be divided
between the informer and the Gods, and he shall pay a sum equal to the
surplus out of his own property.  All property other than the lot must be
inscribed in a register, so that any disputes which arise may be easily
determined.

The city shall be placed in a suitable situation, as nearly as possible in
the centre of the country, and shall be divided into twelve wards.  First,
we will erect an acropolis, encircled by a wall, within which shall be
placed the temples of Hestia, and Zeus, and Athene.  From this shall be
drawn lines dividing the city, and also the country, into twelve sections,
and the country shall be subdivided into 5040 lots.  Each lot shall contain
two parts, one at a distance, the other near the city; and the distance of
one part shall be compensated by the nearness of the other, the badness and
goodness by the greater or less size.  Twelve lots will be assigned to
twelve Gods, and they will give their names to the tribes.  The divisions
of the city shall correspond to those of the country; and every man shall
have two habitations, one near the centre of the country, the other at the
extremity.

The objection will naturally arise, that all the advantages of which we
have been speaking will never concur.  The citizens will not tolerate a
settlement in which they are deprived of gold and silver, and have the
number of their families regulated, and the sites of their houses fixed by
law.  It will be said that our city is a mere image of wax.  And the
legislator will answer:  'I know it, but I maintain that we ought to set
forth an ideal which is as perfect as possible.  If difficulties arise in
the execution of the plan, we must avoid them and carry out the remainder. 
But the legislator must first be allowed to complete his idea without
interruption.'

The number twelve, which we have chosen for the number of division, must
run through all parts of the state,--phratries, villages, ranks of
soldiers, coins, and measures wet and dry, which are all to be made
commensurable with one another.  There is no meanness in requiring that the
smallest vessels should have a common measure; for the divisions of number
are useful in measuring height and depth, as well as sounds and motions,
upwards or downwards, or round and round.  The legislator should impress on
his citizens the value of arithmetic.  No instrument of education has so
much power; nothing more tends to sharpen and inspire the dull intellect. 
But the legislator must be careful to instil a noble and generous spirit
into the students, or they will tend to become cunning rather than wise. 
This may be proved by the example of the Egyptians and Phoenicians, who,
notwithstanding their knowledge of arithmetic, are degraded in their
general character; whether this defect in them is due to some natural cause
or to a bad legislator.  For it is clear that there are great differences
in the power of regions to produce good men:  heat and cold, and water and
food, have great effects both on body and soul; and those spots are
peculiarly fortunate in which the air is holy, and the Gods are pleased to
dwell.  To all this the legislator must attend, so far as in him lies.

BOOK VI.  And now we are about to consider (1) the appointment of
magistrates; (2) the laws which they will have to administer must be
determined.  I may observe by the way that laws, however good, are useless
and even injurious unless the magistrates are capable of executing them. 
And therefore (1) the intended rulers of our imaginary state should be
tested from their youth upwards until the time of their election; and (2)
those who are to elect them ought to be trained in habits of law, that they
may form a right judgment of good and bad men.  But uneducated colonists,
who are unacquainted with each other, will not be likely to choose well. 
What, then, shall we do?  I will tell you:  The colony will have to be
intrusted to the ten commissioners, of whom you are one, and I will help
you and them, which is my reason for inventing this romance.  And I cannot
bear that the tale should go wandering about the world without a head,--it
will be such an ugly monster.  'Very good.'  Yes; and I will be as good as
my word, if God be gracious and old age permit.  But let us not forget what
a courageously mad creation this our city is.  'What makes you say so?' 
Why, surely our courage is shown in imagining that the new colonists will
quietly receive our laws?  For no man likes to receive laws when they are
first imposed:  could we only wait until those who had been educated under
them were grown up, and of an age to vote in the public elections, there
would be far greater reason to expect permanence in our institutions. 
'Very true.'  The Cnosian founders should take the utmost pains in the
matter of the colony, and in the election of the higher officers,
particularly of the guardians of the law.  The latter should be appointed
in this way:  The Cnosians, who take the lead in the colony, together with
the colonists, will choose thirty-seven persons, of whom nineteen will be
colonists, and the remaining eighteen Cnosians--you must be one of the
eighteen yourself, and become a citizen of the new state.  'Why do not you
and Megillus join us?'  Athens is proud, and Sparta too; and they are both
a long way off.  But let me proceed with my scheme.  When the state is
permanently established, the mode of election will be as follows:  All who
are serving, or have served, in the army will be electors; and the election
will be held in the most sacred of the temples.  The voter will place on
the altar a tablet, inscribing thereupon the name of the candidate whom he
prefers, and of his father, tribe, and ward, writing at the side of them
his own name in like manner; and he may take away any tablet which does not
appear written to his mind, and place it in the Agora for thirty days.  The
300 who obtain the greatest number of votes will be publicly announced, and
out of them there will be a second election of 100; and out of the 100 a
third and final election of thirty-seven, accompanied by the solemnity of
the electors passing through victims.  But then who is to arrange all this? 
There is a common saying, that the beginning is half the whole; and I
should say a good deal more than half.  'Most true.'  The only way of
making a beginning is from the parent city; and though in after ages the
tie may be broken, and quarrels may arise between them, yet in early days
the child naturally looks to the mother for care and education.  And, as I
said before, the Cnosians ought to take an interest in the colony, and
select 100 elders of their own citizens, to whom shall be added 100 of the
colonists, to arrange and supervise the first elections and scrutinies; and
when the colony has been started, the Cnosians may return home and leave
the colonists to themselves.

The thirty-seven magistrates who have been elected in the manner described,
shall have the following duties:  first, they shall be guardians of the
law; secondly, of the registers of property in the four classes--not
including the one, two, three, four minae, which are allowed as a surplus.
He who is found to possess what is not entered in the registers, in
addition to the confiscation of such property shall be proceeded against by
law, and if he be cast he shall lose his share in the public property and
in distributions of money; and his sentence shall be inscribed in some
public place.  The guardians are to continue in office twenty years only,
and to commence holding office at fifty years, or if elected at sixty they
are not to remain after seventy.

Generals have now to be elected, and commanders of horse and brigadiers of
foot.  The generals shall be natives of the city, proposed by the guardians
of the law, and elected by those who are or have been of the age for
military service.  Any one may challenge the person nominated and start
another candidate, whom he affirms upon oath to be better qualified.  The
three who obtain the greatest number of votes shall be elected.  The
generals thus elected shall propose the taxiarchs or brigadiers, and the
challenge may be made, and the voting shall take place, in the same manner
as before.  The elective assembly will be presided over in the first
instance, and until the prytanes and council come into being, by the
guardians of the law in some holy place; and they shall divide the citizens
into three divisions,--hoplites, cavalry, and the rest of the army--placing
each of them by itself.  All are to vote for generals and cavalry officers. 
The brigadiers are to be voted for only by the hoplites.  Next, the cavalry
are to choose phylarchs for the generals; but captains of archers and other
irregular troops are to be appointed by the generals themselves.  The
cavalry-officers shall be proposed and voted upon by the same persons who
vote for the generals.  The two who have the greatest number of votes shall
be leaders of all the horse.  Disputes about the voting may be raised once
or twice, but, if a third time, the presiding officers shall decide.

The council shall consist of 360, who may be conveniently divided into four
sections, making ninety councillors of each class.  In the first place, all
the citizens shall select candidates from the first class; and they shall
be compelled to vote under pain of a fine.  This shall be the business of
the first day.  On the second day a similar selection shall be made from
the second class under the same conditions.  On the third day, candidates
shall be selected from the third class; but the compulsion to vote shall
only extend to the voters of the first three classes.  On the fourth day,
members of the council shall be selected from the fourth class; they shall
be selected by all, but the compulsion to vote shall only extend to the
second class, who, if they do not vote, shall pay a fine of triple the
amount which was exacted at first, and to the first class, who shall pay a
quadruple fine.  On the fifth day, the names shall be exhibited, and out of
them shall be chosen by all the citizens 180 of each class:  these are
severally to be reduced by lot to ninety, and 90 x 4 will form the council
for the year.

The mode of election which has been described is a mean between monarchy
and democracy, and such a mean should ever be observed in the state.  For
servants and masters cannot be friends, and, although equality makes
friendship, we must remember that there are two sorts of equality.  One of
them is the rule of number and measure; but there is also a higher
equality, which is the judgment of Zeus.  Of this he grants but little to
mortal men; yet that little is the source of the greatest good to cities
and individuals.  It is proportioned to the nature of each man; it gives
more to the better and less to the inferior, and is the true political
justice; to this we in our state desire to look, as every legislator
should, not to the interests either of tyrants or mobs.  But justice cannot
always be strictly enforced, and then equity and mercy have to be
substituted:  and for a similar reason, when true justice will not be
endured, we must have recourse to the rougher justice of the lot, which God
must be entreated to guide.

These are the principal means of preserving the state, but perpetual care
will also be required.  When a ship is sailing on the sea, vigilance must
not be relaxed night or day; and the vessel of state is tossing in a
political sea, and therefore watch must continually succeed watch, and
rulers must join hands with rulers.  A small body will best perform this
duty, and therefore the greater part of the 360 senators may be permitted
to go and manage their own affairs, but a twelfth portion must be set aside
in each month for the administration of the state.  Their business will be
to receive information and answer embassies; also they must endeavour to
prevent or heal internal disorders; and with this object they must have the
control of all assemblies of the citizens.

Besides the council, there must be wardens of the city and of the agora,
who will superintend houses, ways, harbours, markets, and fountains, in the
city and the suburbs, and prevent any injury being done to them by man or
beast.  The temples, also, will require priests and priestesses.  Those who
hold the priestly office by hereditary tenure shall not be disturbed; but
as there will probably be few or none such in a new colony, priests and
priestesses shall be appointed for the Gods who have no servants.  Some of
these officers shall be elected by vote, some by lot; and all classes shall
mingle in a friendly manner at the elections.  The appointment of priests
should be left to God,--that is, to the lot; but the person elected must
prove that he is himself sound in body and of legitimate birth, and that
his family has been free from homicide or any other stain of impurity. 
Priests and priestesses are to be not less than sixty years of age, and
shall hold office for a year only.  The laws which are to regulate matters
of religion shall be brought from Delphi, and interpreters appointed to
superintend their execution.  These shall be elected in the following
manner:--The twelve tribes shall be formed into three bodies of four, each
of which shall select four candidates, and this shall be done three times: 
of each twelve thus selected the three who receive the largest number of
votes, nine in all, after undergoing a scrutiny shall go to Delphi, in
order that the God may elect one out of each triad.  They shall be
appointed for life; and when any of them dies, another shall be elected by
the four tribes who made the original appointment.  There shall also be
treasurers of the temples; three for the greater temples, two for the
lesser, and one for those of least importance.

The defence of the city should be committed to the generals and other
officers of the army, and to the wardens of the city and agora.  The
defence of the country shall be on this wise:--The twelve tribes shall
allot among themselves annually the twelve divisions of the country, and
each tribe shall appoint five wardens and commanders of the watch.  The
five wardens in each division shall choose out of their own tribe twelve
guards, who are to be between twenty-five and thirty years of age.  Both
the wardens and the guards are to serve two years; and they shall make a
round of the divisions, staying a month in each.  They shall go from West
to East during the first year, and back from East to West during the
second.  Thus they will gain a perfect knowledge of the country at every
season of the year.

While on service, their first duty will be to see that the country is well
protected by means of fortifications and entrenchments; they will use the
beasts of burden and the labourers whom they find on the spot, taking care
however not to interfere with the regular course of agriculture.  But while
they thus render the country as inaccessible as possible to enemies, they
will also make it as accessible as possible to friends by constructing and
maintaining good roads.  They will restrain and preserve the rain which
comes down from heaven, making the barren places fertile, and the wet
places dry.  They will ornament the fountains with plantations and
buildings, and provide water for irrigation at all seasons of the year. 
They will lead the streams to the temples and groves of the Gods; and in
such spots the youth shall make gymnasia for themselves, and warm baths for
the aged; there the rustic worn with toil will receive a kindly welcome,
and be far better treated than at the hands of an unskilful doctor.

These works will be both useful and ornamental; but the sixty wardens must
not fail to give serious attention to other duties.  For they must watch
over the districts assigned to them, and also act as judges.  In small
matters the five commanders shall decide:  in greater matters up to three
minae, the five commanders and the twelve guards.  Like all other judges,
except those who have the final decision, they shall be liable to give an
account.  If the wardens impose unjust tasks on the villagers, or take by
force their crops or implements, or yield to flattery or bribes in deciding
suits, let them be publicly dishonoured.  In regard to any other wrong-
doing, if the question be of a mina, let the neighbours decide; but if the
accused person will not submit, trusting that his monthly removals will
enable him to escape payment, and also in suits about a larger amount, the
injured party may have recourse to the common court; in the former case, if
successful, he may exact a double penalty.

The wardens and guards, while on their two years' service, shall live and
eat together, and the guard who is absent from the daily meals without
permission or sleeps out at night, shall be regarded as a deserter, and may
be punished by any one who meets him.  If any of the commanders is guilty
of such an irregularity, the whole sixty shall have him punished; and he of
them who screens him shall suffer a still heavier penalty than the offender
himself.  Now by service a man learns to rule; and he should pride himself
upon serving well the laws and the Gods all his life, and upon having
served ancient and honourable men in his youth.  The twelve and the five
should be their own servants, and use the labour of the villagers only for
the good of the public.  Let them search the country through, and acquire a
perfect knowledge of every locality; with this view, hunting and field
sports should be encouraged.

Next we have to speak of the elections of the wardens of the agora and of
the city.  The wardens of the city shall be three in number, and they shall
have the care of the streets, roads, buildings, and also of the water-
supply.  They shall be chosen out of the highest class, and when the number
of candidates has been reduced to six who have the greatest number of
votes, three out of the six shall be taken by lot, and, after a scrutiny,
shall be admitted to their office.  The wardens of the agora shall be five
in number--ten are to be first elected, and every one shall vote for all
the vacant places; the ten shall be afterwards reduced to five by lot, as
in the former election.  The first and second class shall be compelled to
go to the assembly, but not the third and fourth, unless they are specially
summoned.  The wardens of the agora shall have the care of the temples and
fountains which are in the agora, and shall punish those who injure them by
stripes and bonds, if they be slaves or strangers; and by fines, if they be
citizens.  And the wardens of the city shall have a similar power of
inflicting punishment and fines in their own department.

In the next place, there must be directors of music and gymnastic; one
class of them superintending gymnasia and schools, and the attendance and
lodging of the boys and girls--the other having to do with contests of
music and gymnastic.  In musical contests there shall be one kind of judges
of solo singing or playing, who will judge of rhapsodists, flute-players,
harp-players and the like, and another of choruses.  There shall be
choruses of men and boys and maidens--one director will be enough to
introduce them all, and he should not be less than forty years of age;
secondly, of solos also there shall be one director, aged not less than
thirty years; he will introduce the competitors and give judgment upon
them.  The director of the choruses is to be elected in an assembly at
which all who take an interest in music are compelled to attend, and no one
else.  Candidates must only be proposed for their fitness, and opposed on
the ground of unfitness.  Ten are to be elected by vote, and the one of
these on whom the lot falls shall be director for a year.  Next shall be
elected out of the second and third classes the judges of gymnastic
contests, who are to be three in number, and are to be tested, after being
chosen by lot out of twenty who have been elected by the three highest
classes--these being compelled to attend at the election.

One minister remains, who will have the general superintendence of
education.  He must be not less than fifty years old, and be himself the
father of children born in wedlock.  His office must be regarded by all as
the highest in the state.  For the right growth of the first shoot in
plants and animals is the chief cause of matured perfection.  Man is
supposed to be a tame animal, but he becomes either the gentlest or the
fiercest of creatures, accordingly as he is well or ill educated. 
Wherefore he who is elected to preside over education should be the best
man possible.  He shall hold office for five years, and shall be elected
out of the guardians of the law, by the votes of the other magistrates with
the exception of the senate and prytanes; and the election shall be held by
ballot in the temple of Apollo.

When a magistrate dies before his term of office has expired, another shall
be elected in his place; and, if the guardian of an orphan dies, the
relations shall appoint another within ten days, or be fined a drachma a
day for neglect.

The city which has no courts of law will soon cease to be a city; and a
judge who sits in silence and leaves the enquiry to the litigants, as in
arbitrations, is not a good judge.  A few judges are better than many, but
the few must be good.  The matter in dispute should be clearly elicited;
time and examination will find out the truth.  Causes should first be tried
before a court of neighbours:  if the decision is unsatisfactory, let them
be referred to a higher court; or, if necessary, to a higher still, of
which the decision shall be final.

Every magistrate is a judge, and every judge is a magistrate, on the day on
which he is deciding the suit.  This will therefore be an appropriate place
to speak of judges and their functions.  The supreme tribunal will be that
on which the litigants agree; and let there be two other tribunals, one for
public and the other for private causes.  The high court of appeal shall be
composed as follows:--All the officers of state shall meet on the last day
but one of the year in some temple, and choose for a judge the best man out
of every magistracy:  and those who are elected, after they have undergone
a scrutiny, shall be judges of appeal.  They shall give their decisions
openly, in the presence of the magistrates who have elected them; and the
public may attend.  If anybody charges one of them with having
intentionally decided wrong, he shall lay his accusation before the
guardians of the law, and if the judge be found guilty he shall pay damages
to the extent of half the injury, unless the guardians of the law deem that
he deserves a severer punishment, in which case the judges shall assess the
penalty.

As the whole people are injured by offences against the state, they should
share in the trial of them.  Such causes should originate with the people
and be decided by them:  the enquiry shall take place before any three of
the highest magistrates upon whom the defendant and plaintiff can agree. 
Also in private suits all should judge as far as possible, and therefore
there should be a court of law in every ward; for he who has no share in
the administration of justice, believes that he has no share in the state. 
The judges in these courts shall be elected by lot and give their decision
at once.  The final judgment in all cases shall rest with the court of
appeal.  And so, having done with the appointment of courts and the
election of officers, we will now make our laws.

'Your way of proceeding, Stranger, is admirable.'

Then so far our old man's game of play has gone off well.

'Say, rather, our serious and noble pursuit.'

Perhaps; but let me ask you whether you have ever observed the manner in
which painters put in and rub out colour:  yet their endless labour will
last but a short time, unless they leave behind them some successor who
will restore the picture and remove its defects.  'Certainly.'  And have we
not a similar object at the present moment?  We are old ourselves, and
therefore we must leave our work of legislation to be improved and
perfected by the next generation; not only making laws for our guardians,
but making them lawgivers.  'We must at least do our best.'  Let us address
them as follows.  Beloved saviours of the laws, we give you an outline of
legislation which you must fill up, according to a rule which we will
prescribe for you.  Megillus and Cleinias and I are agreed, and we hope
that you will agree with us in thinking, that the whole energies of a man
should be devoted to the attainment of manly virtue, whether this is to be
gained by study, or habit, or desire, or opinion.  And rather than accept
institutions which tend to degrade and enslave him, he should fly his
country and endure any hardship.  These are our principles, and we would
ask you to judge of our laws, and praise or blame them, accordingly as they
are or are not capable of improving our citizens.

And first of laws concerning religion.  We have already said that the
number 5040 has many convenient divisions:  and we took a twelfth part of
this (420), which is itself divisible by twelve, for the number of the
tribe.  Every divisor is a gift of God, and corresponds to the months of
the year and to the revolution of the universe.  All cities have a number,
but none is more fortunate than our own, which can be divided by all
numbers up to 12, with the exception of 11, and even by 11, if two families
are deducted.  And now let us divide the state, assigning to each division
some God or demigod, who shall have altars raised to them, and sacrifices
offered twice a month; and assemblies shall be held in their honour, twelve
for the tribes, and twelve for the city, corresponding to their divisions.
The object of them will be first to promote religion, secondly to encourage
friendship and intercourse between families; for families must be
acquainted before they marry into one another, or great mistakes will
occur.  At these festivals there shall be innocent dances of young men and
maidens, who may have the opportunity of seeing one another in modest
undress.  To the details of all this the masters of choruses and the
guardians will attend, embodying in laws the results of their experience;
and, after ten years, making the laws permanent, with the consent of the
legislator, if he be alive, or, if he be not alive, of the guardians of the
law, who shall perfect them and settle them once for all.  At least, if any
further changes are required, the magistrates must take the whole people
into counsel, and obtain the sanction of all the oracles.

Whenever any one who is between the ages of twenty-five and thirty-five
wants to marry, let him do so; but first let him hear the strain which we
will address to him:--

My son, you ought to marry, but not in order to gain wealth or to avoid
poverty; neither should you, as men are wont to do, choose a wife who is
like yourself in property and character.  You ought to consult the
interests of the state rather than your own pleasure; for by equal
marriages a society becomes unequal.  And yet to enact a law that the rich
and mighty shall not marry the rich and mighty, that the quick shall be
united to the slow, and the slow to the quick, will arouse anger in some
persons and laughter in others; for they do not understand that opposite
elements ought to be mingled in the state, as wine should be mingled with
water.  The object at which we aim must therefore be left to the influence
of public opinion.  And do not forget our former precept, that every one
should seek to attain immortality and raise up a fair posterity to serve
God.--Let this be the prelude of the law about the duty of marriage.  But
if a man will not listen, and at thirty-five years of age is still
unmarried, he shall pay an annual fine:  if he be of the first class, 100
drachmas; if of the second, 70; if of the third, 60; and if of the fourth,
30.  This fine shall be sacred to Here; and if he refuse to pay, a tenfold
penalty shall be exacted by the treasurer of Here, who shall be responsible
for the payment.  Further, the unmarried man shall receive no honour or
obedience from the young, and he shall not retain the right of punishing
others.  A man is neither to give nor receive a dowry beyond a certain
fixed sum; in our state, for his consolation, if he be poor, let him know
that he need neither receive nor give one, for every citizen is provided
with the necessaries of life.  Again, if the woman is not rich, her husband
will not be her humble servant.  He who disobeys this law shall pay a fine
according to his class, which shall be exacted by the treasurers of Here
and Zeus.

The betrothal of the parties shall be made by the next of kin, or if there
are none, by the guardians.  The offerings and ceremonies of marriage shall
be determined by the interpreters of sacred rites.  Let the wedding party
be moderate; five male and five female friends, and a like number of
kinsmen, will be enough.  The expense should not exceed, for the first
class, a mina; and for the second, half a mina; and should be in like
proportion for the other classes.  Extravagance is to be regarded as
vulgarity and ignorance of nuptial proprieties.  Much wine is only to be
drunk at the festivals of Dionysus, and certainly not on the occasion of a
marriage.  The bride and bridegroom, who are taking a great step in life,
ought to have all their wits about them; they should be especially careful
of the night on which God may give them increase, and which this will be
none can say.  Their bodies and souls should be in the most temperate
condition; they should abstain from all that partakes of the nature of
disease or vice, which will otherwise become hereditary.  There is an
original divinity in man which preserves all things, if used with proper
respect.  He who marries should make one of the two houses on the lot the
nest and nursery of his young; he should leave his father and mother, and
then his affection for them will be only increased by absence.  He will go
forth as to a colony, and will there rear up his offspring, handing on the
torch of life to another generation.

About property in general there is little difficulty, with the exception of
property in slaves, which is an institution of a very doubtful character. 
The slavery of the Helots is approved by some and condemned by others; and
there is some doubt even about the slavery of the Mariandynians at Heraclea
and of the Thessalian Penestae.  This makes us ask, What shall we do about
slaves?  To which every one would agree in replying,--Let us have the best
and most attached whom we can get.  All of us have heard stories of slaves
who have been better to their masters than sons or brethren.  Yet there is
an opposite doctrine, that slaves are never to be trusted; as Homer says,
'Slavery takes away half a man's understanding.'  And different persons
treat them in different ways:  there are some who never trust them, and
beat them like dogs, until they make them many times more slavish than they
were before; and others pursue the opposite plan.  Man is a troublesome
animal, as has been often shown, Megillus, notably in the revolts of the
Messenians; and great mischiefs have arisen in countries where there are
large bodies of slaves of one nationality.  Two rules may be given for
their management:  first that they should not, if possible, be of the same
country or have a common language; and secondly, that they should be
treated by their master with more justice even than equals, out of regard
to himself quite as much as to them.  For he who is righteous in the
treatment of his slaves, or of any inferiors, will sow in them the seed of
virtue.  Masters should never jest with their slaves:  this, which is a
common but foolish practice, increases the difficulty and painfulness of
managing them.

Next as to habitations.  These ought to have been spoken of before; for no
man can marry a wife, and have slaves, who has not a house for them to live
in.  Let us supply the omission.  The temples should be placed round the
Agora, and the city built in a circle on the heights.  Near the temples,
which are holy places and the habitations of the Gods, should be buildings
for the magistrates, and the courts of law, including those in which
capital offences are to be tried.  As to walls, Megillus, I agree with
Sparta that they should sleep in the earth; 'cold steel is the best wall,'
as the poet finely says.  Besides, how absurd to be sending out our youth
to fortify and guard the borders of our country, and then to build a city
wall, which is very unhealthy, and is apt to make people fancy that they
may run there and rest in idleness, not knowing that true repose comes from
labour, and that idleness is only a renewal of trouble.  If, however, there
must be a wall, the private houses had better be so arranged as to form one
wall; this will have an agreeable aspect, and the building will be safer
and more defensible.  These objects should be attended to at the foundation
of the city.  The wardens of the city must see that they are carried out;
and they must also enforce cleanliness, and preserve the public buildings
from encroachments.  Moreover, they must take care to let the rain flow off
easily, and must regulate other matters concerning the general
administration of the city.  If any further enactments prove to be
necessary, the guardians of the law must supply them.

And now, having provided buildings, and having married our citizens, we
will proceed to speak of their mode of life.  In a well-constituted state,
individuals cannot be allowed to live as they please.  Why do I say this? 
Because I am going to enact that the bridegroom shall not absent himself
from the common meals.  They were instituted originally on the occasion of
some war, and, though deemed singular when first founded, they have tended
greatly to the security of states.  There was a difficulty in introducing
them, but there is no difficulty in them now.  There is, however, another
institution about which I would speak, if I dared.  I may preface my
proposal by remarking that disorder in a state is the source of all evil,
and order of all good.  Now in Sparta and Crete there are common meals for
men, and this, as I was saying, is a divine and natural institution.  But
the women are left to themselves; they live in dark places, and, being
weaker, and therefore wickeder, than men, they are at the bottom of a good
deal more than half the evil of states.  This must be corrected, and the
institution of common meals extended to both sexes.  But, in the present
unfortunate state of opinion, who would dare to establish them?  And still
more, who can compel women to eat and drink in public?  They will defy the
legislator to drag them out of their holes.  And in any other state such a
proposal would be drowned in clamour, but in our own I think that I can
show the attempt to be just and reasonable.  'There is nothing which we
should like to hear better.'  Listen, then; having plenty of time, we will
go back to the beginning of things, which is an old subject with us. 
'Right.'  Either the race of mankind never had a beginning and will never
have an end, or the time which has elapsed since man first came into being
is all but infinite.  'No doubt.'  And in this infinity of time there have
been changes of every kind, both in the order of the seasons and in the
government of states and in the customs of eating and drinking.  Vines and
olives were at length discovered, and the blessings of Demeter and
Persephone, of which one Triptolemus is said to have been the minister;
before his time the animals had been eating one another.  And there are
nations in which mankind still sacrifice their fellow-men, and other
nations in which they lead a kind of Orphic existence, and will not
sacrifice animals, or so much as taste of a cow--they offer fruits or cakes
moistened with honey.  Perhaps you will ask me what is the bearing of these
remarks?  'We would gladly hear.'  I will endeavour to explain their drift.
I see that the virtue of human life depends on the due regulation of three
wants or desires.  The first is the desire of meat, the second of drink;
these begin with birth, and make us disobedient to any voice other than
that of pleasure.  The third and fiercest and greatest need is felt latest;
this is love, which is a madness setting men's whole nature on fire.  These
three disorders of mankind we must endeavour to restrain by three mighty
influences--fear, and law, and reason, which, with the aid of the Muses and
the Gods of contests, may extinguish our lusts.

But to return.  After marriage let us proceed to the generation of
children, and then to their nurture and education--thus gradually
approaching the subject of syssitia.  There are, however, some other points
which are suggested by the three words--meat, drink, love.  'Proceed,'  the
bride and bridegroom ought to set their mind on having a brave offspring. 
Now a man only succeeds when he takes pains; wherefore the bridegroom ought
to take special care of the bride, and the bride of the bridegroom, at the
time when their children are about to be born.  And let there be a
committee of matrons who shall meet every day at the temple of Eilithyia at
a time fixed by the magistrates, and inform against any man or woman who
does not observe the laws of married life.  The time of begetting children
and the supervision of the parents shall last for ten years only; if at the
expiration of this period they have no children, they may part, with the
consent of their relatives and the official matrons, and with a due regard
to the interests of either; if a dispute arise, ten of the guardians of the
law shall be chosen as arbiters.  The matrons shall also have power to
enter the houses of the young people, if necessary, and to advise and
threaten them.  If their efforts fail, let them go to the guardians of the
law; and if they too fail, the offender, whether man or woman, shall be
forbidden to be present at all family ceremonies.  If when the time for
begetting children has ceased, either husband or wife have connexion with
others who are of an age to beget children, they shall be liable to the
same penalties as those who are still having a family.  But when both
parties have ceased to beget children there shall be no penalties.  If men
and women live soberly, the enactments of law may be left to slumber;
punishment is necessary only when there is great disorder of manners.

The first year of children's lives is to be registered in their ancestral
temples; the name of the archon of the year is to be inscribed on a whited
wall in every phratry, and the names of the living members of the phratry
close to them, to be erased at their decease.  The proper time of marriage
for a woman shall be from sixteen years to twenty; for a man, from thirty
to thirty-five (compare Republic).  The age of holding office for a woman
is to be forty, for a man thirty years.  The time for military service for
a man is to be from twenty years to sixty; for a woman, from the time that
she has ceased to bear children until fifty.

BOOK VII.  Now that we have married our citizens and brought their children
into the world, we have to find nurture and education for them.  This is a
matter of precept rather than of law, and cannot be precisely regulated by
the legislator.  For minute regulations are apt to be transgressed, and
frequent transgressions impair the habit of obedience to the laws.  I speak
darkly, but I will also try to exhibit my wares in the light of day.  Am I
not right in saying that a good education tends to the improvement of body
and mind?  'Certainly.'  And the body is fairest which grows up straight
and well-formed from the time of birth.  'Very true.'  And we observe that
the first shoot of every living thing is the greatest; many even contend
that man is not at twenty-five twice the height that he was at five. 
'True.'  And growth without exercise of the limbs is the source of endless
evils in the body.  'Yes.'  The body should have the most exercise when
growing most.  'What, the bodies of young infants?'  Nay, the bodies of
unborn infants.  I should like to explain to you this singular kind of
gymnastics.  The Athenians are fond of cock-fighting, and the people who
keep cocks carry them about in their hands or under their arms, and take
long walks, to improve, not their own health, but the health of the birds.
Here is a proof of the usefulness of motion, whether of rocking, swinging,
riding, or tossing upon the wave; for all these kinds of motion greatly
increase strength and the powers of digestion.  Hence we infer that our
women, when they are with child, should walk about and fashion the embryo;
and the children, when born, should be carried by strong nurses,--there
must be more than one of them,--and should not be suffered to walk until
they are three years old.  Shall we impose penalties for the neglect of
these rules?  The greatest penalty, that is, ridicule, and the difficulty
of making the nurses do as we bid them, will be incurred by ourselves. 
'Then why speak of such matters?'  In the hope that heads of families may
learn that the due regulation of them is the foundation of law and order in
the state.

And now, leaving the body, let us proceed to the soul; but we must first
repeat that perpetual motion by night and by day is good for the young
creature.  This is proved by the Corybantian cure of motion, and by the
practice of nurses who rock children in their arms, lapping them at the
same time in sweet strains.  And the reason of this is obvious.  The
affections, both of the Bacchantes and of the children, arise from fear,
and this fear is occasioned by something wrong which is going on within
them.  Now a violent external commotion tends to calm the violent internal
one; it quiets the palpitation of the heart, giving to the children sleep,
and bringing back the Bacchantes to their right minds by the help of dances
and acceptable sacrifices.  But if fear has such power, will not a child
who is always in a state of terror grow up timid and cowardly, whereas if
he learns from the first to resist fear he will develop a habit of courage?
'Very true.'  And we may say that the use of motion will inspire the souls
of children with cheerfulness and therefore with courage.  'Of course.' 
Softness enervates and irritates the temper of the young, and violence
renders them mean and misanthropical.  'But how is the state to educate
them when they are as yet unable to understand the meaning of words?'  Why,
surely they roar and cry, like the young of any other animal, and the nurse
knows the meaning of these intimations of the child's likes or dislikes,
and the occasions which call them forth.  About three years is passed by
children in a state of imperfect articulation, which is quite long enough
time to make them either good- or ill-tempered.  And, therefore, during
these first three years, the infant should be as free as possible from fear
and pain.  'Yes, and he should have as much pleasure as possible.'  There,
I think, you are wrong; for the influence of pleasure in the beginning of
education is fatal.  A man should neither pursue pleasure nor wholly avoid
pain.  He should embrace the mean, and cultivate that state of calm which
mankind, taught by some inspiration, attribute to God; and he who would be
like God should neither be too fond of pleasure himself, nor should he
permit any other to be thus given; above all, not the infant, whose
character is just in the making.  It may sound ridiculous, but I affirm
that a woman in her pregnancy should be carefully tended, and kept from
excessive pleasures and pains.

'I quite agree with you about the duty of avoiding extremes and following
the mean.'

Let us consider a further point.  The matters which are now in question are
generally called customs rather than laws; and we have already made the
reflection that, though they are not, properly speaking, laws, yet neither
can they be neglected.  For they fill up the interstices of law, and are
the props and ligatures on which the strength of the whole building
depends.  Laws without customs never last; and we must not wonder if habit
and custom sometimes lengthen out our laws.  'Very true.'  Up to their
third year, then, the life of children may be regulated by customs such as
we have described.  From three to six their minds have to be amused; but
they must not be allowed to become self-willed and spoilt.  If punishment
is necessary, the same rule will hold as in the case of slaves; they must
neither be punished in hot blood nor ruined by indulgence.  The children of
that age will have their own modes of amusing themselves; they should be
brought for their play to the village temples, and placed under the care of
nurses, who will be responsible to twelve matrons annually chosen by the
women who have authority over marriage.  These shall be appointed, one out
of each tribe, and their duty shall be to keep order at the meetings: 
slaves who break the rules laid down by them, they shall punish by the help
of some of the public slaves; but citizens who dispute their authority
shall be brought before the magistrates.  After six years of age there
shall be a separation of the sexes; the boys will go to learn riding and
the use of arms, and the girls may, if they please, also learn.  Here I
note a practical error in early training.  Mothers and nurses foolishly
believe that the left hand is by nature different from the right, whereas
the left leg and foot are acknowledged to be the same as the right.  But
the truth is that nature made all things to balance, and the power of using
the left hand, which is of little importance in the case of the plectrum of
the lyre, may make a great difference in the art of the warrior, who should
be a skilled gymnast and able to fight and balance himself in any position.
If a man were a Briareus, he should use all his hundred hands at once; at
any rate, let everybody employ the two which they have.  To these matters
the magistrates, male and female, should attend; the women superintending
the nursing and amusement of the children, and the men superintending their
education, that all of them, boys and girls alike, may be sound, wind and
limb, and not spoil the gifts of nature by bad habits.

Education has two branches--gymnastic, which is concerned with the body;
and music, which improves the soul.  And gymnastic has two parts, dancing
and wrestling.  Of dancing one kind imitates musical recitation and aims at
stateliness and freedom; another kind is concerned with the training of the
body, and produces health, agility, and beauty.  There is no military use
in the complex systems of wrestling which pass under the names of Antaeus
and Cercyon, or in the tricks of boxing, which are attributed to Amycus and
Epeius; but good wrestling and the habit of extricating the neck, hands,
and sides, should be diligently learnt and taught.  In our dances
imitations of war should be practised, as in the dances of the Curetes in
Crete and of the Dioscuri at Sparta, or as in the dances in complete armour
which were taught us Athenians by the goddess Athene.  Youths who are not
yet of an age to go to war should make religious processions armed and on
horseback; and they should also engage in military games and contests. 
These exercises will be equally useful in peace and war, and will benefit
both states and families.

Next follows music, to which we will once more return; and here I shall
venture to repeat my old paradox, that amusements have great influence on
laws.  He who has been taught to play at the same games and with the same
playthings will be content with the same laws.  There is no greater evil in
a state than the spirit of innovation.  In the case of the seasons and
winds, in the management of our bodies and in the habits of our minds,
change is a dangerous thing.  And in everything but what is bad the same
rule holds.  We all venerate and acquiesce in the laws to which we are
accustomed; and if they have continued during long periods of time, and
there is no remembrance of their ever having been otherwise, people are
absolutely afraid to change them.  Now how can we create this quality of
immobility in the laws?  I say, by not allowing innovations in the games
and plays of children.  The children who are always having new plays, when
grown up will be always having new laws.  Changes in mere fashions are not
serious evils, but changes in our estimate of men's characters are most
serious; and rhythms and music are representations of characters, and
therefore we must avoid novelties in dance and song.  For securing
permanence no better method can be imagined than that of the Egyptians. 
'What is their method?'  They make a calendar for the year, arranging on
what days the festivals of the various Gods shall be celebrated, and for
each festival they consecrate an appropriate hymn and dance.  In our state
a similar arrangement shall in the first instance be framed by certain
individuals, and afterwards solemnly ratified by all the citizens.  He who
introduces other hymns or dances shall be excluded by the priests and
priestesses and the guardians of the law; and if he refuses to submit, he
may be prosecuted for impiety.  But we must not be too ready to speak about
such great matters.  Even a young man, when he hears something
unaccustomed, stands and looks this way and that, like a traveller at a
place where three ways meet; and at our age a man ought to be very sure of
his ground in so singular an argument.  'Very true.'  Then, leaving the
subject for further examination at some future time, let us proceed with
our laws about education, for in this manner we may probably throw light
upon our present difficulty.  'Let us do as you say.'  The ancients used
the term nomoi to signify harmonious strains, and perhaps they fancied that
there was a connexion between the songs and laws of a country.  And we say
--Whosoever shall transgress the strains by law established is a
transgressor of the laws, and shall be punished by the guardians of the law
and by the priests and priestesses.  'Very good.'  How can we legislate
about these consecrated strains without incurring ridicule?  Moulds or
types must be first framed, and one of the types shall be--Abstinence from
evil words at sacrifices.  When a son or brother blasphemes at a sacrifice
there is a sound of ill-omen heard in the family; and many a chorus stands
by the altar uttering inauspicious words, and he is crowned victor who
excites the hearers most with lamentations.  Such lamentations should be
reserved for evil days, and should be uttered only by hired mourners; and
let the singers not wear circlets or ornaments of gold.  To avoid every
evil word, then, shall be our first type.  'Agreed.'  Our second law or
type shall be, that prayers ever accompany sacrifices; and our third, that,
inasmuch as all prayers are requests, they shall be only for good; this the
poets must be made to understand.  'Certainly.'  Have we not already
decided that no gold or silver Plutus shall be allowed in our city?  And
did not this show that we were dissatisfied with the poets?  And may we not
fear that, if they are allowed to utter injudicious prayers, they will
bring the greatest misfortunes on the state?  And we must therefore make a
law that the poet is not to contradict the laws or ideas of the state; nor
is he to show his poems to any private persons until they have first
received the imprimatur of the director of education.  A fourth musical law
will be to the effect that hymns and praises shall be offered to Gods, and
to heroes and demigods.  Still another law will permit eulogies of eminent
citizens, whether men or women, but only after their death.  As to songs
and dances, we will enact as follows:--There shall be a selection made of
the best ancient musical compositions and dances; these shall be chosen by
judges, who ought not to be less than fifty years of age.  They will accept
some, and reject or amend others, for which purpose they will call, if
necessary, the poets themselves into council.  The severe and orderly music
is the style in which to educate children, who, if they are accustomed to
this, will deem the opposite kind to be illiberal, but if they are
accustomed to the other, will count this to be cold and unpleasing. 
'True.'  Further, a distinction should be made between the melodies of men
and women.  Nature herself teaches that the grand or manly style should be
assigned to men, and to women the moderate and temperate.  So much for the
subjects of education.  But to whom are they to be taught, and when?  I
must try, like the shipwright, who lays down the keel of a vessel, to build
a secure foundation for the vessel of the soul in her voyage through life. 
Human affairs are hardly serious, and yet a sad necessity compels us to be
serious about them.  Let us, therefore, do our best to bring the matter to
a conclusion.  'Very good.'  I say then, that God is the object of a man's
most serious endeavours.  But man is created to be the plaything of the
Gods; and therefore the aim of every one should be to pass through life,
not in grim earnest, but playing at the noblest of pastimes, in another
spirit from that which now prevails.  For the common opinion is, that work
is for the sake of play, war of peace; whereas in war there is neither
amusement nor instruction worth speaking of.  The life of peace is that
which men should chiefly desire to lengthen out and improve.  They should
live sacrificing, singing, and dancing, with the view of propitiating Gods
and heroes.  I have already told you the types of song and dance which they
should follow:  and

'Some things,' as the poet well says, 'you will devise for yourself--
others, God will suggest to you.'

These words of his may be applied to our pupils.  They will partly teach
themselves, and partly will be taught by God, the art of propitiating Him;
for they are His puppets, and have only a small portion in truth.  'You
have a poor opinion of man.'  No wonder, when I compare him with God; but,
if you are offended, I will place him a little higher.

Next follow the building for gymnasia and schools; these will be in the
midst of the city, and outside will be riding-schools and archery-grounds.
In all of them there ought to be instructors of the young, drawn from
foreign parts by pay, and they will teach them music and war.  Education
shall be compulsory; the children must attend school, whether their parents
like it or not; for they belong to the state more than to their parents. 
And I say further, without hesitation, that the same education in riding
and gymnastic shall be given both to men and women.  The ancient tradition
about the Amazons confirms my view, and at the present day there are
myriads of women, called Sauromatides, dwelling near the Pontus, who
practise the art of riding as well as archery and the use of arms.  But if
I am right, nothing can be more foolish than our modern fashion of training
men and women differently, whereby the power the city is reduced to a half. 
For reflect--if women are not to have the education of men, some other must
be found for them, and what other can we propose?  Shall they, like the
women of Thrace, tend cattle and till the ground; or, like our own, spin
and weave, and take care of the house? or shall they follow the Spartan
custom, which is between the two?--there the maidens share in gymnastic
exercises and in music; and the grown women, no longer engaged in spinning,
weave the web of life, although they are not skilled in archery, like the
Amazons, nor can they imitate our warrior goddess and carry shield or
spear, even in the extremity of their country's need.  Compared with our
women, the Sauromatides are like men.  But your legislators, Megillus, as I
maintain, only half did their work; they took care of the men, and left the
women to take care of themselves.

'Shall we suffer the Stranger, Cleinias, to run down Sparta in this way?'

'Why, yes; for we cannot withdraw the liberty which we have already
conceded to him.'

What will be the manner of life of men in moderate circumstances, freed
from the toils of agriculture and business, and having common tables for
themselves and their families which are under the inspection of
magistrates, male and female?  Are men who have these institutions only to
eat and fatten like beasts?  If they do, how can they escape the fate of a
fatted beast, which is to be torn in pieces by some other beast more
valiant than himself?  True, theirs is not the perfect way of life, for
they have not all things in common; but the second best way of life also
confers great blessings.  Even those who live in the second state have a
work to do twice as great as the work of any Pythian or Olympic victor; for
their labour is for the body only, but ours both for body and soul.  And
this higher work ought to be pursued night and day to the exclusion of
every other.  The magistrates who keep the city should be wakeful, and the
master of the household should be up early and before all his servants; and
the mistress, too, should awaken her handmaidens, and not be awakened by
them.  Much sleep is not required either for our souls or bodies.  When a
man is asleep, he is no better than if he were dead; and he who loves life
and wisdom will take no more sleep than is necessary for health. 
Magistrates who are wide awake at night are terrible to the bad; but they
are honoured by the good, and are useful to themselves and the state.

When the morning dawns, let the boy go to school.  As the sheep need the
shepherd, so the boy needs a master; for he is at once the most cunning and
the most insubordinate of creatures.  Let him be taken away from mothers
and nurses, and tamed with bit and bridle, being treated as a freeman in
that he learns and is taught, but as a slave in that he may be chastised by
all other freemen; and the freeman who neglects to chastise him shall be
disgraced.  All these matters will be under the supervision of the Director
of Education.

Him we will address as follows:  We have spoken to you, O illustrious
teacher of youth, of the song, the time, and the dance, and of martial
strains; but of the learning of letters and of prose writings, and of
music, and of the use of calculation for military and domestic purposes we
have not spoken, nor yet of the higher use of numbers in reckoning divine
things--such as the revolutions of the stars, or the arrangements of days,
months, and years, of which the true calculation is necessary in order that
seasons and festivals may proceed in regular course, and arouse and enliven
the city, rendering to the Gods their due, and making men know them better. 
There are, we say, many things about which we have not as yet instructed
you--and first, as to reading and music:  Shall the pupil be a perfect
scholar and musician, or not even enter on these studies?  He should
certainly enter on both:--to letters he will apply himself from the age of
ten to thirteen, and at thirteen he will begin to handle the lyre, and
continue to learn music until he is sixteen; no shorter and no longer time
will be allowed, however fond he or his parents may be of the pursuit. The
study of letters he should carry to the extent of simple reading and
writing, but he need not care for calligraphy and tachygraphy, if his
natural gifts do not enable him to acquire them in the three years.  And
here arises a question as to the learning of compositions when
unaccompanied with music, I mean, prose compositions.  They are a dangerous
species of literature.  Speak then, O guardians of the law, and tell us
what we shall do about them.  'You seem to be in a difficulty.'  Yes; it is
difficult to go against the opinion of all the world.  'But have we not
often already done so?'  Very true.  And you imply that the road which we
are taking, though disagreeable to many, is approved by those whose
judgment is most worth having.  'Certainly.'  Then I would first observe
that we have many poets, comic as well as tragic, with whose compositions,
as people say, youth are to be imbued and saturated.  Some would have them
learn by heart entire poets; others prefer extracts.  Now I believe, and
the general opinion is, that some of the things which they learn are good,
and some bad.  'Then how shall we reject some and select others?'  A happy
thought occurs to me; this long discourse of ours is a sample of what we
want, and is moreover an inspired work and a kind of poem.  I am naturally
pleased in reflecting upon all our words, which appear to me to be just the
thing for a young man to hear and learn.  I would venture, then, to offer
to the Director of Education this treatise of laws as a pattern for his
guidance; and in case he should find any similar compositions, written or
oral, I would have him carefully preserve them, and commit them in the
first place to the teachers who are willing to learn them (he should turn
off the teacher who refuses), and let them communicate the lesson to the
young.

I have said enough to the teacher of letters; and now we will proceed to
the teacher of the lyre.  He must be reminded of the advice which we gave
to the sexagenarian minstrels; like them he should be quick to perceive the
rhythms suited to the expression of virtue, and to reject the opposite. 
With a view to the attainment of this object, the pupil and his instructor
are to use the lyre because its notes are pure; the voice and string should
coincide note for note:  nor should there be complex harmonies and
contrasts of intervals, or variations of times or rhythms.  Three years'
study is not long enough to give a knowledge of these intricacies; and our
pupils will have many things of more importance to learn.  The tunes and
hymns which are to be consecrated for each festival have been already
determined by us.

Having given these instructions to the Director of Music, let us now
proceed to dancing and gymnastic, which must also be taught to boys and
girls by masters and mistresses.  Our minister of education will have a
great deal to do; and being an old man, how will he get through so much
work?  There is no difficulty;--the law will provide him with assistants,
male and female; and he will consider how important his office is, and how
great the responsibility of choosing them.  For if education prospers, the
vessel of state sails merrily along; or if education fails, the
consequences are not even to be mentioned.  Of dancing and gymnastics
something has been said already.  We include under the latter military
exercises, the various uses of arms, all that relates to horsemanship, and
military evolutions and tactics.  There should be public teachers of both
arts, paid by the state, and women as well as men should be trained in
them.  The maidens should learn the armed dance, and the grown-up women be
practised in drill and the use of arms, if only in case of extremity, when
the men are gone out to battle, and they are left to guard their families. 
Birds and beasts defend their young, but women instead of fighting run to
the altars, thus degrading man below the level of the animals.  'Such a
lack of education, Stranger, is both unseemly and dangerous.'

Wrestling is to be pursued as a military exercise, but the meaning of this,
and the nature of the art, can only be explained when action is combined
with words.  Next follows dancing, which is of two kinds; imitative, first,
of the serious and beautiful; and, secondly, of the ludicrous and
grotesque.  The first kind may be further divided into the dance of war and
the dance of peace.  The former is called the Pyrrhic; in this the
movements of attack and defence are imitated in a direct and manly style,
which indicates strength and sufficiency of body and mind.  The latter of
the two, the dance of peace, is suitable to orderly and law-abiding men. 
These must be distinguished from the Bacchic dances which imitate drunken
revelry, and also from the dances by which purifications are effected and
mysteries celebrated.  Such dances cannot be characterized either as
warlike or peaceful, and are unsuited to a civilized state.  Now the dances
of peace are of two classes:--the first of them is the more violent, being
an expression of joy and triumph after toil and danger; the other is more
tranquil, symbolizing the continuance and preservation of good.  In
speaking or singing we naturally move our bodies, and as we have more or
less courage or self-control we become less or more violent and excited. 
Thus from the imitation of words in gestures the art of dancing arises. 
Now one man imitates in an orderly, another in a disorderly manner:  and so
the peaceful kinds of dance have been appropriately called Emmeleiai, or
dances of order, as the warlike have been called Pyrrhic.  In the latter a
man imitates all sorts of blows and the hurling of weapons and the avoiding
of them; in the former he learns to bear himself gracefully and like a
gentleman.  The types of these dances are to be fixed by the legislator,
and when the guardians of the law have assigned them to the several
festivals, and consecrated them in due order, no further change shall be
allowed.

Thus much of the dances which are appropriate to fair forms and noble
souls.  Comedy, which is the opposite of them, remains to be considered. 
For the serious implies the ludicrous, and opposites cannot be understood
without opposites.  But a man of repute will desire to avoid doing what is
ludicrous.  He should leave such performances to slaves,--they are not fit
for freemen; and there should be some element of novelty in them. 
Concerning tragedy, let our law be as follows:  When the inspired poet
comes to us with a request to be admitted into our state, we will reply in
courteous words--We also are tragedians and your rivals; and the drama
which we enact is the best and noblest, being the imitation of the truest
and noblest life, with a view to which our state is ordered.  And we cannot
allow you to pitch your stage in the agora, and make your voices to be
heard above ours, or suffer you to address our women and children and the
common people on opposite principles to our own.  Come then, ye children of
the Lydian Muse, and present yourselves first to the magistrates, and if
they decide that your hymns are as good or better than ours, you shall have
your chorus; but if not, not.

There remain three kinds of knowledge which should be learnt by freemen--
arithmetic, geometry of surfaces and of solids, and thirdly, astronomy. 
Few need make an accurate study of such sciences; and of special students
we will speak at another time.  But most persons must be content with the
study of them which is absolutely necessary, and may be said to be a
necessity of that nature against which God himself is unable to contend. 
'What are these divine necessities of knowledge?'  Necessities of a
knowledge without which neither gods, nor demigods, can govern mankind. 
And far is he from being a divine man who cannot distinguish one, two, odd
and even; who cannot number day and night, and is ignorant of the
revolutions of the sun and stars; for to every higher knowledge a knowledge
of number is necessary--a fool may see this; how much, is a matter
requiring more careful consideration.  'Very true.'  But the legislator
cannot enter into such details, and therefore we must defer the more
careful consideration of these matters to another occasion.  'You seem to
fear our habitual want of training in these subjects.'  Still more do I
fear the danger of bad training, which is often worse than none at all. 
'Very true.'  I think that a gentleman and a freeman may be expected to
know as much as an Egyptian child.  In Egypt, arithmetic is taught to
children in their sports by a distribution of apples or garlands among a
greater or less number of people; or a calculation is made of the various
combinations which are possible among a set of boxers or wrestlers; or they
distribute cups among the children, sometimes of gold, brass, and silver
intermingled, sometimes of one metal only.  The knowledge of arithmetic
which is thus acquired is a great help, either to the general or to the
manager of a household; wherever measure is employed, men are more wide-
awake in their dealings, and they get rid of their ridiculous ignorance. 
'What do you mean?'  I have observed this ignorance among my countrymen--
they are like pigs--and I am heartily ashamed both on my own behalf and on
that of all the Hellenes.  'In what respect?'  Let me ask you a question. 
You know that there are such things as length, breadth, and depth?  'Yes.' 
And the Hellenes imagine that they are commensurable (1) with themselves,
and (2) with each other; whereas they are only commensurable with
themselves.  But if this is true, then we are in an unfortunate case, and
may well say to our compatriots that not to possess necessary knowledge is
a disgrace, though to possess such knowledge is nothing very grand. 
'Certainly.'  The discussion of arithmetical problems is a much better
amusement for old men than their favourite game of draughts.  'True.' 
Mathematics, then, will be one of the subjects in which youth should be
trained.  They may be regarded as an amusement, as well as a useful and
innocent branch of knowledge;--I think that we may include them
provisionally.  'Yes; that will be the way.'  The next question is, whether
astronomy shall be made a part of education.  About the stars there is a
strange notion prevalent.  Men often suppose that it is impious to enquire
into the nature of God and the world, whereas the very reverse is the
truth.  'How do you mean?'  What I am going to say may seem absurd and at
variance with the usual language of age, and yet if true and advantageous
to the state, and pleasing to God, ought not to be withheld.  'Let us
hear.'  My dear friend, how falsely do we and all the Hellenes speak about
the sun and moon!  'In what respect?'  We are always saying that they and
certain of the other stars do not keep the same path, and we term them
planets.  'Yes; and I have seen the morning and evening stars go all manner
of ways, and the sun and moon doing what we know that they always do.  But
I wish that you would explain your meaning further.'  You will easily
understand what I have had no difficulty in understanding myself, though we
are both of us past the time of learning.  'True; but what is this
marvellous knowledge which youth are to acquire, and of which we are
ignorant?'  Men say that the sun, moon, and stars are planets or wanderers;
but this is the reverse of the fact.  Each of them moves in one orbit only,
which is circular, and not in many; nor is the swiftest of them the
slowest, as appears to human eyes.  What an insult should we offer to
Olympian runners if we were to put the first last and the last first!  And
if that is a ridiculous error in speaking of men, how much more in speaking
of the Gods?  They cannot be pleased at our telling falsehoods about them. 
'They cannot.'  Then people should at least learn so much about them as
will enable them to avoid impiety.

Enough of education.  Hunting and similar pursuits now claim our attention.
These require for their regulation that mixture of law and admonition of
which we have often spoken; e.g., in what we were saying about the nurture
of young children.  And therefore the whole duty of the citizen will not
consist in mere obedience to the laws; he must regard not only the
enactments but also the precepts of the legislator.  I will illustrate my
meaning by an example.  Of hunting there are many kinds--hunting of fish
and fowl, man and beast, enemies and friends; and the legislator can
neither omit to speak about these things, nor make penal ordinances about
them all.  'What is he to do then?'  He will praise and blame hunting,
having in view the discipline and exercise of youth.  And the young man
will listen obediently and will regard his praises and censures; neither
pleasure nor pain should hinder him.  The legislator will express himself
in the form of a pious wish for the welfare of the young:--O my friends, he
will say, may you never be induced to hunt for fish in the waters, either
by day or night; or for men, whether by sea or land.  Never let the wish to
steal enter into your minds; neither be ye fowlers, which is not an
occupation for gentlemen.  As to land animals, the legislator will
discourage hunting by night, and also the use of nets and snares by day;
for these are indolent and unmanly methods.  The only mode of hunting which
he can praise is with horses and dogs, running, shooting, striking at close
quarters.  Enough of the prelude:  the law shall be as follows:--

Let no one hinder the holy order of huntsmen; but let the nightly hunters
who lay snares and nets be everywhere prohibited.  Let the fowler confine
himself to waste places and to the mountains.  The fisherman is also
permitted to exercise his calling, except in harbours and sacred streams,
marshes and lakes; in all other places he may fish, provided he does not
make use of poisonous mixtures.

BOOK VIII.  Next, with the help of the Delphian Oracle, we will appoint
festivals and sacrifices.  There shall be 365 of them, one for every day in
the year; and one magistrate, at least, shall offer sacrifice daily
according to rites prescribed by a convocation of priests and interpreters,
who shall co-operate with the guardians of the law, and supply what the
legislator has omitted.  Moreover there shall be twelve festivals to the
twelve Gods after whom the twelve tribes are named:  these shall be
celebrated every month with appropriate musical and gymnastic contests. 
There shall also be festivals for women, to be distinguished from the men's
festivals.  Nor shall the Gods below be forgotten, but they must be
separated from the Gods above--Pluto shall have his own in the twelfth
month.  He is not the enemy, but the friend of man, who releases the soul
from the body, which is at least as good a work as to unite them.  Further,
those who have to regulate these matters should consider that our state has
leisure and abundance, and wishing to be happy, like an individual, should
lead a good life; for he who leads such a life neither does nor suffers
injury, of which the first is very easy, and the second very difficult of
attainment, and is only to be acquired by perfect virtue.  A good city has
peace, but the evil city is full of wars within and without.  To guard
against the danger of external enemies the citizens should practise war at
least one day in every month; they should go out en masse, including their
wives and children, or in divisions, as the magistrates determine, and have
mimic contests, imitating in a lively manner real battles; they should also
have prizes and encomiums of valour, both for the victors in these
contests, and for the victors in the battle of life.  The poet who
celebrates the victors should be fifty years old at least, and himself a
man who has done great deeds.  Of such an one the poems may be sung, even
though he is not the best of poets.  To the director of education and the
guardians of the law shall be committed the judgment, and no song, however
sweet, which has not been licensed by them shall be recited.  These
regulations about poetry, and about military expeditions, apply equally to
men and to women.

The legislator may be conceived to make the following address to himself:--
With what object am I training my citizens?  Are they not strivers for
mastery in the greatest of combats?  Certainly, will be the reply.  And if
they were boxers or wrestlers, would they think of entering the lists
without many days' practice?  Would they not as far as possible imitate all
the circumstances of the contest; and if they had no one to box with, would
they not practise on a lifeless image, heedless of the laughter of the
spectators?  And shall our soldiers go out to fight for life and kindred
and property unprepared, because sham fights are thought to be ridiculous?
Will not the legislator require that his citizens shall practise war daily,
performing lesser exercises without arms, while the combatants on a greater
scale will carry arms, and take up positions, and lie in ambuscade?  And
let their combats be not without danger, that opportunity may be given for
distinction, and the brave man and the coward may receive their meed of
honour or disgrace.  If occasionally a man is killed, there is no great
harm done--there are others as good as he is who will replace him; and the
state can better afford to lose a few of her citizens than to lose the only
means of testing them.

'We agree, Stranger, that such warlike exercises are necessary.'  But why
are they so rarely practised?  Or rather, do we not all know the reasons? 
One of them (1) is the inordinate love of wealth.  This absorbs the soul of
a man, and leaves him no time for any other pursuit.  Knowledge is valued
by him only as it tends to the attainment of wealth.  All is lost in the
desire of heaping up gold and silver; anybody is ready to do anything,
right or wrong, for the sake of eating and drinking, and the indulgence of
his animal passions.  'Most true.'  This is one of the causes which
prevents a man being a good soldier, or anything else which is good; it
converts the temperate and orderly into shopkeepers or servants, and the
brave into burglars or pirates.  Many of these latter are men of ability,
and are greatly to be pitied, because their souls are hungering and
thirsting all their lives long.  The bad forms of government (2) are
another reason--democracy, oligarchy, tyranny, which, as I was saying, are
not states, but states of discord, in which the rulers are afraid of their
subjects, and therefore do not like them to become rich, or noble, or
valiant.  Now our state will escape both these causes of evil; the society
is perfectly free, and has plenty of leisure, and is not allowed by the
laws to be absorbed in the pursuit of wealth; hence we have an excellent
field for a perfect education, and for the introduction of martial
pastimes.  Let us proceed to describe the character of these pastimes.  All
gymnastic exercises in our state must have a military character; no other
will be allowed.  Activity and quickness are most useful in war; and yet
these qualities do not attain their greatest efficiency unless the
competitors are armed.  The runner should enter the lists in armour, and in
the races which our heralds proclaim, no prize is to be given except to
armed warriors.  Let there be six courses--first, the stadium; secondly,
the diaulos or double course; thirdly, the horse course; fourthly, the long
course; fifthly, races (1) between heavy-armed soldiers who shall pass over
sixty stadia and finish at a temple of Ares, and (2) between still more
heavily-armed competitors who run over smoother ground; sixthly, a race for
archers, who shall run over hill and dale a distance of a hundred stadia,
and their goal shall be a temple of Apollo and Artemis.  There shall be
three contests of each kind--one for boys, another for youths, a third for
men; the course for the boys we will fix at half, and that for the youths
at two-thirds of the entire length.  Women shall join in the races:  young
girls who are not grown up shall run naked; but after thirteen they shall
be suitably dressed; from thirteen to eighteen they shall be obliged to
share in these contests, and from eighteen to twenty they may if they
please and if they are unmarried.  As to trials of strength, single combats
in armour, or battles between two and two, or of any number up to ten,
shall take the place of wrestling and the heavy exercises.  And there must
be umpires, as there are now in wrestling, to determine what is a fair hit
and who is conqueror.  Instead of the pancratium, let there be contests in
which the combatants carry bows and wear light shields and hurl javelins
and throw stones.  The next provision of the law will relate to horses,
which, as we are in Crete, need be rarely used by us, and chariots never;
our horse-racing prizes will only be given to single horses, whether colts,
half-grown, or full-grown.  Their riders are to wear armour, and there
shall be a competition between mounted archers.  Women, if they have a
mind, may join in the exercises of men.

But enough of gymnastics, and nearly enough of music.  All musical contests
will take place at festivals, whether every third or every fifth year,
which are to be fixed by the guardians of the law, the judges of the games,
and the director of education, who for this purpose shall become
legislators and arrange times and conditions.  The principles on which such
contests are to be ordered have been often repeated by the first
legislator; no more need be said of them, nor are the details of them
important.  But there is another subject of the highest importance, which,
if possible, should be determined by the laws, not of man, but of God; or,
if a direct revelation is impossible, there is need of some bold man who,
alone against the world, will speak plainly of the corruption of human
nature, and go to war with the passions of mankind.  'We do not understand
you.'  I will try to make my meaning plainer.  In speaking of education, I
seemed to see young men and maidens in friendly intercourse with one
another; and there arose in my mind a natural fear about a state, in which
the young of either sex are well nurtured, and have little to do, and
occupy themselves chiefly with festivals and dances.  How can they be saved
from those passions which reason forbids them to indulge, and which are the
ruin of so many?  The prohibition of wealth, and the influence of
education, and the all-seeing eye of the ruler, will alike help to promote
temperance; but they will not wholly extirpate the unnatural loves which
have been the destruction of states; and against this evil what remedy can
be devised?  Lacedaemon and Crete give no assistance here; on the subject
of love, as I may whisper in your ear, they are against us.  Suppose a
person were to urge that you ought to restore the natural use which existed
before the days of Laius; he would be quite right, but he would not be
supported by public opinion in either of your states.  Or try the matter by
the test which we apply to all laws,--who will say that the permission of
such things tends to virtue?  Will he who is seduced learn the habit of
courage; or will the seducer acquire temperance?  And will any legislator
be found to make such actions legal?

But to judge of this matter truly, we must understand the nature of love
and friendship, which may take very different forms.  For we speak of
friendship, first, when there is some similarity or equality of virtue;
secondly, when there is some want; and either of these, when in excess, is
termed love.  The first kind is gentle and sociable; the second is fierce
and unmanageable; and there is also a third kind, which is akin to both,
and is under the dominion of opposite principles.  The one is of the body,
and has no regard for the character of the beloved; but he who is under the
influence of the other disregards the body, and is a looker rather than a
lover, and desires only with his soul to be knit to the soul of his friend;
while the intermediate sort is both of the body and of the soul.  Here are
three kinds of love:  ought the legislator to prohibit all of them equally,
or to allow the virtuous love to remain?  'The latter, clearly.'  I
expected to gain your approval; but I will reserve the task of convincing
our friend Cleinias for another occasion.  'Very good.'  To make right laws
on this subject is in one point of view easy, and in another most
difficult; for we know that in some cases most men abstain willingly from
intercourse with the fair.  The unwritten law which prohibits members of
the same family from such intercourse is strictly obeyed, and no thought of
anything else ever enters into the minds of men in general.  A little word
puts out the fire of their lusts.  'What is it?'  The declaration that such
things are hateful to the Gods, and most abominable and unholy.  The reason
is that everywhere, in jest and earnest alike, this is the doctrine which
is repeated to all from their earliest youth.  They see on the stage that
an Oedipus or a Thyestes or a Macareus, when undeceived, are ready to kill
themselves.  There is an undoubted power in public opinion when no breath
is heard adverse to the law; and the legislator who would enslave these
enslaving passions must consecrate such a public opinion all through the
city.  'Good:  but how can you create it?'  A fair objection; but I
promised to try and find some means of restraining loves to their natural
objects.  A law which would extirpate unnatural love as effectually as
incest is at present extirpated, would be the source of innumerable
blessings, because it would be in accordance with nature, and would get rid
of excess in eating and drinking and of adulteries and frenzies, making men
love their wives, and having other excellent effects.  I can imagine that
some lusty youth overhears what we are saying, and roars out in abusive
terms that we are legislating for impossibilities.  And so a person might
have said of the syssitia, or common meals; but this is refuted by facts,
although even now they are not extended to women.  'True.'  There is no
impossibility or super-humanity in my proposed law, as I shall endeavour to
prove.  'Do so.'  Will not a man find abstinence more easy when his body is
sound than when he is in ill-condition?  'Yes.'  Have we not heard of Iccus
of Tarentum and other wrestlers who abstained wholly for a time?  Yet they
were infinitely worse educated than our citizens, and far more lusty in
their bodies.  And shall they have abstained for the sake of an athletic
contest, and our citizens be incapable of a similar endurance for the sake
of a much nobler victory,--the victory over pleasure, which is true
happiness?  Will not the fear of impiety enable them to conquer that which
many who were inferior to them have conquered?  'I dare say.'  And
therefore the law must plainly declare that our citizens should not fall
below the other animals, who live all together in flocks, and yet remain
pure and chaste until the time of procreation comes, when they pair, and
are ever after faithful to their compact.  But if the corruption of public
opinion is too great to allow our first law to be carried out, then our
guardians of the law must turn legislators, and try their hand at a second
law.  They must minimize the appetites, diverting the vigour of youth into
other channels, allowing the practice of love in secret, but making
detection shameful.  Three higher principles may be brought to bear on all
these corrupt natures.  'What are they?'  Religion, honour, and the love of
the higher qualities of the soul.  Perhaps this is a dream only, yet it is
the best of dreams; and if not the whole, still, by the grace of God, a
part of what we desire may be realized.  Either men may learn to abstain
wholly from any loves, natural or unnatural, except of their wedded wives;
or, at least, they may give up unnatural loves; or, if detected, they shall
be punished with loss of citizenship, as aliens from the state in their
morals.  'I entirely agree with you,' said Megillus, 'but Cleinias must
speak for himself.'  'I will give my opinion by-and-by.'

We were speaking of the syssitia, which will be a natural institution in a
Cretan colony.  Whether they shall be established after the model of Crete
or Lacedaemon, or shall be different from either, is an unimportant
question which may be determined without difficulty.  We may, therefore,
proceed to speak of the mode of life among our citizens, which will be far
less complex than in other cities; a state which is inland and not maritime
requires only half the number of laws.  There is no trouble about trade and
commerce, and a thousand other things.  The legislator has only to regulate
the affairs of husbandmen and shepherds, which will be easily arranged, now
that the principal questions, such as marriage, education, and government,
have been settled.

Let us begin with husbandry:  First, let there be a law of Zeus against
removing a neighbour's landmark, whether he be a citizen or stranger.  For
this is 'to move the immoveable'; and Zeus, the God of kindred, witnesses
to the wrongs of citizens, and Zeus, the God of strangers, to the wrongs of
strangers.  The offence of removing a boundary shall receive two
punishments--the first will be inflicted by the God himself; the second by
the judges.  In the next place, the differences between neighbours about
encroachments must be guarded against.  He who encroaches shall pay twofold
the amount of the injury; of all such matters the wardens of the country
shall be the judges, in lesser cases the officers, and in greater the whole
number of them belonging to any one division.  Any injury done by cattle,
the decoying of bees, the careless firing of woods, the planting unduly
near a neighbour's ground, shall all be visited with proper damages.  Such
details have been determined by previous legislators, and need not now be
mixed up with greater matters.  Husbandmen have had of old excellent rules
about streams and waters; and we need not 'divert their course.'  Anybody
may take water from a common stream, if he does not thereby cut off a
private spring; he may lead the water in any direction, except through a
house or temple, but he must do no harm beyond the channel.  If land is
without water the occupier shall dig down to the clay, and if at this depth
he find no water, he shall have a right of getting water from his
neighbours for his household; and if their supply is limited, he shall
receive from them a measure of water fixed by the wardens of the country. 
If there be heavy rains, the dweller on the higher ground must not
recklessly suffer the water to flow down upon a neighbour beneath him, nor
must he who lives upon lower ground or dwells in an adjoining house refuse
an outlet.  If the two parties cannot agree, they shall go before the
wardens of the city or country, and if a man refuse to abide by their
decision, he shall pay double the damage which he has caused.

In autumn God gives us two boons--one the joy of Dionysus not to be laid
up--the other to be laid up.  About the fruits of autumn let the law be as
follows:  He who gathers the storing fruits of autumn, whether grapes or
figs, before the time of the vintage, which is the rising of Arcturus,
shall pay fifty drachmas as a fine to Dionysus, if he gathers on his own
ground; if on his neighbour's ground, a mina, and two-thirds of a mina if
on that of any one else.  The grapes or figs not used for storing a man may
gather when he pleases on his own ground, but on that of others he must pay
the penalty of removing what he has not laid down.  If he be a slave who
has gathered, he shall receive a stroke for every grape or fig.  A metic
must purchase the choice fruit; but a stranger may pluck for himself and
his attendant.  This right of hospitality, however, does not extend to
storing grapes.  A slave who eats of the storing grapes or figs shall be
beaten, and the freeman be dismissed with a warning.  Pears, apples,
pomegranates, may be taken secretly, but he who is detected in the act of
taking them shall be lightly beaten off, if he be not more than thirty
years of age.  The stranger and the elder may partake of them, but not
carry any away; the latter, if he does not obey the law, shall fail in the
competition of virtue, if anybody brings up his offence against him.

Water is also in need of protection, being the greatest element of
nutrition, and, unlike the other elements--soil, air, and sun--which
conspire in the growth of plants, easily polluted.  And therefore he who
spoils another's water, whether in springs or reservoirs, either by
trenching, or theft, or by means of poisonous substances, shall pay the
damage and purify the stream.  At the getting-in of the harvest everybody
shall have a right of way over his neighbour's ground, provided he is
careful to do no damage beyond the trespass, or if he himself will gain
three times as much as his neighbour loses.  Of all this the magistrates
are to take cognizance, and they are to assess the damage where the injury
does not exceed three minae; cases of greater damage can be tried only in
the public courts.  A charge against a magistrate is to be referred to the
public courts, and any one who is found guilty of deciding corruptly shall
pay twofold to the aggrieved person.  Matters of detail relating to
punishments and modes of procedure, and summonses, and witnesses to
summonses, do not require the mature wisdom of the aged legislator; the
younger generation may determine them according to their experience; but
when once determined, they shall remain unaltered.

The following are to be the regulations respecting handicrafts:--No
citizen, or servant of a citizen, is to practise them.  For the citizen has
already an art and mystery, which is the care of the state; and no man can
practise two arts, or practise one and superintend another.  No smith
should be a carpenter, and no carpenter, having many slaves who are smiths,
should look after them himself; but let each man practise one art which
shall be his means of livelihood.  The wardens of the city should see to
this, punishing the citizen who offends with temporary deprival of his
rights--the foreigner shall be imprisoned, fined, exiled.  Any disputes
about contracts shall be determined by the wardens of the city up to fifty
drachmae--above that sum by the public courts.  No customs are to be
exacted either on imports or exports.  Nothing unnecessary is to be
imported from abroad, whether for the service of the Gods or for the use of
man--neither purple, nor other dyes, nor frankincense,--and nothing needed
in the country is to be exported.  These things are to be decided on by the
twelve guardians of the law who are next in seniority to the five elders. 
Arms and the materials of war are to be imported and exported only with the
consent of the generals, and then only by the state.  There is to be no
retail trade either in these or any other articles.  For the distribution
of the produce of the country, the Cretan laws afford a rule which may be
usefully followed.  All shall be required to distribute corn, grain,
animals, and other valuable produce, into twelve portions.  Each of these
shall be subdivided into three parts--one for freemen, another for
servants, and the third shall be sold for the supply of artisans,
strangers, and metics.  These portions must be equal whether the produce be
much or little; and the master of a household may distribute the two
portions among his family and his slaves as he pleases--the remainder is to
be measured out to the animals.

Next as to the houses in the country--there shall be twelve villages, one
in the centre of each of the twelve portions; and in every village there
shall be temples and an agora--also shrines for heroes or for any old
Magnesian deities who linger about the place.  In every division there
shall be temples of Hestia, Zeus, and Athene, as well as of the local
deity, surrounded by buildings on eminences, which will be the guard-houses
of the rural police.  The dwellings of the artisans will be thus arranged:
--The artisans shall be formed into thirteen guilds, one of which will be
divided into twelve parts and settled in the city; of the rest there shall
be one in each division of the country.  And the magistrates will fix them
on the spots where they will cause the least inconvenience and be most
serviceable in supplying the wants of the husbandmen.

The care of the agora will fall to the wardens of the agora.  Their first
duty will be the regulation of the temples which surround the market-place;
and their second to see that the markets are orderly and that fair dealing
is observed.  They will also take care that the sales which the citizens
are required to make to strangers are duly executed.  The law shall be,
that on the first day of each month the auctioneers to whom the sale is
entrusted shall offer grain; and at this sale a twelfth part of the whole
shall be exposed, and the foreigner shall supply his wants for a month.  On
the tenth, there shall be a sale of liquids, and on the twenty-third of
animals, skins, woven or woollen stuffs, and other things which husbandmen
have to sell and foreigners want to buy.  None of these commodities, any
more than barley or flour, or any other food, may be retailed by a citizen
to a citizen; but foreigners may sell them to one another in the
foreigners' market.  There must also be butchers who will sell parts of
animals to foreigners and craftsmen, and their servants; and foreigners may
buy firewood wholesale of the commissioners of woods, and may sell retail
to foreigners.  All other goods must be sold in the market, at some place
indicated by the magistrates, and shall be paid for on the spot.  He who
gives credit, and is cheated, will have no redress.  In buying or selling,
any excess or diminution of what the law allows shall be registered.  The
same rule is to be observed about the property of metics.  Anybody who
practises a handicraft may come and remain twenty years from the day on
which he is enrolled; at the expiration of this time he shall take what he
has and depart.  The only condition which is to be imposed upon him as the
tax of his sojourn is good conduct; and he is not to pay any tax for being
allowed to buy or sell.  But if he wants to extend the time of his sojourn,
and has done any service to the state, and he can persuade the council and
assembly to grant his request, he may remain.  The children of metics may
also be metics; and the period of twenty years, during which they are
permitted to sojourn, is to count, in their case, from their fifteenth
year.

No mention occurs in the Laws of the doctrine of Ideas.  The will of God,
the authority of the legislator, and the dignity of the soul, have taken
their place in the mind of Plato.  If we ask what is that truth or
principle which, towards the end of his life, seems to have absorbed him
most, like the idea of good in the Republic, or of beauty in the Symposium,
or of the unity of virtue in the Protagoras, we should answer--The priority
of the soul to the body:  his later system mainly hangs upon this.  In the
Laws, as in the Sophist and Statesman, we pass out of the region of
metaphysical or transcendental ideas into that of psychology.

The opening of the fifth book, though abrupt and unconnected in style, is
one of the most elevated passages in Plato.  The religious feeling which he
seeks to diffuse over the commonest actions of life, the blessedness of
living in the truth, the great mistake of a man living for himself, the
pity as well as anger which should be felt at evil, the kindness due to the
suppliant and the stranger, have the temper of Christian philosophy.  The
remark that elder men, if they want to educate others, should begin by
educating themselves; the necessity of creating a spirit of obedience in
the citizens; the desirableness of limiting property; the importance of
parochial districts, each to be placed under the protection of some God or
demigod, have almost the tone of a modern writer.  In many of his views of
politics, Plato seems to us, like some politicians of our own time, to be
half socialist, half conservative.

In the Laws, we remark a change in the place assigned by him to pleasure
and pain.  There are two ways in which even the ideal systems of morals may
regard them:  either like the Stoics, and other ascetics, we may say that
pleasure must be eradicated; or if this seems unreal to us, we may affirm
that virtue is the true pleasure; and then, as Aristotle says, 'to be
brought up to take pleasure in what we ought, exercises a great and
paramount influence on human life' (Arist. Eth. Nic.).  Or as Plato says in
the Laws, 'A man will recognize the noblest life as having the greatest
pleasure and the least pain, if he have a true taste.'  If we admit that
pleasures differ in kind, the opposition between these two modes of
speaking is rather verbal than real; and in the greater part of the
writings of Plato they alternate with each other.  In the Republic, the
mere suggestion that pleasure may be the chief good, is received by
Socrates with a cry of abhorrence; but in the Philebus, innocent pleasures
vindicate their right to a place in the scale of goods.  In the Protagoras,
speaking in the person of Socrates rather than in his own, Plato admits the
calculation of pleasure to be the true basis of ethics, while in the Phaedo
he indignantly denies that the exchange of one pleasure for another is the
exchange of virtue.  So wide of the mark are they who would attribute to
Plato entire consistency in thoughts or words.

He acknowledges that the second state is inferior to the first--in this, at
any rate, he is consistent; and he still casts longing eyes upon the ideal.
Several features of the first are retained in the second:  the education of
men and women is to be as far as possible the same; they are to have common
meals, though separate, the men by themselves, the women with their
children; and they are both to serve in the army; the citizens, if not
actually communists, are in spirit communistic; they are to be lovers of
equality; only a certain amount of wealth is permitted to them, and their
burdens and also their privileges are to be proportioned to this.  The
constitution in the Laws is a timocracy of wealth, modified by an
aristocracy of merit.  Yet the political philosopher will observe that the
first of these two principles is fixed and permanent, while the latter is
uncertain and dependent on the opinion of the multitude.  Wealth, after
all, plays a great part in the Second Republic of Plato.  Like other
politicians, he deems that a property qualification will contribute
stability to the state.  The four classes are derived from the constitution
of Athens, just as the form of the city, which is clustered around a
citadel set on a hill, is suggested by the Acropolis at Athens.  Plato,
writing under Pythagorean influences, seems really to have supposed that
the well-being of the city depended almost as much on the number 5040 as on
justice and moderation.  But he is not prevented by Pythagoreanism from
observing the effects which climate and soil exercise on the characters of
nations.

He was doubtful in the Republic whether the ideal or communistic state
could be realized, but was at the same time prepared to maintain that
whether it existed or not made no difference to the philosopher, who will
in any case regulate his life by it (Republic).  He has now lost faith in
the practicability of his scheme--he is speaking to 'men, and not to Gods
or sons of Gods' (Laws).  Yet he still maintains it to be the true pattern
of the state, which we must approach as nearly as possible:  as Aristotle
says, 'After having created a more general form of state, he gradually
brings it round to the other' (Pol.).  He does not observe, either here or
in the Republic, that in such a commonwealth there would be little room for
the development of individual character.  In several respects the second
state is an improvement on the first, especially in being based more
distinctly on the dignity of the soul.  The standard of truth, justice,
temperance, is as high as in the Republic;--in one respect higher, for
temperance is now regarded, not as a virtue, but as the condition of all
virtue.  It is finally acknowledged that the virtues are all one and
connected, and that if they are separated, courage is the lowest of them. 
The treatment of moral questions is less speculative but more human.  The
idea of good has disappeared; the excellences of individuals--of him who is
faithful in a civil broil, of the examiner who is incorruptible, are the
patterns to which the lives of the citizens are to conform.  Plato is never
weary of speaking of the honour of the soul, which can only be honoured
truly by being improved.  To make the soul as good as possible, and to
prepare her for communion with the Gods in another world by communion with
divine virtue in this, is the end of life.  If the Republic is far superior
to the Laws in form and style, and perhaps in reach of thought, the Laws
leave on the mind of the modern reader much more strongly the impression of
a struggle against evil, and an enthusiasm for human improvement.  When
Plato says that he must carry out that part of his ideal which is
practicable, he does not appear to have reflected that part of an ideal
cannot be detached from the whole.

The great defect of both his constitutions is the fixedness which he seeks
to impress upon them.  He had seen the Athenian empire, almost within the
limits of his own life, wax and wane, but he never seems to have asked
himself what would happen if, a century from the time at which he was
writing, the Greek character should have as much changed as in the century
which had preceded.  He fails to perceive that the greater part of the
political life of a nation is not that which is given them by their
legislators, but that which they give themselves.  He has never reflected
that without progress there cannot be order, and that mere order can only
be preserved by an unnatural and despotic repression.  The possibility of a
great nation or of an universal empire arising never occurred to him.  He
sees the enfeebled and distracted state of the Hellenic world in his own
later life, and thinks that the remedy is to make the laws unchangeable. 
The same want of insight is apparent in his judgments about art.  He would
like to have the forms of sculpture and of music fixed as in Egypt.  He
does not consider that this would be fatal to the true principles of art,
which, as Socrates had himself taught, was to give life (Xen. Mem.).  We
wonder how, familiar as he was with the statues of Pheidias, he could have
endured the lifeless and half-monstrous works of Egyptian sculpture.  The
'chants of Isis' (Laws), we might think, would have been barbarous in an
Athenian ear. But although he is aware that there are some things which are
not so well among 'the children of the Nile,' he is deeply struck with the
stability of Egyptian institutions.  Both in politics and in art Plato
seems to have seen no way of bringing order out of disorder, except by
taking a step backwards.  Antiquity, compared with the world in which he
lived, had a sacredness and authority for him:  the men of a former age
were supposed by him to have had a sense of reverence which was wanting
among his contemporaries.  He could imagine the early stages of
civilization; he never thought of what the future might bring forth.  His
experience is confined to two or three centuries, to a few Greek states,
and to an uncertain report of Egypt and the East.  There are many ways in
which the limitations of their knowledge affected the genius of the Greeks. 
In criticism they were like children, having an acute vision of things
which were near to them, blind to possibilities which were in the distance.

The colony is to receive from the mother-country her original constitution,
and some of the first guardians of the law.  The guardians of the law are
to be ministers of justice, and the president of education is to take
precedence of them all.  They are to keep the registers of property, to
make regulations for trade, and they are to be superannuated at seventy
years of age.  Several questions of modern politics, such as the limitation
of property, the enforcement of education, the relations of classes, are
anticipated by Plato.  He hopes that in his state will be found neither
poverty nor riches; every man having the necessaries of life, he need not
go fortune-hunting in marriage.  Almost in the spirit of the Gospel he
would say, 'How hardly can a rich man dwell in a perfect state.'  For he
cannot be a good man who is always gaining too much and spending too little
(Laws; compare Arist. Eth. Nic.).  Plato, though he admits wealth as a
political element, would deny that material prosperity can be the
foundation of a really great community.  A man's soul, as he often says, is
more to be esteemed than his body; and his body than external goods.  He
repeats the complaint which has been made in all ages, that the love of
money is the corruption of states.  He has a sympathy with thieves and
burglars, 'many of whom are men of ability and greatly to be pitied,
because their souls are hungering and thirsting all their lives long;' but
he has little sympathy with shopkeepers or retailers, although he makes the
reflection, which sometimes occurs to ourselves, that such occupations, if
they were carried on honestly by the best men and women, would be
delightful and honourable.  For traders and artisans a moderate gain was,
in his opinion, best.  He has never, like modern writers, idealized the
wealth of nations, any more than he has worked out the problems of
political economy, which among the ancients had not yet grown into a
science.  The isolation of Greek states, their constant wars, the want of a
free industrial population, and of the modern methods and instruments of
'credit,' prevented any great extension of commerce among them; and so
hindered them from forming a theory of the laws which regulate the
accumulation and distribution of wealth.

The constitution of the army is aristocratic and also democratic; official
appointment is combined with popular election.  The two principles are
carried out as follows:  The guardians of the law nominate generals out of
whom three are chosen by those who are or have been of the age for military
service; and the generals elected have the nomination of certain of the
inferior officers.  But if either in the case of generals or of the
inferior officers any one is ready to swear that he knows of a better man
than those nominated, he may put the claims of his candidate to the vote of
the whole army, or of the division of the service which he will, if
elected, command.  There is a general assembly, but its functions, except
at elections, are hardly noticed.  In the election of the Boule, Plato
again attempts to mix aristocracy and democracy.  This is effected, first
as in the Servian constitution, by balancing wealth and numbers; for it
cannot be supposed that those who possessed a higher qualification were
equal in number with those who had a lower, and yet they have an equal
number of representatives.  In the second place, all classes are compelled
to vote in the election of senators from the first and second class; but
the fourth class is not compelled to elect from the third, nor the third
and fourth from the fourth.  Thirdly, out of the 180 persons who are thus
chosen from each of the four classes, 720 in all, 360 are to be taken by
lot; these form the council for the year.

These political adjustments of Plato's will be criticised by the practical
statesman as being for the most part fanciful and ineffectual.  He will
observe, first of all, that the only real check on democracy is the
division into classes.  The second of the three proposals, though
ingenious, and receiving some light from the apathy to politics which is
often shown by the higher classes in a democracy, would have little power
in times of excitement and peril, when the precaution was most needed.  At
such political crises, all the lower classes would vote equally with the
higher.  The subtraction of half the persons chosen at the first election
by the chances of the lot would not raise the character of the senators,
and is open to the objection of uncertainty, which necessarily attends this
and similar schemes of double representative government.  Nor can the
voters be expected to retain the continuous political interest required for
carrying out such a proposal as Plato's.  Who could select 180 persons of
each class, fitted to be senators?  And whoever were chosen by the voter in
the first instance, his wishes might be neutralized by the action of the
lot.  Yet the scheme of Plato is not really so extravagant as the actual
constitution of Athens, in which all the senators appear to have been
elected by lot (apo kuamou bouleutai), at least, after the revolution made
by Cleisthenes; for the constitution of the senate which was established by
Solon probably had some aristocratic features, though their precise nature
is unknown to us.  The ancients knew that election by lot was the most
democratic of all modes of appointment, seeming to say in the objectionable
sense, that 'one man is as good as another.'  Plato, who is desirous of
mingling different elements, makes a partial use of the lot, which he
applies to candidates already elected by vote.  He attempts also to devise
a system of checks and balances such as he supposes to have been intended
by the ancient legislators.  We are disposed to say to him, as he himself
says in a remarkable passage, that 'no man ever legislates, but accidents
of all sorts, which legislate for us in all sorts of ways.  The violence of
war and the hard necessity of poverty are constantly overturning
governments and changing laws.'  And yet, as he adds, the true legislator
is still required:  he must co-operate with circumstances.  Many things
which are ascribed to human foresight are the result of chance.  Ancient,
and in a less degree modern political constitutions, are never consistent
with themselves, because they are never framed on a single design, but are
added to from time to time as new elements arise and gain the preponderance
in the state.  We often attribute to the wisdom of our ancestors great
political effects which have sprung unforeseen from the accident of the
situation.  Power, not wisdom, is most commonly the source of political
revolutions.  And the result, as in the Roman Republic, of the co-existence
of opposite elements in the same state is, not a balance of power or an
equable progress of liberal principles, but a conflict of forces, of which
one or other may happen to be in the ascendant.  In Greek history, as well
as in Plato's conception of it, this 'progression by antagonism' involves
reaction:  the aristocracy expands into democracy and returns again to
tyranny.

The constitution of the Laws may be said to consist, besides the
magistrates, mainly of three elements,--an administrative Council, the
judiciary, and the Nocturnal Council, which is an intellectual aristocracy,
composed of priests and the ten eldest guardians of the law and some
younger co-opted members.  To this latter chiefly are assigned the
functions of legislation, but to be exercised with a sparing hand.  The
powers of the ordinary council are administrative rather than legislative.
The whole number of 360, as in the Athenian constitution, is distributed
among the months of the year according to the number of the tribes.  Not
more than one-twelfth is to be in office at once, so that the government
would be made up of twelve administrations succeeding one another in the
course of the year.  They are to exercise a general superintendence, and,
like the Athenian counsellors, are to preside in monthly divisions over all
assemblies.  Of the ecclesia over which they presided little is said, and
that little relates to comparatively trifling duties.  Nothing is less
present to the mind of Plato than a House of Commons, carrying on year by
year the work of legislation.  For he supposes the laws to be already
provided.  As little would he approve of a body like the Roman Senate.  The
people and the aristocracy alike are to be represented, not by assemblies,
but by officers elected for one or two years, except the guardians of the
law, who are elected for twenty years.

The evils of this system are obvious.  If in any state, as Plato says in
the Statesman, it is easier to find fifty good draught-players than fifty
good rulers, the greater part of the 360 who compose the council must be
unfitted to rule.  The unfitness would be increased by the short period
during which they held office.  There would be no traditions of government
among them, as in a Greek or Italian oligarchy, and no individual would be
responsible for any of their acts.  Everything seems to have been
sacrificed to a false notion of equality, according to which all have a
turn of ruling and being ruled.  In the constitution of the Magnesian state
Plato has not emancipated himself from the limitations of ancient politics.
His government may be described as a democracy of magistrates elected by
the people.  He never troubles himself about the political consistency of
his scheme.  He does indeed say that the greater part of the good of this
world arises, not from equality, but from proportion, which he calls the
judgment of Zeus (compare Aristotle's Distributive Justice), but he hardly
makes any attempt to carry out the principle in practice.  There is no
attempt to proportion representation to merit; nor is there any body in his
commonwealth which represents the life either of a class or of the whole
state.  The manner of appointing magistrates is taken chiefly from the old
democratic constitution of Athens, of which it retains some of the worst
features, such as the use of the lot, while by doing away with the
political character of the popular assembly the mainspring of the machine
is taken out.  The guardians of the law, thirty-seven in number, of whom
the ten eldest reappear as a part of the Nocturnal Council at the end of
the twelfth book, are to be elected by the whole military class, but they
are to hold office for twenty years, and would therefore have an
oligarchical rather than a democratic character.  Nothing is said of the
manner in which the functions of the Nocturnal Council are to be harmonized
with those of the guardians of the law, or as to how the ordinary council
is related to it.

Similar principles are applied to inferior offices.  To some the
appointment is made by vote, to others by lot.  In the elections to the
priesthood, Plato endeavours to mix or balance in a friendly manner 'demus
and not demus.'  The commonwealth of the Laws, like the Republic, cannot
dispense with a spiritual head, which is the same in both--the oracle of
Delphi.  From this the laws about all divine things are to be derived.  The
final selection of the Interpreters, the choice of an heir for a vacant
lot, the punishment for removing a deposit, are also to be determined by
it.  Plato is not disposed to encourage amateur attempts to revive religion
in states.  For, as he says in the Laws, 'To institute religious rites is
the work of a great intelligence.'

Though the council is framed on the model of the Athenian Boule, the law
courts of Plato do not equally conform to the pattern of the Athenian
dicasteries.  Plato thinks that the judges should speak and ask questions:
--this is not possible if they are numerous; he would, therefore, have a
few judges only, but good ones.  He is nevertheless aware that both in
public and private suits there must be a popular element.  He insists that
the whole people must share in the administration of justice--in public
causes they are to take the first step, and the final decision is to remain
with them.  In private suits they are also to retain a share; 'for the
citizen who has no part in the administration of justice is apt to think
that he has no share in the state.  For this reason there is to be a court
of law in every tribe (i.e. for about every 2,000 citizens), and the judges
are to be chosen by lot.'  Of the courts of law he gives what he calls a
superficial sketch.  Nor, indeed is it easy to reconcile his various
accounts of them.  It is however clear that although some officials, like
the guardians of the law, the wardens of the agora, city, and country have
power to inflict minor penalties, the administration of justice is in the
main popular.  The ingenious expedient of dividing the questions of law and
fact between a judge and jury, which would have enabled Plato to combine
the popular element with the judicial, did not occur to him or to any other
ancient political philosopher.  Though desirous of limiting the number of
judges, and thereby confining the office to persons specially fitted for
it, he does not seem to have understood that a body of law must be formed
by decisions as well as by legal enactments.

He would have men in the first place seek justice from their friends and
neighbours, because, as he truly remarks, they know best the questions at
issue; these are called in another passage arbiters rather than judges. 
But if they cannot settle the matter, it is to be referred to the courts of
the tribes, and a higher penalty is to be paid by the party who is
unsuccessful in the suit.  There is a further appeal allowed to the select
judges, with a further increase of penalty.  The select judges are to be
appointed by the magistrates, who are to choose one from every magistracy.
They are to be elected annually, and therefore probably for a year only,
and are liable to be called to account before the guardians of the law.  In
cases of which death is the penalty, the trial takes place before a special
court, which is composed of the guardians of the law and of the judges of
appeal.

In treating of the subject in Book ix, he proposes to leave for the most
part the methods of procedure to a younger generation of legislators; the
procedure in capital causes he determines himself.  He insists that the
vote of the judges shall be given openly, and before they vote they are to
hear speeches from the plaintiff and defendant.  They are then to take
evidence in support of what has been said, and to examine witnesses.  The
eldest judge is to ask his questions first, and then the second, and then
the third.  The interrogatories are to continue for three days, and the
evidence is to be written down.  Apparently he does not expect the judges
to be professional lawyers, any more than he expects the members of the
council to be trained statesmen.

In forming marriage connexions, Plato supposes that the public interest
will prevail over private inclination.  There was nothing in this very
shocking to the notions of Greeks, among whom the feeling of love towards
the other sex was almost deprived of sentiment or romance.  Married life is
to be regulated solely with a view to the good of the state.  The newly-
married couple are not allowed to absent themselves from their respective
syssitia, even during their honeymoon; they are to give their whole mind to
the procreation of children; their duties to one another at a later period
of life are not a matter about which the state is equally solicitous. 
Divorces are readily allowed for incompatibility of temper.  As in the
Republic, physical considerations seem almost to exclude moral and social
ones.  To modern feelings there is a degree of coarseness in Plato's
treatment of the subject.  Yet he also makes some shrewd remarks on
marriage, as for example, that a man who does not marry for money will not
be the humble servant of his wife.  And he shows a true conception of the
nature of the family, when he requires that the newly-married couple
'should leave their father and mother,' and have a separate home.  He also
provides against extravagance in marriage festivals, which in some states
of society, for instance in the case of the Hindoos, has been a social evil
of the first magnitude.

In treating of property, Plato takes occasion to speak of property in
slaves.  They are to be treated with perfect justice; but, for their own
sake, to be kept at a distance.  The motive is not so much humanity to the
slave, of which there are hardly any traces (although Plato allows that
many in the hour of peril have found a slave more attached than members of
their own family), but the self-respect which the freeman and citizen owes
to himself (compare Republic).  If they commit crimes, they are doubly
punished; if they inform against illegal practices of their masters, they
are to receive a protection, which would probably be ineffectual, from the
guardians of the law; in rare cases they are to be set free.  Plato still
breathes the spirit of the old Hellenic world, in which slavery was a
necessity, because leisure must be provided for the citizen.

The education propounded in the Laws differs in several points from that of
the Republic.  Plato seems to have reflected as deeply and earnestly on the
importance of infancy as Rousseau, or Jean Paul (compare the saying of the
latter--'Not the moment of death, but the moment of birth, is probably the
more important').  He would fix the amusements of children in the hope of
fixing their characters in after-life.  In the spirit of the statesman who
said, 'Let me make the ballads of a country, and I care not who make their
laws,' Plato would say, 'Let the amusements of children be unchanged, and
they will not want to change the laws.  The 'Goddess Harmonia' plays a
great part in Plato's ideas of education.  The natural restless force of
life in children, 'who do nothing but roar until they are three years old,'
is gradually to be reduced to law and order.  As in the Republic, he fixes
certain forms in which songs are to be composed:  (1) they are to be
strains of cheerfulness and good omen; (2) they are to be hymns or prayers
addressed to the Gods; (3) they are to sing only of the lawful and good. 
The poets are again expelled or rather ironically invited to depart; and
those who remain are required to submit their poems to the censorship of
the magistrates.  Youth are no longer compelled to commit to memory many
thousand lyric and tragic Greek verses; yet, perhaps, a worse fate is in
store for them.  Plato has no belief in 'liberty of prophesying'; and
having guarded against the dangers of lyric poetry, he remembers that there
is an equal danger in other writings.  He cannot leave his old enemies, the
Sophists, in possession of the field; and therefore he proposes that youth
shall learn by heart, instead of the compositions of poets or prose
writers, his own inspired work on laws.  These, and music and mathematics,
are the chief parts of his education.

Mathematics are to be cultivated, not as in the Republic with a view to the
science of the idea of good,--though the higher use of them is not
altogether excluded,--but rather with a religious and political aim.  They
are a sacred study which teaches men how to distribute the portions of a
state, and which is to be pursued in order that they may learn not to
blaspheme about astronomy.  Against three mathematical errors Plato is in
profound earnest.  First, the error of supposing that the three dimensions
of length, breadth, and height, are really commensurable with one another.
The difficulty which he feels is analogous to the difficulty which he
formerly felt about the connexion of ideas, and is equally characteristic
of ancient philosophy:  he fixes his mind on the point of difference, and
cannot at the same time take in the similarity.  Secondly, he is puzzled
about the nature of fractions:  in the Republic, he is disposed to deny the
possibility of their existence.  Thirdly, his optimism leads him to insist
(unlike the Spanish king who thought that he could have improved on the
mechanism of the heavens) on the perfect or circular movement of the
heavenly bodies.  He appears to mean, that instead of regarding the stars
as overtaking or being overtaken by one another, or as planets wandering in
many paths, a more comprehensive survey of the heavens would enable us to
infer that they all alike moved in a circle around a centre (compare
Timaeus; Republic).  He probably suspected, though unacquainted with the
true cause, that the appearance of the heavens did not agree with the
reality:  at any rate, his notions of what was right or fitting easily
overpowered the results of actual observation.  To the early astronomers,
who lived at the revival of science, as to Plato, there was nothing absurd
in a priori astronomy, and they would probably have made fewer real
discoveries of they had followed any other track.  (Compare Introduction to
the Republic.)

The science of dialectic is nowhere mentioned by name in the Laws, nor is
anything said of the education of after-life.  The child is to begin to
learn at ten years of age:  he is to be taught reading and writing for
three years, from ten to thirteen, and no longer; and for three years more,
from thirteen to sixteen, he is to be instructed in music.  The great fault
which Plato finds in the contemporary education is the almost total
ignorance of arithmetic and astronomy, in which the Greeks would do well to
take a lesson from the Egyptians (compare Republic).  Dancing and wrestling
are to have a military character, and women as well as men are to be taught
the use of arms.  The military spirit which Plato has vainly endeavoured to
expel in the first two books returns again in the seventh and eighth.  He
has evidently a sympathy with the soldier, as well as with the poet, and he
is no mean master of the art, or at least of the theory, of war (compare
Laws; Republic), though inclining rather to the Spartan than to the
Athenian practice of it (Laws).  Of a supreme or master science which was
to be the 'coping-stone' of the rest, few traces appear in the Laws.  He
seems to have lost faith in it, or perhaps to have realized that the time
for such a science had not yet come, and that he was unable to fill up the
outline which he had sketched. There is no requirement that the guardians
of the law shall be philosophers, although they are to know the unity of
virtue, and the connexion of the sciences.  Nor are we told that the
leisure of the citizens, when they are grown up, is to be devoted to any
intellectual employment.  In this respect we note a falling off from the
Republic, but also there is 'the returning to it' of which Aristotle speaks
in the Politics.  The public and family duties of the citizens are to be
their main business, and these would, no doubt, take up a great deal more
time than in the modern world we are willing to allow to either of them. 
Plato no longer entertains the idea of any regular training to be pursued
under the superintendence of the state from eighteen to thirty, or from
thirty to thirty-five; he has taken the first step downwards on
'Constitution Hill' (Republic).  But he maintains as earnestly as ever that
'to men living under this second polity there remains the greatest of all
works, the education of the soul,' and that no bye-work should be allowed
to interfere with it.  Night and day are not long enough for the
consummation of it.

Few among us are either able or willing to carry education into later life;
five or six years spent at school, three or four at a university, or in the
preparation for a profession, an occasional attendance at a lecture to
which we are invited by friends when we have an hour to spare from house-
keeping or money-making--these comprise, as a matter of fact, the education
even of the educated; and then the lamp is extinguished 'more truly than
Heracleitus' sun, never to be lighted again' (Republic).  The description
which Plato gives in the Republic of the state of adult education among his
contemporaries may be applied almost word for word to our own age.  He does
not however acquiesce in this widely-spread want of a higher education; he
would rather seek to make every man something of a philosopher before he
enters on the duties of active life.  But in the Laws he no longer
prescribes any regular course of study which is to be pursued in mature
years.  Nor does he remark that the education of after-life is of another
kind, and must consist with the majority of the world rather in the
improvement of character than in the acquirement of knowledge.  It comes
from the study of ourselves and other men:  from moderation and experience: 
from reflection on circumstances:  from the pursuit of high aims:  from a
right use of the opportunities of life.  It is the preservation of what we
have been, and the addition of something more.  The power of abstract study
or continuous thought is very rare, but such a training as this can be
given by every one to himself.

The singular passage in Book vii., in which Plato describes life as a
pastime, like many other passages in the Laws is imperfectly expressed. 
Two thoughts seem to be struggling in his mind:  first, the reflection, to
which he returns at the end of the passage, that men are playthings or
puppets, and that God only is the serious aim of human endeavours; this
suggests to him the afterthought that, although playthings, they are the
playthings of the Gods, and that this is the best of them.  The cynical,
ironical fancy of the moment insensibly passes into a religious sentiment. 
In another passage he says that life is a game of which God, who is the
player, shifts the pieces so as to procure the victory of good on the
whole.  Or once more:  Tragedies are acted on the stage; but the best and
noblest of them is the imitation of the noblest life, which we affirm to be
the life of our whole state.  Again, life is a chorus, as well as a sort of
mystery, in which we have the Gods for playmates.  Men imagine that war is
their serious pursuit, and they make war that they may return to their
amusements.  But neither wars nor amusements are the true satisfaction of
men, which is to be found only in the society of the Gods, in sacrificing
to them and propitiating them.  Like a Christian ascetic, Plato seems to
suppose that life should be passed wholly in the enjoyment of divine
things.  And after meditating in amazement on the sadness and unreality of
the world, he adds, in a sort of parenthesis, 'Be cheerful, Sirs'
(Shakespeare, Tempest.)

In one of the noblest passages of Plato, he speaks of the relation of the
sexes.  Natural relations between members of the same family have been
established of old; a 'little word' has put a stop to incestuous
connexions.  But unnatural unions of another kind continued to prevail at
Crete and Lacedaemon, and were even justified by the example of the Gods. 
They, too, might be banished, if the feeling that they were unholy and
abominable could sink into the minds of men.  The legislator is to cry
aloud, and spare not, 'Let not men fall below the level of the beasts.' 
Plato does not shrink, like some modern philosophers, from 'carrying on war
against the mightiest lusts of mankind;' neither does he expect to
extirpate them, but only to confine them to their natural use and purpose,
by the enactments of law, and by the influence of public opinion.  He will
not feed them by an over-luxurious diet, nor allow the healthier instincts
of the soul to be corrupted by music and poetry.  The prohibition of
excessive wealth is, as he says, a very considerable gain in the way of
temperance, nor does he allow of those enthusiastic friendships between
older and younger persons which in his earlier writings appear to be
alluded to with a certain degree of amusement and without reproof (compare
Introduction to the Symposium).  Sappho and Anacreon are celebrated by him
in the Charmides and the Phaedrus; but they would have been expelled from
the Magnesian state.

Yet he does not suppose that the rule of absolute purity can be enforced on
all mankind.  Something must be conceded to the weakness of human nature. 
He therefore adopts a 'second legal standard of honourable and
dishonourable, having a second standard of right.'  He would abolish
altogether 'the connexion of men with men...As to women, if any man has to
do with any but those who come into his house duly married by sacred rites,
and he offends publicly in the face of all mankind, we shall be right in
enacting that he be deprived of civic honours and privileges.'  But feeling
also that it is impossible wholly to control the mightiest passions of
mankind,' Plato, like other legislators, makes a compromise.  The offender
must not be found out; decency, if not morality, must be respected.  In
this he appears to agree with the practice of all civilized ages and
countries.  Much may be truly said by the moralist on the comparative harm
of open and concealed vice.  Nor do we deny that some moral evils are
better turned out to the light, because, like diseases, when exposed, they
are more easily cured.  And secrecy introduces mystery which enormously
exaggerates their power; a mere animal want is thus elevated into a
sentimental ideal.  It may very well be that a word spoken in season about
things which are commonly concealed may have an excellent effect.  But
having regard to the education of youth, to the innocence of children, to
the sensibilities of women, to the decencies of society, Plato and the
world in general are not wrong in insisting that some of the worst vices,
if they must exist, should be kept out of sight; this, though only a
second-best rule, is a support to the weakness of human nature.  There are
some things which may be whispered in the closet, but should not be shouted
on the housetop.  It may be said of this, as of many other things, that it
is a great part of education to know to whom they are to be spoken of, and
when, and where.

BOOK IX.  Punishments of offences and modes of procedure come next in
order.  We have a sense of disgrace in making regulations for all the
details of crime in a virtuous and well-ordered state.  But seeing that we
are legislating for men and not for Gods, there is no uncharitableness in
apprehending that some one of our citizens may have a heart, like the seed
which has touched the ox's horn, so hard as to be impenetrable to the law.
Let our first enactment be directed against the robbing of temples.  No
well-educated citizen will be guilty of such a crime, but one of their
servants, or some stranger, may, and with a view to him, and at the same
time with a remoter eye to the general infirmity of human nature, I will
lay down the law, beginning with a prelude.  To the intending robber we
will say--O sir, the complaint which troubles you is not human; but some
curse has fallen upon you, inherited from the crimes of your ancestors, of
which you must purge yourself:  go and sacrifice to the Gods, associate
with the good, avoid the wicked; and if you are cured of the fatal impulse,
well; but if not, acknowledge death to be better than life, and depart.

These are the accents, soft and low, in which we address the would-be
criminal.  And if he will not listen, then cry aloud as with the sound of a
trumpet:  Whosoever robs a temple, if he be a slave or foreigner shall be
branded in the face and hands, and scourged, and cast naked beyond the
border.  And perhaps this may improve him:  for the law aims either at the
reformation of the criminal, or the repression of crime.  No punishment is
designed to inflict useless injury.  But if the offender be a citizen, he
must be incurable, and for him death is the only fitting penalty.  His
iniquity, however, shall not be visited on his children, nor shall his
property be confiscated.

As to the exaction of penalties, any person who is fined for an offence
shall not be liable to pay the fine, unless he have property in excess of
his lot.  For the lots must never go uncultivated for lack of means; the
guardians of the law are to provide against this.  If a fine is inflicted
upon a man which he cannot pay, and for which his friends are unwilling to
give security, he shall be imprisoned and otherwise dishonoured.  But no
criminal shall go unpunished:--whether death, or imprisonment, or stripes,
or fines, or the stocks, or banishment to a remote temple, be the penalty. 
Capital offences shall come under the cognizance of the guardians of the
law, and a college of the best of the last year's magistrates.  The order
of suits and similar details we shall leave to the lawgivers of the future,
and only determine the mode of voting.  The judges are to sit in order of
seniority, and the proceedings shall begin with the speeches of the
plaintiff and the defendant; and then the judges, beginning with the
eldest, shall ask questions and collect evidence during three days, which,
at the end of each day, shall be deposited in writing under their seals on
the altar of Hestia; and when they have evidence enough, after a solemn
declaration that they will decide justly, they shall vote and end the case.
The votes are to be given openly in the presence of the citizens.

Next to religion, the preservation of the constitution is the first object
of the law.  The greatest enemy of the state is he who attempts to set up a
tyrant, or breeds plots and conspiracies; not far below him in guilt is a
magistrate who either knowingly, or in ignorance, fails to bring the
offender to justice.  Any one who is good for anything will give
information against traitors.  The mode of proceeding at such trials will
be the same as at trials for sacrilege; the penalty, death.  But neither in
this case nor in any other is the son to bear the iniquity of the father,
unless father, grandfather, great-grandfather, have all of them been
capitally convicted, and then the family of the criminal are to be sent off
to the country of their ancestor, retaining their property, with the
exception of the lot and its fixtures.  And ten are to be selected from the
younger sons of the other citizens--one of whom is to be chosen by the
oracle of Delphi to be heir of the lot.

Our third law will be a general one, concerning the procedure and the
judges in cases of treason.  As regards the remaining or departure of the
family of the offender, the same law shall apply equally to the traitor,
the sacrilegious, and the conspirator.

A thief, whether he steals much or little, must refund twice the amount, if
he can do so without impairing his lot; if he cannot, he must go to prison
until he either pays the plaintiff, or in case of a public theft, the city,
or they agree to forgive him.  'But should all kinds of theft incur the
same penalty?'  You remind me of what I know--that legislation is never
perfect.  The men for whom laws are now made may be compared to the slave
who is being doctored, according to our old image, by the unscientific
doctor.  For the empirical practitioner, if he chance to meet the educated
physician talking to his patient, and entering into the philosophy of his
disease, would burst out laughing and say, as doctors delight in doing,
'Foolish fellow, instead of curing the patient you are educating him!' 
'And would he not be right?'  Perhaps; and he might add, that he who
discourses in our fashion preaches to the citizens instead of legislating
for them.  'True.'  There is, however, one advantage which we possess--that
being amateurs only, we may either take the most ideal, or the most
necessary and utilitarian view.  'But why offer such an alternative?  As if
all our legislation must be done to-day, and nothing put off until the
morrow.  We may surely rough-hew our materials first, and shape and place
them afterwards.'  That will be the natural way of proceeding.  There is a
further point.  Of all writings either in prose or verse the writings of
the legislator are the most important.  For it is he who has to determine
the nature of good and evil, and how they should be studied with a view to
our instruction.  And is it not as disgraceful for Solon and Lycurgus to
lay down false precepts about the institutions of life as for Homer and
Tyrtaeus?  The laws of states ought to be the models of writing, and what
is at variance with them should be deemed ridiculous.  And we may further
imagine them to express the affection and good sense of a father or mother,
and not to be the fiats of a tyrant.  'Very true.'

Let us enquire more particularly about sacrilege, theft and other crimes,
for which we have already legislated in part.  And this leads us to ask,
first of all, whether we are agreed or disagreed about the nature of the
honourable and just.  'To what are you referring?'  I will endeavour to
explain.  All are agreed that justice is honourable, whether in men or
things, and no one who maintains that a very ugly men who is just, is in
his mind fair, would be thought extravagant.  'Very true.'  But if honour
is to be attributed to justice, are just sufferings honourable, or only
just actions?  'What do you mean?'  Our laws supply a case in point; for we
enacted that the robber of temples and the traitor should die; and this was
just, but the reverse of honourable.  In this way does the language of the
many rend asunder the just and honourable.  'That is true.'  But is our own
language consistent?  I have already said that the evil are involuntarily
evil; and the evil are the unjust.  Now the voluntary cannot be the
involuntary; and if you two come to me and say, 'Then shall we legislate
for our city?'  Of course, I shall reply.--'Then will you distinguish what
crimes are voluntary and what involuntary, and shall we impose lighter
penalties on the latter, and heavier on the former?  Or shall we refuse to
determine what is the meaning of voluntary and involuntary, and maintain
that our words have come down from heaven, and that they should be at once
embodied in a law?'  All states legislate under the idea that there are two
classes of actions, the voluntary and the involuntary, but there is great
confusion about them in the minds of men; and the law can never act unless
they are distinguished.  Either we must abstain from affirming that unjust
actions are involuntary, or explain the meaning of this statement. 
Believing, then, that acts of injustice cannot be divided into voluntary
and involuntary, I must endeavour to find some other mode of classifying
them.  Hurts are voluntary and involuntary, but all hurts are not injuries: 
on the other hand, a benefit when wrongly conferred may be an injury.  An
act which gives or takes away anything is not simply just; but the
legislator who has to decide whether the case is one of hurt or injury,
must consider the animus of the agent; and when there is hurt, he must as
far as possible, provide a remedy and reparation:  but if there is
injustice, he must, when compensation has been made, further endeavour to
reconcile the two parties.  'Excellent.'  Where injustice, like disease, is
remediable, there the remedy must be applied in word or deed, with the
assistance of pleasures and pains, of bounties and penalties, or any other
influence which may inspire man with the love of justice, or hatred of
injustice; and this is the noblest work of law.  But when the legislator
perceives the evil to be incurable, he will consider that the death of the
offender will be a good to himself, and in two ways a good to society: 
first, as he becomes an example to others; secondly, because the city will
be quit of a rogue; and in such a case, but in no other, the legislator
will punish with death.  'There is some truth in what you say.  I wish,
however, that you would distinguish more clearly the difference of injury
and hurt, and the complications of voluntary and involuntary.'  You will
admit that anger is of a violent and destructive nature?  'Certainly.'  And
further, that pleasure is different from anger, and has an opposite power,
working by persuasion and deceit?  'Yes.'  Ignorance is the third source of
crimes; this is of two kinds--simple ignorance and ignorance doubled by
conceit of knowledge; the latter, when accompanied with power, is a source
of terrible errors, but is excusable when only weak and childish.  'True.' 
We often say that one man masters, and another is mastered by pleasure and
anger.  'Just so.'  But no one says that one man masters, and another is
mastered by ignorance. 'You are right.'  All these motives actuate men and
sometimes drive them in different ways.  'That is so.'  Now, then, I am in
a position to define the nature of just and unjust.  By injustice I mean
the dominion of anger and fear, pleasure and pain, envy and desire, in the
soul, whether doing harm or not:  by justice I mean the rule of the opinion
of the best, whether in states or individuals, extending to the whole of
life; although actions done in error are often thought to be involuntary
injustice.  No controversy need be raised about names at present; we are
only desirous of fixing in our memories the heads of error.  And the pain
which is called fear and anger is our first head of error; the second is
the class of pleasures and desires; and the third, of hopes which aim at
true opinion about the best;--this latter falls into three divisions (i.e.
(1) when accompanied by simple ignorance, (2) when accompanied by conceit
of wisdom combined with power, or (3) with weakness), so that there are in
all five.  And the laws relating to them may be summed up under two heads,
laws which deal with acts of open violence and with acts of deceit; to
which may be added acts both violent and deceitful, and these last should
be visited with the utmost rigour of the law.  'Very properly.'

Let us now return to the enactment of laws.  We have treated of sacrilege,
and of conspiracy, and of treason.  Any of these crimes may be committed by
a person not in his right mind, or in the second childhood of old age.  If
this is proved to be the fact before the judges, the person in question
shall only have to pay for the injury, and not be punished further, unless
he have on his hands the stain of blood.  In this case he shall be exiled
for a year, and if he return before the expiration of the year, he shall be
retained in the public prison two years.

Homicides may be divided into voluntary and involuntary:  and first of
involuntary homicide.  He who unintentionally kills another man at the
games or in military exercises duly authorized by the magistrates, whether
death follow immediately or after an interval, shall be acquitted, subject
only to the purification required by the Delphian Oracle.  Any physician
whose patient dies against his will shall in like manner be acquitted.  Any
one who unintentionally kills the slave of another, believing that he is
his own, with or without weapons, shall bear the master of the slave
harmless, or pay a penalty amounting to twice the value of the slave, and
to this let him add a purification greater than in the case of homicide at
the games.  If a man kill his own slave, a purification only is required of
him.  If he kill a freeman unintentionally, let him also make purification;
and let him remember the ancient tradition which says that the murdered man
is indignant when he sees the murderer walk about in his own accustomed
haunts, and that he terrifies him with the remembrance of his crime.  And
therefore the homicide should keep away from his native land for a year,
or, if he have slain a stranger, let him avoid the land of the stranger for
a like period.  If he complies with this condition, the nearest kinsman of
the deceased shall take pity upon him and be reconciled to him; but if he
refuses to remain in exile, or visits the temples unpurified, then let the
kinsman proceed against him, and demand a double penalty.  The kinsman who
neglects this duty shall himself incur the curse, and any one who likes may
proceed against him, and compel him to leave his country for five years. 
If a stranger involuntarily kill a stranger, any one may proceed against
him in the same manner:  and the homicide, if he be a metic, shall be
banished for a year; but if he be an entire stranger, whether he have
murdered metic, citizen, or stranger, he shall be banished for ever; and if
he return, he shall be punished with death, and his property shall go to
the next of kin of the murdered man.  If he come back by sea against his
will, he shall remain on the seashore, wetting his feet in the water while
he waits for a vessel to sail; or if he be brought back by land, the
magistrates shall send him unharmed beyond the border.

Next follows murder done from anger, which is of two kinds--either arising
out of a sudden impulse, and attended with remorse; or committed with
premeditation, and unattended with remorse.  The cause of both is anger,
and both are intermediate between voluntary and involuntary.  The one which
is committed from sudden impulse, though not wholly involuntary, bears the
image of the involuntary, and is therefore the more excusable of the two,
and should receive a gentler punishment.  The act of him who nurses his
wrath is more voluntary, and therefore more culpable.  The degree of
culpability depends on the presence or absence of intention, to which the
degree of punishment should correspond.  For the first kind of murder, that
which is done on a momentary impulse, let two years' exile be the penalty;
for the second, that which is accompanied with malice prepense, three. 
When the time of any one's exile has expired, the guardians shall send
twelve judges to the borders of the land, who shall have authority to
decide whether he may return or not.  He who after returning repeats the
offence, shall be exiled and return no more, and, if he return, shall be
put to death, like the stranger in a similar case.  He who in a fit of
anger kills his own slave, shall purify himself; and he who kills another
man's slave, shall pay to his master double the value.  Any one may proceed
against the offender if he appear in public places, not having been
purified; and may bring to trial both the next of kin to the dead man and
the homicide, and compel the one to exact, and the other to pay, a double
penalty.  If a slave kill his master, or a freeman who is not his master,
in anger, the kinsmen of the murdered person may do with the murderer
whatever they please, but they must not spare his life.  If a father or
mother kill their son or daughter in anger, let the slayer remain in exile
for three years; and on the return of the exile let the parents separate,
and no longer continue to cohabit, or have the same sacred rites with those
whom he or she has deprived of a brother or sister.  The same penalty is
decreed against the husband who murders his wife, and also against the wife
who murders her husband.  Let them be absent three years, and on their
return never again share in the same sacred rites with their children, or
sit at the same table with them.  Nor is a brother or sister who have
lifted up their hands against a brother or sister, ever to come under the
same roof or share in the same rites with those whom they have robbed of a
child.  If a son feels such hatred against his father or mother as to take
the life of either of them, then, if the parent before death forgive him,
he shall only suffer the penalty due to involuntary homicide; but if he be
unforgiven, there are many laws against which he has offended; he is guilty
of outrage, impiety, sacrilege all in one, and deserves to be put to death
many times over.  For if the law will not allow a man to kill the authors
of his being even in self-defence, what other penalty than death can be
inflicted upon him who in a fit of passion wilfully slays his father or
mother?  If a brother kill a brother in self-defence during a civil broil,
or a citizen a citizen, or a slave a slave, or a stranger a stranger, let
them be free from blame, as he is who slays an enemy in battle.  But if a
slave kill a freeman, let him be as a parricide.  In all cases, however,
the forgiveness of the injured party shall acquit the agents; and then they
shall only be purified, and remain in exile for a year.

Enough of actions that are involuntary, or done in anger; let us proceed to
voluntary and premeditated actions.  The great source of voluntary crime is
the desire of money, which is begotten by evil education; and this arises
out of the false praise of riches, common both among Hellenes and
barbarians; they think that to be the first of goods which is really the
third.  For the body is not for the sake of wealth, but wealth for the
body, as the body is for the soul.  If this were better understood, the
crime of murder, of which avarice is the chief cause, would soon cease
among men.  Next to avarice, ambition is a source of crime, troublesome to
the ambitious man himself, as well as to the chief men of the state.  And
next to ambition, base fear is a motive, which has led many an one to
commit murder in order that he may get rid of the witnesses of his crimes. 
Let this be said as a prelude to all enactments about crimes of violence;
and the tradition must not be forgotten, which tells that the murderer is
punished in the world below, and that when he returns to this world he
meets the fate which he has dealt out to others.  If a man is deterred by
the prelude and the fear of future punishment, he will have no need of the
law; but in case he disobey, let the law be declared against him as
follows:--He who of malice prepense kills one of his kindred, shall in the
first place be outlawed; neither temple, harbour, nor agora shall be
polluted by his presence.  And if a kinsman of the deceased refuse to
proceed against his slayer, he shall take the curse of pollution upon
himself, and also be liable to be prosecuted by any one who will avenge the
dead.  The prosecutor, however, must observe the customary ceremonial
before he proceeds against the offender.  The details of these observances
will be best determined by a conclave of prophets and interpreters and
guardians of the law, and the judges of the cause itself shall be the same
as in cases of sacrilege.  He who is convicted shall be punished with
death, and not be buried within the country of the murdered person.  He who
flies from the law shall undergo perpetual banishment; if he return, he may
be put to death with impunity by any relative of the murdered man or by any
other citizen, or bound and delivered to the magistrates.  He who accuses a
man of murder shall demand satisfactory bail of the accused, and if this is
not forthcoming, the magistrate shall keep him in prison against the day of
trial.  If a man commit murder by the hand of another, he shall be tried in
the same way as in the cases previously supposed, but if the offender be a
citizen, his body after execution shall be buried within the land.

If a slave kill a freeman, either with his own hand or by contrivance, let
him be led either to the grave or to a place whence he can see the grave of
the murdered man, and there receive as many stripes at the hand of the
public executioner as the person who took him pleases; and if he survive he
shall be put to death.  If a slave be put out of the way to prevent his
informing of some crime, his death shall be punished like that of a
citizen.  If there are any of those horrible murders of kindred which
sometimes occur even in well-regulated societies, and of which the
legislator, however unwilling, cannot avoid taking cognizance, he will
repeat the old myth of the divine vengeance against the perpetrators of
such atrocities.  The myth will say that the murderer must suffer what he
has done:  if he have slain his father, he must be slain by his children;
if his mother, he must become a woman and perish at the hands of his
offspring in another age of the world.  Such a preamble may terrify him;
but if, notwithstanding, in some evil hour he murders father or mother or
brethren or children, the mode of proceeding shall be as follows:--Him who
is convicted, the officers of the judges shall lead to a spot without the
city where three ways meet, and there slay him and expose his body naked;
and each of the magistrates shall cast a stone upon his head and justify
the city, and he shall be thrown unburied beyond the border.  But what
shall we say of him who takes the life which is dearest to him, that is to
say, his own; and this not from any disgrace or calamity, but from
cowardice and indolence?  The manner of his burial and the purification of
his crime is a matter for God and the interpreters to decide and for his
kinsmen to execute.  Let him, at any rate, be buried alone in some
uncultivated and nameless spot, and be without name or monument.  If a
beast kill a man, not in a public contest, let it be prosecuted for murder,
and after condemnation slain and cast without the border.  Also inanimate
things which have caused death, except in the case of lightning and other
visitations from heaven, shall be carried without the border.  If the body
of a dead man be found, and the murderer remain unknown, the trial shall
take place all the same, and the unknown murderer shall be warned not to
set foot in the temples or come within the borders of the land; if
discovered, he shall die, and his body shall be cast out.  A man is
justified in taking the life of a burglar, of a footpad, of a violator of
women or youth; and he may take the life of another with impunity in
defence of father, mother, brother, wife, or other relations.

The nurture and education which are necessary to the existence of men have
been considered, and the punishment of acts of violence which destroy life.
There remain maiming, wounding, and the like, which admit of a similar
division into voluntary and involuntary.  About this class of actions the
preamble shall be:  Whereas men would be like wild beasts unless they
obeyed the laws, the first duty of citizens is the care of the public
interests, which unite and preserve states, as private interests distract
them.  A man may know what is for the public good, but if he have absolute
power, human nature will impel him to seek pleasure instead of virtue, and
so darkness will come over his soul and over the state.  If he had mind, he
would have no need of law; for mind is the perfection of law.  But such a
freeman, 'whom the truth makes free,' is hardly to be found; and therefore
law and order are necessary, which are the second-best, and they regulate
things as they exist in part only, but cannot take in the whole.  For
actions have innumerable characteristics, which must be partly determined
by the law and partly left to the judge.  The judge must determine the
fact; and to him also the punishment must sometimes be left.  What shall
the law prescribe, and what shall be left to the judge?  A city is
unfortunate in which the tribunals are either secret and speechless, or,
what is worse, noisy and public, when the people, as if they were in a
theatre, clap and hoot the various speakers.  Such courts a legislator
would rather not have; but if he is compelled to have them, he will speak
distinctly, and leave as little as possible to their discretion.  But where
the courts are good, and presided over by well-trained judges, the
penalties to be inflicted may be in a great measure left to them; and as
there are to be good courts among our colonists, we need not determine
beforehand the exact proportion of the penalty and the crime.  Returning,
then, to our legislator, let us indite a law about wounding, which shall
run as follows:--He who wounds with intent to kill, and fails in his
object, shall be tried as if he had succeeded.  But since God has favoured
both him and his victim, instead of being put to death, he shall be allowed
to go into exile and take his property with him, the damage due to the
sufferer having been previously estimated by the court, which shall be the
same as would have tried the case if death had ensued.  If a child should
intentionally wound a parent, or a servant his master, or brother or sister
wound brother or sister with malice prepense, the penalty shall be death. 
If a husband or wife wound one another with intent to kill, the penalty
which is inflicted upon them shall be perpetual exile; and if they have
young children, the guardians shall take care of them and administer their
property as if they were orphans.  If they have no children, their kinsmen
male and female shall meet, and after a consultation with the priests and
guardians of the law, shall appoint an heir of the house; for the house and
family belong to the state, being a 5040th portion of the whole.  And the
state is bound to preserve her families happy and holy; therefore, when the
heir of a house has committed a capital offence, or is in exile for life,
the house is to be purified, and then the kinsmen of the house and the
guardians of the law are to find out a family which has a good name and in
which there are many sons, and introduce one of them to be the heir and
priest of the house.  He shall assume the fathers and ancestors of the
family, while the first son dies in dishonour and his name is blotted out.

Some actions are intermediate between the voluntary and involuntary.  Those
done from anger are of this class.  If a man wound another in anger, let
him pay double the damage, if the injury is curable; or fourfold, if
curable, and at the same time dishonourable; and fourfold, if incurable;
the amount is to be assessed by the judges.  If the wounded person is
rendered incapable of military service, the injurer, besides the other
penalties, shall serve in his stead, or be liable to a suit for refusing to
serve.  If brother wounds brother, then their parents and kindred, of both
sexes, shall meet and judge the crime.  The damages shall be assessed by
the parents; and if the amount fixed by them is disputed, an appeal shall
be made to the male kindred; or in the last resort to the guardians of the
law.  Parents who wound their children are to be tried by judges of at
least sixty years of age, who have children of their own; and they are to
determine whether death, or some lesser punishment, is to be inflicted upon
them--no relatives are to take part in the trial.  If a slave in anger
smite a freeman, he is to be delivered up by his master to the injured
person.  If the master suspect collusion between the slave and the injured
person, he may bring the matter to trial:  and if he fail he shall pay
three times the injury; or if he obtain a conviction, the contriver of the
conspiracy shall be liable to an action for kidnapping.  He who wounds
another unintentionally shall only pay for the actual harm done.

In all outrages and acts of violence, the elder is to be more regarded than
the younger.  An injury done by a younger man to an elder is abominable and
hateful; but the younger man who is struck by an elder is to bear with him
patiently, considering that he who is twenty years older is loco parentis,
and remembering the reverence which is due to the Gods who preside over
birth.  Let him keep his hands, too, from the stranger; instead of taking
upon himself to chastise him when he is insolent, he shall bring him before
the wardens of the city, who shall examine into the case, and if they find
him guilty, shall scourge him with as many blows as he has given; or if he
be innocent, they shall warn and threaten his accuser.  When an equal
strikes an equal, whether an old man an old man, or a young man a young
man, let them use only their fists and have no weapons.  He who being above
forty years of age commences a fight, or retaliates, shall be counted mean
and base.

To this preamble, let the law be added:  If a man smite another who is his
elder by twenty years or more, let the bystander, in case he be older than
the combatants, part them; or if he be younger than the person struck, or
of the same age with him, let him defend him as he would a father or
brother; and let the striker be brought to trial, and if convicted
imprisoned for a year or more at the discretion of the judges.  If a
stranger smite one who is his elder by twenty years or more, he shall be
imprisoned for two years, and a metic, in like case, shall suffer three
years' imprisonment.  He who is standing by and gives no assistance, shall
be punished according to his class in one of four penalties--a mina, fifty,
thirty, twenty drachmas.  The generals and other superior officers of the
army shall form the court which tries this class of offences.

Laws are made to instruct the good, and in the hope that there may be no
need of them; also to control the bad, whose hardness of heart will not be
hindered from crime.  The uttermost penalty will fall upon those who lay
violent hands upon a parent, having no fear of the Gods above, or of the
punishments which will pursue them in the world below.  They are too wise
in their own conceits to believe in such things:  wherefore the tortures
which await them in another life must be anticipated in this.  Let the law
be as follows:--

If a man, being in his right mind, dare to smite his father and mother, or
his grandfather and grandmother, let the passer-by come to the rescue; and
if he be a metic or stranger who comes to the rescue, he shall have the
first place at the games; or if he do not come to the rescue, he shall be a
perpetual exile.  Let the citizen in the like case be praised or blamed,
and the slave receive freedom or a hundred stripes.  The wardens of the
agora, the city, or the country, as the case may be, shall see to the
execution of the law.  And he who is an inhabitant of the same place and is
present shall come to the rescue, or he shall fall under a curse.

If a man be convicted of assaulting his parents, let him be banished for
ever from the city into the country, and let him abstain from all sacred
rites; and if he do not abstain, let him be punished by the wardens of the
country; and if he return to the city, let him be put to death.  If any
freeman consort with him, let him be purified before he returns to the
city.  If a slave strike a freeman, whether citizen or stranger, let the
bystander be obliged to seize and deliver him into the hands of the injured
person, who may inflict upon him as many blows as he pleases, and shall
then return him to his master.  The law will be as follows:--The slave who
strikes a freeman shall be bound by his master, and not set at liberty
without the consent of the person whom he has injured.  All these laws
apply to women as well as to men.

BOOK X.  The greatest wrongs arise out of youthful insolence, and the
greatest of all are committed against public temples; they are in the
second degree great when private rites and sepulchres are insulted; in the
third degree, when committed against parents; in the fourth degree, when
they are done against the authority or property of the rulers; in the fifth
degree, when the rights of individuals are violated.  Most of these
offences have been already considered; but there remains the question of
admonition and punishment of offences against the Gods.  Let the admonition
be in the following terms:--No man who ever intentionally did or said
anything impious, had a true belief in the existence of the Gods; but
either he thought that there were no Gods, or that they did not care about
men, or that they were easily appeased by sacrifices and prayers.  'What
shall we say or do to such persons?'  My good sir, let us first hear the
jests which they in their superiority will make upon us.  'What will they
say?'  Probably something of this kind:--'Strangers you are right in
thinking that some of us do not believe in the existence of the Gods; while
others assert that they do not care for us, and others that they are
propitiated by prayers and offerings.  But we want you to argue with us
before you threaten; you should prove to us by reasonable evidence that
there are Gods, and that they are too good to be bribed.  Poets, priests,
prophets, rhetoricians, even the best of them, speak to us of atoning for
evil, and not of avoiding it.  From legislators who profess to be gentle we
ask for instruction, which may, at least, have the persuasive power of
truth, if no other.'  What have you to say?  'Well, there is no difficulty
in proving the being of the Gods.  The sun, and earth, and stars, moving in
their courses, the recurring seasons, furnish proofs of their existence;
and there is the general opinion of mankind.'  I fear that the unbelievers-
-not that I care for their opinion--will despise us.  You are not aware
that their impiety proceeds, not from sensuality, but from ignorance taking
the garb of wisdom.  'What do you mean?'  At Athens there are tales current
both in prose and verse of a kind which are not tolerated in a well-
regulated state like yours.  The oldest of them relate the origin of the
world, and the birth and life of the Gods.  These narratives have a bad
influence on family relations; but as they are old we will let them pass,
and consider another kind of tales, invented by the wisdom of a younger
generation, who, if any one argues for the existence of the Gods and claims
that the stars have a divine being, insist that these are mere earth and
stones, which can have no care of human things, and that all theology is a
cooking up of words.  Now what course ought we to take?  Shall we suppose
some impious man to charge us with assuming the existence of the Gods, and
make a defence?  Or shall we leave the preamble and go on to the laws? 
'There is no hurry, and we have often said that the shorter and worse
method should not be preferred to the longer and better.  The proof that
there are Gods who are good, and the friends of justice, is the best
preamble of all our laws.'  Come, let us talk with the impious, who have
been brought up from their infancy in the belief of religion, and have
heard their own fathers and mothers praying for them and talking with the
Gods as if they were absolutely convinced of their existence; who have seen
mankind prostrate in prayer at the rising and setting of the sun and moon
and at every turn of fortune, and have dared to despise and disbelieve all
this.  Can we keep our temper with them, when they compel us to argue on
such a theme?  We must; or like them we shall go mad, though with more
reason.  Let us select one of them and address him as follows:

O my son, you are young; time and experience will make you change many of
your opinions.  Do not be hasty in forming a conclusion about the divine
nature; and let me mention to you a fact which I know.  You and your
friends are not the first or the only persons who have had these notions
about the Gods.  There are always a considerable number who are infected by
them:  I have known many myself, and can assure you that no one who was an
unbeliever in his youth ever persisted till he was old in denying the
existence of the Gods.  The two other opinions, first, that the Gods exist
and have no care of men, secondly, that they care for men, but may be
propitiated by sacrifices and prayers, may indeed last through life in a
few instances, but even this is not common.  I would beg of you to be
patient, and learn the truth of the legislator and others; in the mean time
abstain from impiety.  'So far, our discourse has gone well.'

I will now speak of a strange doctrine, which is regarded by many as the
crown of philosophy.  They affirm that all things come into being either by
art or nature or chance, and that the greater things are done by nature and
chance, and the lesser things by art, which receiving from nature the
greater creations, moulds and fashions all those lesser works which are
termed works of art.  Their meaning is that fire, water, earth, and air all
exist by nature and chance, and not by art; and that out of these,
according to certain chance affinities of opposites, the sun, the moon, the
stars, and the earth have been framed, not by any action of mind, but by
nature and chance only.  Thus, in their opinion, the heaven and earth were
created, as well as the animals and plants.  Art came later, and is of
mortal birth; by her power were invented certain images and very partial
imitations of the truth, of which kind are the creations of musicians and
painters:  but they say that there are other arts which combine with
nature, and have a deeper truth, such as medicine, husbandry, gymnastic. 
Also the greater part of politics they imagine to co-operate with nature,
but in a less degree, having more of art, while legislation is declared by
them to be wholly a work of art.  'How do you mean?'  In the first place,
they say that the Gods exist neither by nature nor by art, but by the laws
of states, which are different in different countries; and that virtue is
one thing by nature and another by convention; and that justice is
altogether conventional, made by law, and having authority for the moment
only.  This is repeated to young men by sages and poets, and leads to
impiety, and the pretended life according to nature and in disobedience to
law; for nobody believes the Gods to be such as the law affirms.  'How
true! and oh! how injurious to states and to families!'  But then, what
should the lawgiver do?  Should he stand up in the state and threaten
mankind with the severest penalties if they persist in their unbelief,
while he makes no attempt to win them by persuasion?  'Nay, Stranger, the
legislator ought never to weary of trying to persuade the world that there
are Gods; and he should declare that law and art exist by nature.'  Yes,
Cleinias; but these are difficult and tedious questions.  'And shall our
patience, which was not exhausted in the enquiry about music or drink, fail
now that we are discoursing about the Gods?  There may be a difficulty in
framing laws, but when written down they remain, and time and diligence
will make them clear; if they are useful there would be neither reason nor
religion in rejecting them on account of their length.'  Most true.  And
the general spread of unbelief shows that the legislator should do
something in vindication of the laws, when they are being undermined by bad
men.  'He should.'  You agree with me, Cleinias, that the heresy consists
in supposing earth, air, fire, and water to be the first of all things. 
These the heretics call nature, conceiving them to be prior to the soul. 
'I agree.'  You would further agree that natural philosophy is the source
of this impiety--the study appears to be pursued in a wrong way.  'In what
way do you mean?'  The error consists in transposing first and second
causes.  They do not see that the soul is before the body, and before all
other things, and the author and ruler of them all.  And if the soul is
prior to the body, then the things of the soul are prior to the things of
the body.  In other words, opinion, attention, mind, art, law, are prior to
sensible qualities; and the first and greater works of creation are the
results of art and mind, whereas the works of nature, as they are
improperly termed, are secondary and subsequent.  'Why do you say
"improperly"?'  Because when they speak of nature they seem to mean the
first creative power.  But if the soul is first, and not fire and air, then
the soul above all things may be said to exist by nature.  And this can
only be on the supposition that the soul is prior to the body.  Shall we
try to prove that it is so?  'By all means.'  I fear that the greenness of
our argument will ludicrously contrast with the ripeness of our ages.  But
as we must go into the water, and the stream is strong, I will first
attempt to cross by myself, and if I arrive at the bank, you shall follow. 
Remembering that you are unaccustomed to such discussions, I will ask and
answer the questions myself, while you listen in safety.  But first I must
pray the Gods to assist at the demonstration of their own existence--if
ever we are to call upon them, now is the time.  Let me hold fast to the
rope, and enter into the depths:  Shall I put the question to myself in
this form?--Are all things at rest, and is nothing in motion? or are some
things in motion, and some things at rest?  'The latter.'  And do they move
and rest, some in one place, some in more?  'Yes.'  There may be (1) motion
in the same place, as in revolution on an axis, which is imparted swiftly
to the larger and slowly to the lesser circle; and there may be motion in
different places, having sometimes (2) one centre of motion and sometimes
(3) more.  (4) When bodies in motion come against other bodies which are at
rest, they are divided by them, and (5) when they are caught between other
bodies coming from opposite directions they unite with them; and (6) they
grow by union and (7) waste by dissolution while their constitution remains
the same, but are (8) destroyed when their constitution fails.  There is a
growth from one dimension to two, and from a second to a third, which then
becomes perceptible to sense; this process is called generation, and the
opposite, destruction.  We have now enumerated all possible motions with
the exception of two.  'What are they?'  Just the two with which our
enquiry is concerned; for our enquiry relates to the soul.  There is one
kind of motion which is only able to move other things; there is another
which can move itself as well, working in composition and decomposition, by
increase and diminution, by generation and destruction.  'Granted.'  (9)
That which moves and is moved by another is the ninth kind of motion; (10)
that which is self-moved and moves others is the tenth.  And this tenth
kind of motion is the mightiest, and is really the first, and is followed
by that which was improperly called the ninth.  'How do you mean?'  Must
not that which is moved by others finally depend upon that which is moved
by itself?  Nothing can be affected by any transition prior to self-motion. 
Then the first and eldest principle of motion, whether in things at rest or
not at rest, will be the principle of self-motion; and that which is moved
by others and can move others will be the second.  'True.'  Let me ask
another question:

What is the name which is given to self-motion when manifested in any
material substance?  'Life.'  And soul too is life?  'Very good.'  And are
there not three kinds of knowledge--a knowledge (1) of the essence, (2) of
the definition, (3) of the name?  And sometimes the name leads us to ask
the definition, sometimes the definition to ask the name.  For example,
number can be divided into equal parts, and when thus divided is termed
even, and the definition of even and the word 'even' refer to the same
thing.  'Very true.'  And what is the definition of the thing which is
named 'soul'?  Must we not reply, 'The self-moved'?  And have we not proved
that the self-moved is the source of motion in other things?  'Yes.'  And
the motion which is not self-moved will be inferior to this?  'True.'  And
if so, we shall be right in saying that the soul is prior and superior to
the body, and the body by nature subject and inferior to the soul?  'Quite
right.'  And we agreed that if the soul was prior to the body, the things
of the soul were prior to the things of the body?  'Certainly.'  And
therefore desires, and manners, and thoughts, and true opinions, and
recollections, are prior to the length and breadth and force of bodies. 
'To be sure.'  In the next place, we acknowledge that the soul is the cause
of good and evil, just and unjust, if we suppose her to be the cause of all
things?  'Certainly.'  And the soul which orders all things must also order
the heavens?  'Of course.'  One soul or more?  More; for less than two are
inconceivable, one good, the other evil.  'Most true.'  The soul directs
all things by her movements, which we call will, consideration, attention,
deliberation, opinion true and false, joy, sorrow, courage, fear, hatred,
love, and similar affections.  These are the primary movements, and they
receive the secondary movements of bodies, and guide all things to increase
and diminution, separation and union, and to all the qualities which
accompany them--cold, hot, heavy, light, hard, soft, white, black, sweet,
bitter; these and other such qualities the soul, herself a goddess, uses,
when truly receiving the divine mind she leads all things rightly to their
happiness; but under the impulse of folly she works out an opposite result.
For the controller of heaven and earth and the circle of the world is
either the wise and good soul, or the foolish and vicious soul, working in
them.  'What do you mean?'  If we say that the whole course and motion of
heaven and earth is in accordance with the workings and reasonings of mind,
clearly the best soul must have the care of the heaven, and guide it along
that better way.  'True.'  But if the heavens move wildly and disorderly,
then they must be under the guidance of the evil soul.  'True again.'  What
is the nature of the movement of the soul?  We must not suppose that we can
see and know the soul with our bodily eyes, any more than we can fix them
on the midday sun; it will be safer to look at an image only.  'How do you
mean?'  Let us find among the ten kinds of motion an image of the motion of
the mind.  You remember, as we said, that all things are divided into two
classes; and some of them were moved and some at rest.  'Yes.'  And of
those which were moved, some were moved in the same place, others in more
places than one.  'Just so.'  The motion which was in one place was
circular, like the motion of a spherical body; and such a motion in the
same place, and in the same relations, is an excellent image of the motion
of mind.  'Very true.'  The motion of the other sort, which has no fixed
place or manner or relation or order or proportion, is akin to folly and
nonsense.  'Very true.'  After what has been said, it is clear that, since
the soul carries round all things, some soul which is either very good or
the opposite carries round the circumference of heaven.  But that soul can
be no other than the best.  Again, the soul carries round the sun, moon,
and stars, and if the sun has a soul, then either the soul of the sun is
within and moves the sun as the human soul moves the body; or, secondly,
the sun is contained in some external air or fire, which the soul provides
and through which she operates; or, thirdly, the course of the sun is
guided by the soul acting in a wonderful manner without a body.  'Yes, in
one of those ways the soul must guide all things.'  And this soul of the
sun, which is better than the sun, whether driving him in a chariot or
employing any other agency, is by every man called a God?  'Yes, by every
man who has any sense.'  And of the seasons, stars, moon, and year, in like
manner, it may be affirmed that the soul or souls from which they derive
their excellence are divine; and without insisting on the manner of their
working, no one can deny that all things are full of Gods.  'No one.'  And
now let us offer an alternative to him who denies that there are Gods. 
Either he must show that the soul is not the origin of all things, or he
must live for the future in the belief that there are Gods.

Next, as to the man who believes in the Gods, but refuses to acknowledge
that they take care of human things--let him too have a word of admonition.
'Best of men,' we will say to him, 'some affinity to the Gods leads you to
honour them and to believe in them.  But you have heard the happiness of
wicked men sung by poets and admired by the world, and this has drawn you
away from your natural piety.  Or you have seen the wicked growing old in
prosperity, and leaving great offices to their children; or you have
watched the tyrant succeeding in his career of crime; and considering all
these things you have been led to believe in an irrational way that the
Gods take no care of human affairs.  That your error may not increase, I
will endeavour to purify your soul.'  Do you, Megillus and Cleinias, make
answer for the youth, and when we come to a difficulty, I will carry you
over the water as I did before.  'Very good.'  He will easily be convinced
that the Gods care for the small as well as the great; for he heard what
was said of their goodness and of their having all things under their care.
'He certainly heard.'  Then now let us enquire what is meant by the virtue
of the Gods.  To possess mind belongs to virtue, and the contrary to vice.
'That is what we say.'  And is not courage a part of virtue, and cowardice
of vice?  'Certainly.'  And to the Gods we ascribe virtues; but idleness
and indolence are not virtues.  'Of course not.'  And is God to be
conceived of as a careless, indolent fellow, such as the poet would compare
to a stingless drone?  'Impossible.'  Can we be right in praising any one
who cares for great matters and leaves the small to take care of
themselves?  Whether God or man, he who does so, must either think the
neglect of such matters to be of no consequence, or he is indolent and
careless.  For surely neither of them can be charged with neglect if they
fail to attend to something which is beyond their power?  'Certainly not.'

And now we will examine the two classes of offenders who admit that there
are Gods, but say,--the one that they may be appeased, the other that they
take no care of small matters:  do they not acknowledge that the Gods are
omnipotent and omniscient, and also good and perfect?  'Certainly.'  Then
they cannot be indolent, for indolence is the offspring of idleness, and
idleness of cowardice, and there is no cowardice in God.  'True.'  If the
Gods neglect small matters, they must either know or not know that such
things are not to be regarded.  But of course they know that they should be
regarded, and knowing, they cannot be supposed to neglect their duty,
overcome by the seductions of pleasure or pain.  'Impossible.'  And do not
all human things share in soul, and is not man the most religious of
animals and the possession of the Gods?  And the Gods, who are the best of
owners, will surely take care of their property, small or great.  Consider
further, that the greater the power of perception, the less the power of
action.  For it is harder to see and hear the small than the great, but
easier to control them.  Suppose a physician who had to cure a patient--
would he ever succeed if he attended to the great and neglected the little?
'Impossible.'  Is not life made up of littles?--the pilot, general,
householder, statesman, all attend to small matters; and the builder will
tell you that large stones do not lie well without small ones.  And God is
not inferior to mortal craftsmen, who in proportion to their skill are
careful in the details of their work; we must not imagine the best and
wisest to be a lazy good-for-nothing, who wearies of his work and hurries
over small and easy matters.  'Never, never!'  He who charges the Gods with
neglect has been forced to admit his error; but I should like further to
persuade him that the author of all has made every part for the sake of the
whole, and that the smallest part has an appointed state of action or
passion, and that the least action or passion of any part has a presiding
minister.  You, we say to him, are a minute fraction of this universe,
created with a view to the whole; the world is not made for you, but you
for the world; for the good artist considers the whole first, and
afterwards the parts.  And you are annoyed at not seeing how you and the
universe are all working together for the best, so far as the laws of the
common creation admit.  The soul undergoes many changes from her contact
with bodies; and all that the player does is to put the pieces into their
right places.  'What do you mean?'  I mean that God acts in the way which
is simplest and easiest.  Had each thing been formed without any regard to
the rest, the transposition of the Cosmos would have been endless; but now
there is not much trouble in the government of the world.  For when the
king saw the actions of the living souls and bodies, and the virtue and
vice which were in them, and the indestructibility of the soul and body
(although they were not eternal), he contrived so to arrange them that
virtue might conquer and vice be overcome as far as possible; giving them a
seat and room adapted to them, but leaving the direction of their separate
actions to men's own wills, which make our characters to be what they are.
'That is very probable.'  All things which have a soul possess in
themselves the principle of change, and in changing move according to fate
and law; natures which have undergone lesser changes move on the surface;
but those which have changed utterly for the worse, sink into Hades and the
infernal world.  And in all great changes for good and evil which are
produced either by the will of the soul or the influence of others, there
is a change of place.  The good soul, which has intercourse with the divine
nature, passes into a holier and better place; and the evil soul, as she
grows worse, changes her place for the worse.  This,--as we declare to the
youth who fancies that he is neglected of the Gods,--is the law of divine
justice--the worse to the worse, the better to the better, like to like, in
life and in death.  And from this law no man will ever boast that he has
escaped.  Even if you say--'I am small, and will creep into the earth,' or
'I am high, and will mount to heaven'--you are not so small or so high that
you shall not pay the fitting penalty, either here or in the world below.
This is also the explanation of the seeming prosperity of the wicked, in
whose actions as in a mirror you imagined that you saw the neglect of the
Gods, not considering that they make all things contribute to the whole. 
And how then could you form any idea of true happiness?--If Cleinias and
Megillus and I have succeeded in persuading you that you know not what you
say about the Gods, God will help you; but if there is still any deficiency
of proof, hear our answer to the third opponent.

Enough has been said to prove that the Gods exist and care for us; that
they can be propitiated, or that they receive gifts, is not to be allowed
or admitted for an instant.  'Let us proceed with the argument.'  Tell me,
by the Gods, I say, how the Gods are to be propitiated by us?  Are they not
rulers, who may be compared to charioteers, pilots, perhaps generals, or
physicians providing against the assaults of disease, husbandmen observing
the perils of the seasons, shepherds watching their flocks?  To whom shall
we compare them?  We acknowledged that the world is full both of good and
evil, but having more of evil than of good.  There is an immortal conflict
going on, in which Gods and demigods are our allies, and we their property;
for injustice and folly and wickedness make war in our souls upon justice
and temperance and wisdom.  There is little virtue to be found on earth;
and evil natures fawn upon the Gods, like wild beasts upon their keepers,
and believe that they can win them over by flattery and prayers.  And this
sin, which is termed dishonesty, is to the soul what disease is to the
body, what pestilence is to the seasons, what injustice is to states. 
'Quite so.'  And they who maintain that the Gods can be appeased must say
that they forgive the sins of men, if they are allowed to share in their
spoils; as you might suppose wolves to mollify the dogs by throwing them a
portion of the prey.  'That is the argument.'  But let us apply our images
to the Gods--are they the pilots who are won by gifts to wreck their own
ships--or the charioteers who are bribed to lose the race--or the generals,
or doctors, or husbandmen, who are perverted from their duty--or the dogs
who are silenced by wolves?  'God forbid.'  Are they not rather our best
guardians; and shall we suppose them to fall short even of a moderate
degree of human or even canine virtue, which will not betray justice for
reward?  'Impossible.'  He, then, who maintains such a doctrine, is the
most blasphemous of mankind.

And now our three points are proven; and we are agreed (1) that there are
Gods, (2) that they care for men, (3) that they cannot be bribed to do
injustice.  I have spoken warmly, from a fear lest this impiety of theirs
should lead to a perversion of life.  And our warmth will not have been in
vain, if we have succeeded in persuading these men to abominate themselves,
and to change their ways.  'So let us hope.'  Then now that the preamble is
completed, we will make a proclamation commanding the impious to renounce
their evil ways; and in case they refuse, the law shall be added:--If a man
is guilty of impiety in word or deed, let the bystander inform the
magistrates, and let the magistrates bring the offender before the court;
and if any of the magistrates refuses to act, he likewise shall be tried
for impiety.  Any one who is found guilty of such an offence shall be fined
at the discretion of the court, and shall also be punished by a term of
imprisonment.  There shall be three prisons--one for common offences
against life and property; another, near by the spot where the Nocturnal
Council will assemble, which is to be called the 'House of Reformation';
the third, to be situated in some desolate region in the centre of the
country, shall be called by a name indicating retribution.  There are three
causes of impiety, and from each of them spring impieties of two kinds, six
in all.  First, there is the impiety of those who deny the existence of the
Gods; these may be honest men, haters of evil, who are only dangerous
because they talk loosely about the Gods and make others like themselves;
but there is also a more vicious class, who are full of craft and
licentiousness.  To this latter belong diviners, jugglers, despots,
demagogues, generals, hierophants of private mysteries, and sophists.  The
first class shall be only imprisoned and admonished.  The second class
should be put to death, if they could be, many times over.  The two other
sorts of impiety, first of those who deny the care of the Gods, and
secondly, of those who affirm that they may be propitiated, have similar
subdivisions, varying in degree of guilt.  Those who have learnt to
blaspheme from mere ignorance shall be imprisoned in the House of
Reformation for five years at least, and not allowed to see any one but
members of the Nocturnal Council, who shall converse with them touching
their souls health.  If any of the prisoners come to their right mind, at
the end of five years let them be restored to sane company; but he who
again offends shall die.  As to that class of monstrous natures who not
only believe that the Gods are negligent, or may be propitiated, but
pretend to practise on the souls of quick and dead, and promise to charm
the Gods, and to effect the ruin of houses and states--he, I say, who is
guilty of these things, shall be bound in the central prison, and shall
have no intercourse with any freeman, receiving only his daily rations of
food from the public slaves; and when he dies, let him be cast beyond the
border; and if any freeman assist to bury him, he shall be liable to a suit
for impiety.  But the sins of the father shall not be visited upon his
children, who, like other orphans, shall be educated by the state. 
Further, let there be a general law which will have a tendency to repress
impiety.  No man shall have religious services in his house, but he shall
go with his friends to pray and sacrifice in the temples.  The reason of
this is, that religious institutions can only be framed by a great
intelligence.  But women and weak men are always consecrating the event of
the moment; they are under the influence of dreams and apparitions, and
they build altars and temples in every village and in any place where they
have had a vision.  The law is designed to prevent this, and also to deter
men from attempting to propitiate the Gods by secret sacrifices, which only
multiply their sins.  Therefore let the law run:--No one shall have private
religious rites; and if a man or woman who has not been previously noted
for any impiety offend in this way, let them be admonished to remove their
rites to a public temple; but if the offender be one of the obstinate sort,
he shall be brought to trial before the guardians, and if he be found
guilty, let him die.

BOOK XI.  As to dealings between man and man, the principle of them is
simple--Thou shalt not take what is not thine; and shalt do to others as
thou wouldst that they should do to thee.  First, of treasure trove:--May I
never desire to find, or lift, if I find, or be induced by the counsel of
diviners to lift, a treasure which one who was not my ancestor has laid
down; for I shall not gain so much in money as I shall lose in virtue.  The
saying, 'Move not the immovable,' may be repeated in a new sense; and there
is a common belief which asserts that such deeds prevent a man from having
a family.  To him who is careless of such consequences, and, despising the
word of the wise, takes up a treasure which is not his--what will be done
by the hand of the Gods, God only knows,--but I would have the first person
who sees the offender, inform the wardens of the city or the country; and
they shall send to Delphi for a decision, and whatever the oracle orders,
they shall carry out.  If the informer be a freeman, he shall be honoured,
and if a slave, set free; but he who does not inform, if he be a freeman,
shall be dishonoured, and if a slave, shall be put to death.  If a man
leave anywhere anything great or small, intentionally or unintentionally,
let him who may find the property deem the deposit sacred to the Goddess of
ways.  And he who appropriates the same, if he be a slave, shall be beaten
with many stripes; if a freeman, he shall pay tenfold, and be held to have
done a dishonourable action.  If a person says that another has something
of his, and the other allows that he has the property in dispute, but
maintains it to be his own, let the ownership be proved out of the
registers of property.  If the property is registered as belonging to some
one who is absent, possession shall be given to him who offers sufficient
security on behalf of the absentee; or if the property is not registered,
let it remain with the three eldest magistrates, and if it should be an
animal, the defeated party must pay the cost of its keep.  A man may arrest
his own slave, and he may also imprison for safe-keeping the runaway slave
of a friend.  Any one interfering with him must produce three sureties;
otherwise, he will be liable to an action for violence, and if he be cast,
must pay a double amount of damages to him from whom he has taken the
slave.  A freedman who does not pay due respect to his patron, may also be
seized.  Due respect consists in going three times a month to the house of
his patron, and offering to perform any lawful service for him; he must
also marry as his master pleases; and if his property be greater than his
master's, he must hand over to him the excess.  A freedman may not remain
in the state, except with the consent of the magistrates and of his master,
for more than twenty years; and whenever his census exceeds that of the
third class, he must in any case leave the country within thirty days,
taking his property with him.  If he break this regulation, the penalty
shall be death, and his property shall be confiscated.  Suits about these
matters are to be decided in the courts of the tribes, unless the parties
have settled the matter before a court of neighbours or before arbiters. 
If anybody claim a beast, or anything else, let the possessor refer to the
seller or giver of the property within thirty days, if the latter reside in
the city, or, if the goods have been received from a stranger, within five
months, of which the middle month shall include the summer solstice.  All
purchases and exchanges are to be made in the agora, and paid for on the
spot; the law will not allow credit to be given.  No law shall protect the
money subscribed for clubs.  He who sells anything of greater value than
fifty drachmas shall abide in the city for ten days, and let his
whereabouts be known to the buyer, in case of any reclamation.  When a
slave is sold who is subject to epilepsy, stone, or any other invisible
disorder, the buyer, if he be a physician or trainer, or if he be warned,
shall have no redress; but in other cases within six months, or within
twelve months in epileptic disorders, he may bring the matter before a jury
of physicians to be agreed upon by both parties; and the seller who loses
the suit, if he be an expert, shall pay twice the price; or if he be a
private person, the bargain shall be rescinded, and he shall simply refund. 
If a person knowingly sells a homicide to another, who is informed of his
character, there is no redress.  But if the judges--who are to be the five
youngest guardians of the law--decide that the purchaser was not aware,
then the seller is to pay threefold, and to purify the house of the buyer.

He who exchanges money for money, or beast for beast, must warrant either
of them to be sound and good.  As in the case of other laws, let us have a
preamble, relating to all this class of crime.  Adulteration is a kind of
falsehood about which the many commonly say that at proper times the
practice may often be right, but they do not define at what times.  But the
legislator will tell them, that no man should invoke the Gods when he is
practising deceit or fraud, in word or deed.  For he is the enemy of
heaven, first, who swears falsely, not thinking of the Gods by whom he
swears, and secondly, he who lies to his superiors.  (Now the superiors are
the betters of inferiors,--the elder of the younger, parents of children,
men of women, and rulers of subjects.)  The trader who cheats in the agora
is a liar and is perjured--he respects neither the name of God nor the
regulations of the magistrates.  If after hearing this he will still be
dishonest, let him listen to the law:--The seller shall not have two prices
on the same day, neither must he puff his goods, nor offer to swear about
them.  If he break the law, any citizen not less than thirty years of age
may smite him.  If he sell adulterated goods, the slave or metic who
informs against him shall have the goods; the citizen who brings such a
charge, if he prove it, shall offer up the goods in question to the Gods of
the agora; or if he fail to prove it, shall be dishonoured.  He who is
detected in selling adulterated goods shall be deprived of them, and shall
receive a stripe for every drachma of their value.  The wardens of the
agora and the guardians of the law shall take experienced persons into
counsel, and draw up regulations for the agora.  These shall be inscribed
on a column in front of the court of the wardens of the agora.--As to the
wardens of the city, enough has been said already.  But if any omissions in
the law are afterwards discovered, the wardens and the guardians shall
supply them, and have them inscribed after the original regulations on a
column before the court of the wardens of the city.

Next in order follows the subject of retail trades, which in their natural
use are the reverse of mischievous; for every man is a benefactor who
reduces what is unequal to symmetry and proportion.  Money is the
instrument by which this is accomplished, and the shop-keeper, the
merchant, and hotel-keeper do but supply the wants and equalize the
possessions of mankind.  Why, then, does any dishonour attach to a
beneficent occupation?  Let us consider the nature of the accusation first,
and then see whether it can be removed.  'What is your drift?'  Dear
Cleinias, there are few men who are so gifted by nature, and improved by
education, as to be able to control the desire of making money; or who are
sober in their wishes and prefer moderation to accumulation.  The great
majority think that they can never have enough, and the consequence is that
retail trade has become a reproach.  Whereas, however ludicrous the idea
may seem, if noble men and noble women could be induced to open a shop, and
to trade upon incorruptible principles, then the aspect of things would
change, and retail traders would be regarded as nursing fathers and
mothers.  In our own day the trader goes and settles in distant places, and
receives the weary traveller hospitably at first, but in the end treats him
as an enemy and a captive, whom he only liberates for an enormous ransom. 
This is what has brought retail trade into disrepute, and against this the
legislator ought to provide.  Men have said of old, that to fight against
two opponents is hard; and the two opponents of whom I am thinking are
wealth and poverty--the one corrupting men by luxury; the other, through
misery, depriving them of the sense of shame.  What remedies can a city
find for this disease?  First, to have as few retail traders as possible;
secondly, to give retail trade over to a class whose corruption will not
injure the state; and thirdly, to restrain the insolence and meanness of
the retailers.

Let us make the following laws:--(1) In the city of the Magnetes none of
the 5040 citizens shall be a retailer or merchant, or do any service to any
private persons who do not equally serve him, except to his father and
mother and their fathers and mothers, and generally to his elders who are
freemen, and whom he serves as a freeman.  He who follows an illiberal
pursuit may be cited for dishonouring his family, and kept in bonds for a
year; and if he offend again, he shall be bound for two years; and for
every offence his punishment shall be doubled:  (2) Every retailer shall be
a metic or a foreigner:  (3) The guardians of the law shall have a special
care of this part of the community, whose calling exposes them to peculiar
temptations.  They shall consult with persons of experience, and find out
what prices will yield the traders a moderate profit, and fix them.

When a man does not fulfil his contract, he being under no legal or other
impediment, the case shall be brought before the court of the tribes, if
not previously settled by arbitration.  The class of artisans is
consecrated to Hephaestus and Athene; the makers of weapons to Ares and
Athene:  all of whom, remembering that the Gods are their ancestors, should
be ashamed to deceive in the practice of their craft.  If any man is lazy
in the fulfilment of his work, and fancies, foolish fellow, that his patron
God will not deal hardly with him, he will be punished by the God; and let
the law follow:--He who fails in his undertaking shall pay the value, and
do the work gratis in a specified time.  The contractor, like the seller,
is enjoined by law to charge the simple value of his work; in a free city,
art should be a true thing, and the artist must not practise on the
ignorance of others.  On the other hand, he who has ordered any work and
does not pay the workman according to agreement, dishonours Zeus and
Athene, and breaks the bonds of society.  And if he does not pay at the
time agreed, let him pay double; and although interest is forbidden in
other cases, let the workman receive after the expiration of a year
interest at the rate of an obol a month for every drachma (equal to 200 per
cent. per ann.).  And we may observe by the way, in speaking of craftsmen,
that if our military craft do their work well, the state will praise those
who honour them, and blame those who do not honour them.  Not that the
first place of honour is to be assigned to the warrior; a higher still is
reserved for those who obey the laws.

Most of the dealings between man and man are now settled, with the
exception of such as relate to orphans and guardianships.  These lead us to
speak of the intentions of the dying, about which we must make regulations. 
I say 'must'; for mankind cannot be allowed to dispose of their property as
they please, in ways at variance with one another and with law and custom. 
But a dying person is a strange being, and is not easily managed; he wants
to be master of all he has, and is apt to use angry words.  He will say,--
'May I not do what I will with my own, and give much to my friends, and
little to my enemies?'  'There is reason in that.'  O Cleinias, in my
judgment the older lawgivers were too soft-hearted, and wanting  in insight
into human affairs.  They were too ready to listen to the outcry of a dying
man, and hence they were induced to give him an absolute power of bequest.
But I would say to him:--O creature of a day, you know neither what is
yours nor yourself:  for you and your property are not your own, but belong
to your whole family, past and to come, and property and family alike
belong to the State.  And therefore I must take out of your hands the
charge of what you leave behind you, with a view to the interests of all. 
And I hope that you will not quarrel with us, now that you are going the
way of all mankind; we will do our best for you and yours when you are no
longer here.  Let this be our address to the living and dying, and let the
law be as follows:--The father who has sons shall appoint one of them to be
the heir of the lot; and if he has given any other son to be adopted by
another, the adoption shall also be recorded; and if he has still a son who
has no lot, and has a chance of going to a colony, he may give him what he
has more than the lot; or if he has more than one son unprovided for, he
may divide the money between them.  A son who has a house of his own, and a
daughter who is betrothed, are not to share in the bequest of money; and
the son or daughter who, having inherited one lot, acquires another, is to
bequeath the new inheritance to the next of kin.  If a man have only
daughters, he may adopt the husband of any one of them; or if he have lost
a son, let him make mention of the circumstance in his will and adopt
another.  If he have no children, he may give away a tenth of his acquired
property to whomsoever he likes; but he must adopt an heir to inherit the
lot, and may leave the remainder to him.  Also he may appoint guardians for
his children; or if he die without appointing them or without making a
will, the nearest kinsmen,--two on the father's and two on the mother's
side,--and one friend of the departed, shall be appointed guardians.  The
fifteen eldest guardians of the law are to have special charge of all
orphans, the whole number of fifteen being divided into bodies of three,
who will succeed one another according to seniority every year for five
years.  If a man dying intestate leave daughters, he must pardon the law
which marries them for looking, first to kinship, and secondly to the
preservation of the lot.  The legislator cannot regard the character of the
heir, which to the father is the first consideration.  The law will
therefore run as follows:--If the intestate leave daughters, husbands are
to be found for them among their kindred according to the following table
of affinity:  first, their father's brothers; secondly, the sons of their
father's brothers; thirdly, of their father's sisters; fourthly, their
great-uncles; fifthly, the sons of a great-uncle; sixthly, the sons of a
great-aunt.  The kindred in such cases shall always be reckoned in this
way; the relationship shall proceed upwards through brothers and sisters
and brothers' and sisters' children, and first the male line must be taken
and then the female.  If there is a dispute in regard to fitness of age for
marriage, this the judge shall decide, after having made an inspection of
the youth naked, and of the maiden naked down to the waist.  If the maiden
has no relations within the degree of third cousin, she may choose whom she
likes, with the consent of her guardians; or she may even select some one
who has gone to a colony, and he, if he be a kinsman, will take the lot by
law; if not, he must have her guardians' consent, as well as hers.  When a
man dies without children and without a will, let a young man and a young
woman go forth from the family and take up their abode in the desolate
house.  The woman shall be selected from the kindred in the following order
of succession:--first, a sister of the deceased; second, a brother's
daughter; third, a sister's daughter; fourth, a father's sister; fifth, a
daughter of a father's brother; sixth, a daughter of a father's sister. 
For the man the same order shall be observed as in the preceding case.  The
legislator foresees that laws of this kind will sometimes press heavily,
and that his intention cannot always be fulfilled; as for example, when
there are mental and bodily defects in the persons who are enjoined to
marry.  But he must be excused for not being always able to reconcile the
general principles of public interest with the particular circumstances of
individuals; and he is willing to allow, in like manner, that the
individual cannot always do what the lawgiver wishes.  And then arbiters
must be chosen, who will determine equitably the cases which may arise
under the law:  e.g. a rich cousin may sometimes desire a grander match, or
the requirements of the law can only be fulfilled by marrying a madwoman. 
To meet such cases let the following law be enacted:--If any one comes
forward and says that the lawgiver, had he been alive, would not have
required the carrying out of the law in a particular case, let him go to
the fifteen eldest guardians of the law who have the care of orphans; but
if he thinks that too much power is thus given to them, he may bring the
case before the court of select judges.

Thus will orphans have a second birth.  In order to make their sad
condition as light as possible, the guardians of the law shall be their
parents, and shall be admonished to take care of them.  And what admonition
can be more appropriate than the assurance which we formerly gave, that the
souls of the dead watch over mortal affairs?  About this there are many
ancient traditions, which may be taken on trust from the legislator.  Let
men fear, in the first place, the Gods above; secondly, the souls of the
departed, who naturally care for their own descendants; thirdly, the aged
living, who are quick to hear of any neglect of family duties, especially
in the case of orphans.  For they are the holiest and most sacred of all
deposits, and the peculiar care of guardians and magistrates; and those who
try to bring them up well will contribute to their own good and to that of
their families.  He who listens to the preamble of the law will never know
the severity of the legislator; but he who disobeys, and injures the
orphan, will pay twice the penalty he would have paid if the parents had
been alive.  More laws might have been made about orphans, did we not
suppose that the guardians have children and property of their own which
are protected by the laws; and the duty of the guardian in our state is the
same as that of a father, though his honour or disgrace is greater.  A
legal admonition and threat may, however, be of service:  the guardian of
the orphan and the guardian of the law who is over him, shall love the
orphan as their own children, and take more care of his or her property
than of their own.  If the guardian of the child neglect his duty, the
guardian of the law shall fine him; and the guardian may also have the
magistrate tried for neglect in the court of select judges, and he shall
pay, if convicted, a double penalty.  Further, the guardian of the orphan
who is careless or dishonest may be fined on the information of any of the
citizens in a fourfold penalty, half to go to the orphan and half to the
prosecutor of the suit.  When the orphan is of age, if he thinks that he
has been ill-used, his guardian may be brought to trial by him within five
years, and the penalty shall be fixed by the court.  Or if the magistrate
has neglected the orphan, he shall pay damages to him; but if he have
defrauded him, he shall make compensation and also be deposed from his
office of guardian of the law.

If irremediable differences arise between fathers and sons, the father may
want to renounce his son, or the son may indict his father for imbecility: 
such violent separations only take place when the family are 'a bad lot';
if only one of the two parties is bad, the differences do not grow to so
great a height.  But here arises a difficulty.  Although in any other state
a son who is disinherited does not cease to be a citizen, in ours he does;
for the number of citizens cannot exceed 5040.  And therefore he who is to
suffer such a penalty ought to be abjured, not only by his father, but by
the whole family.  The law, then, should run as follows:--If any man's evil
fortune or temper incline him to disinherit his son, let him not do so
lightly or on the instant; but let him have a council of his own relations
and of the maternal relations of his son, and set forth to them the
propriety of disinheriting him, and allow his son to answer.  And if more
than half of the kindred male and female, being of full age, condemn the
son, let him be disinherited.  If any other citizen desires to adopt him,
he may, for young men's characters often change in the course of life.  But
if, after ten years, he remains unadopted, let him be sent to a colony.  If
disease, or old age, or evil disposition cause a man to go out of his mind,
and he is ruining his house and property, and his son doubts about
indicting him for insanity, let him lay the case before the eldest
guardians of the law, and consult with them.  And if they advise him to
proceed, and the father is decided to be imbecile, he shall have no more
control over his property, but shall live henceforward like a child in the
house.

If a man and his wife are of incompatible tempers, ten guardians of the law
and ten of the matrons who regulate marriage shall take their case in hand,
and reconcile them, if possible.  If, however, their swelling souls cannot
be pacified, the wife may try and find a new husband, and the husband a new
wife; probably they are not very gentle creatures, and should therefore be
joined to milder natures.  The younger of those who are separated should
also select their partners with a view to the procreation of children;
while the older should seek a companion for their declining years.  If a
woman dies, leaving children male or female, the law will advise, but not
compel, the widower to abstain from a second marriage; if she leave no
children, he shall be compelled to marry.  Also a widow, if she is not old
enough to live honestly without marriage, shall marry again; and in case
she have no children, she should marry for the sake of them.  There is
sometimes an uncertainty which parent the offspring is to follow:  in
unions of a female slave with a male slave, or with a freedman or free man,
or of a free woman with a male slave, the offspring is to belong to the
master; but if the master or mistress be themselves the parent of the
child, the slave and the child are to be sent away to another land.

Concerning duty to parents, let the preamble be as follows:--We honour the
Gods in their lifeless images, and believe that we thus propitiate them. 
But he who has an aged father or mother has a living image, which if he
cherish it will do him far more good than any statue.  'What do you mean by
cherishing them?'  I will tell you.  Oedipus and Amyntor and Theseus cursed
their children, and their curses took effect.  This proves that the Gods
hear the curses of parents who are wronged; and shall we doubt that they
hear and fulfil their blessings too?'  'Surely not.'  And, as we were
saying, no image is more honoured by the Gods than an aged father and
mother, to whom when honour is done, the God who hears their prayers is
rejoiced, and their influence is greater than that of the lifeless statue;
for they pray that good or evil may come to us in proportion as they are
honoured or dishonoured, but the statue is silent.  'Excellent.'  Good men
are glad when their parents live to extreme old age, or if they depart
early, lament their loss; but to bad man their parents are always terrible.
Wherefore let every one honour his parents, and if this preamble fails of
influencing him, let him hear the law:--If any one does not take sufficient
care of his parents, let the aggrieved person inform the three eldest
guardians of the law and three of the women who are concerned with
marriages.  Women up to forty years of age, and men up to thirty, who thus
offend, shall be beaten and imprisoned.  After that age they are to be
brought before a court composed of the eldest citizens, who may inflict any
punishment upon them which they please.  If the injured party cannot
inform, let any freeman who hears of the case inform; a slave who does so
shall be set free,--if he be the slave of the one of the parties, by the
magistrate,--if owned by another, at the cost of the state; and let the
magistrates, take care that he is not wronged by any one out of revenge.

The injuries which one person does to another by the use of poisons are of
two kinds;--one affects the body by the employment of drugs and potions;
the other works on the mind by the practice of sorcery and magic.  Fatal
cases of either sort have been already mentioned; and now we must have a
law respecting cases which are not fatal.  There is no use in arguing with
a man whose mind is disturbed by waxen images placed at his own door, or on
the sepulchre of his father or mother, or at a spot where three ways meet.
But to the wizards themselves we must address a solemn preamble, begging
them not to treat the world as if they were children, or compel the
legislator to expose them, and to show men that the poisoner who is not a
physician and the wizard who is not a prophet or diviner are equally
ignorant of what they are doing.  Let the law be as follows:--He who by the
use of poison does any injury not fatal to a man or his servants, or any
injury whether fatal or not to another's cattle or bees, is to be punished
with death if he be a physician, and if he be not a physician he is to
suffer the punishment awarded by the court:  and he who injures another by
sorcery, if he be a diviner or prophet, shall be put to death; and, if he
be not a diviner, the court shall determine what he ought to pay or suffer.

Any one who injures another by theft or violence shall pay damages at least
equal to the injury; and besides the compensation, a suitable punishment
shall be inflicted.  The foolish youth who is the victim of others is to
have a lighter punishment; he whose folly is occasioned by his own jealousy
or desire or anger is to suffer more heavily.  Punishment is to be
inflicted, not for the sake of vengeance, for what is done cannot be
undone, but for the sake of prevention and reformation.  And there should
be a proportion between the punishment and the crime, in which the judge,
having a discretion left him, must, by estimating the crime, second the
legislator, who, like a painter, furnishes outlines for him to fill up.

A madman is not to go about at large in the city, but is to be taken care
of by his relatives.  Neglect on their part is to be punished in the first
class by a fine of a hundred drachmas, and proportionally in the others. 
Now madness is of various kinds; in addition to that which arises from
disease there is the madness which originates in a passionate temperament,
and makes men when engaged in a quarrel use foul and abusive language
against each other.  This is intolerable in a well-ordered state; and
therefore our law shall be as follows:--No one is to speak evil of another,
but when men differ in opinion they are to instruct one another without
speaking evil.  Nor should any one seek to rouse the passions which
education has calmed; for he who feeds and nurses his wrath is apt to make
ribald jests at his opponent, with a loss of character or dignity to
himself.  And for this reason no one may use any abusive word in a temple,
or at sacrifices, or games, or in any public assembly, and he who offends
shall be censured by the proper magistrate; and the magistrate, if he fail
to censure him, shall not claim the prize of virtue.  In any other place
the angry man who indulges in revilings, whether he be the beginner or not,
may be chastised by an elder.  The reviler is always trying to make his
opponent ridiculous; and the use of ridicule in anger we cannot allow.  We
forbid the comic poet to ridicule our citizens, under a penalty of
expulsion from the country or a fine of three minae.  Jest in which there
is no offence may be allowed; but the question of offence shall be
determined by the director of education, who is to be the licenser of
theatrical performances.

The righteous man who is in adversity will not be allowed to starve in a
well-ordered city; he will never be a beggar.  Nor is a man to be pitied,
merely because he is hungry, unless he be temperate.  Therefore let the law
be as follows:--Let there be no beggars in our state; and he who begs shall
be expelled by the magistrates both from town and country.

If a slave, male or female, does any harm to the property of another, who
is not himself a party to the harm, the master shall compensate the injury
or give up the offending slave.  But if the master argue that the charge
has arisen by collusion, with the view of obtaining the slave, he may put
the plaintiff on his trial for malpractices, and recover from him twice the
value of the slave; or if he is cast he must make good the damage and
deliver up the slave.  The injury done by a horse or other animal shall be
compensated in like manner.

A witness who will not come of himself may be summoned, and if he fail in
appearing, he shall be liable for any harm which may ensue:  if he swears
that he does not know, he may leave the court.  A judge who is called upon
as a witness must not vote.  A free woman, if she is over forty, may bear
witness and plead, and, if she have no husband, she may also bring an
action.  A slave, male or female, and a child may witness and plead only in
case of murder, but they must give sureties that they will appear at the
trial, if they should be charged with false witness.  Such charges must be
made pending the trial, and the accusations shall be sealed by both parties
and kept by the magistrates until the trial for perjury comes off.  If a
man is twice convicted of perjury, he is not to be required, if three
times, he is not to be allowed to bear witness, or, if he persists in
bearing witness, is to be punished with death.  When more than half the
evidence is proved to be false there must be a new trial.

The best and noblest things in human life are liable to be defiled and
perverted.  Is not justice the civilizer of mankind?  And yet upon the
noble profession of the advocate has come an evil name.  For he is said to
make the worse appear the better cause, and only requires money in return
for his services.  Such an art will be forbidden by the legislator, and if
existing among us will be requested to depart to another city.  To the
disobedient let the voice of the law be heard saying:--He who tries to
pervert justice in the minds of the judges, or to increase litigation,
shall be brought before the supreme court.  If he does so from
contentiousness, let him be silenced for a time, and, if he offend again,
put to death.  If he have acted from a love of gain, let him be sent out of
the country if he be a foreigner, or if he be a citizen let him be put to
death.

BOOK XII.  If a false message be taken to or brought from other states,
whether friendly or hostile, by ambassadors or heralds, they shall be
indicted for having dishonoured their sacred office, and, if convicted,
shall suffer a penalty.--Stealing is mean; robbery is shameless.  Let no
man deceive himself by the supposed example of the Gods, for no God or son
of a God ever really practised either force or fraud.  On this point the
legislator is better informed than all the poets put together.  He who
listens to him shall be for ever happy, but he who will not listen shall
have the following law directed against him:--He who steals much, or he who
steals little of the public property is deserving of the same penalty; for
they are both impelled by the same evil motive.  When the law punishes one
man more lightly than another, this is done under the idea, not that he is
less guilty, but that he is more curable.  Now a thief who is a foreigner
or slave may be curable; but the thief who is a citizen, and has had the
advantages of education, should be put to death, for he is incurable.

Much consideration and many regulations are necessary about military
expeditions; the great principal of all is that no one, male or female, in
war or peace, in great matters or small, shall be without a commander. 
Whether men stand or walk, or drill, or pursue, or retreat, or wash, or
eat, they should all act together and in obedience to orders.  We should
practise from our youth upwards the habits of command and obedience.  All
dances, relaxations, endurances of meats and drinks, of cold and heat, and
of hard couches, should have a view to war, and care should be taken not to
destroy the natural covering and use of the head and feet by wearing shoes
and caps; for the head is the lord of the body, and the feet are the best
of servants.  The soldier should have thoughts like these; and let him hear
the law:--He who is enrolled shall serve, and if he absent himself without
leave he shall be indicted for failure of service before his own branch of
the army when the expedition returns, and if he be found guilty he shall
suffer the penalty which the courts award, and never be allowed to contend
for any prize of valour, or to accuse another of misbehaviour in military
matters.  Desertion shall also be tried and punished in the same manner. 
After the courts for trying failure of service and desertion have been
held, the generals shall hold another court, in which the several arms of
the service will award prizes for the expedition which has just concluded. 
The prize is to be a crown of olive, which the victor shall offer up at the
temple of his favourite war God...In any suit which a man brings, let the
indictment be scrupulously true, for justice is an honourable maiden, to
whom falsehood is naturally hateful.  For example, when men are prosecuted
for having lost their arms, great care should be taken by the witnesses to
distinguish between cases in which they have been lost from necessity and
from cowardice.  If the hero Patroclus had not been killed but had been
brought back alive from the field, he might have been reproached with
having lost the divine armour.  And a man may lose his arms in a storm at
sea, or from a fall, and under many other circumstances.  There is a
distinction of language to be observed in the use of the two terms,
'thrower away of a shield' (ripsaspis), and 'loser of arms' (apoboleus
oplon), one being the voluntary, the other the involuntary relinquishment
of them.  Let the law then be as follows:--If any one is overtaken by the
enemy, having arms in his hands, and he leaves them behind him voluntarily,
choosing base life instead of honourable death, let justice be done.  The
old legend of Caeneus, who was changed by Poseidon from a woman into a man,
may teach by contraries the appropriate punishment.  Let the thrower away
of his shield be changed from a man into a woman--that is to say, let him
be all his life out of danger, and never again be admitted by any commander
into the ranks of his army; and let him pay a heavy fine according to his
class.  And any commander who permits him to serve shall also be punished
by a fine.

All magistrates, whatever be their tenure of office, must give an account
of their magistracy.  But where shall we find the magistrate who is worthy
to supervise them or look into their short-comings and crooked ways?  The
examiner must be more than man who is sufficient for these things.  For the
truth is that there are many causes of the dissolution of states; which,
like ships or animals, have their cords, and girders, and sinews easily
relaxed, and nothing tends more to their welfare and preservation than the
supervision of them by examiners who are better than the magistrates;
failing in this they fall to pieces, and each becomes many instead of one.
Wherefore let the people meet after the summer solstice, in the precincts
of Apollo and the Sun, and appoint three men of not less than fifty years
of age.  They shall proceed as follows:--Each citizen shall select some
one, not himself, whom he thinks the best.  The persons selected shall be
reduced to one half, who have the greatest number of votes, if they are an
even number; but if an odd number, he who has the smallest number of votes
shall be previously withdrawn.  The voting shall continue in the same
manner until three only remain; and if the number of votes cast for them be
equal, a distinction between the first, second, and third shall be made by
lot.  The three shall be crowned with an olive wreath, and proclamation
made, that the city of the Magnetes, once more preserved by the Gods,
presents her three best men to Apollo and the Sun, to whom she dedicates
them as long as their lives answer to the judgment formed of them.  They
shall choose in the first year of their office twelve examiners, to
continue until they are seventy-five years of age; afterwards three shall
be added annually.  While they hold office, they shall dwell within the
precinct of the God.  They are to divide all the magistracies into twelve
classes, and may apply any methods of enquiry, and inflict any punishments
which they please; in some cases singly, in other cases together,
announcing the acquittal or punishment of the magistrate on a tablet which
they will place in the agora.  A magistrate who has been condemned by the
examiners may appeal to the select judges, and, if he gain his suit, may in
turn prosecute the examiners; but if the appellant is cast, his punishment
shall be doubled, unless he was previously condemned to death.

And what honours shall be paid to these examiners, whom the whole state
counts worthy of the rewards of virtue?  They shall have the first place at
all sacrifices and other ceremonies, and in all assemblies and public
places; they shall go on sacred embassies, and have the exclusive privilege
of wearing a crown of laurel.  They are priests of Apollo and the Sun, and
he of their number who is judged first shall be high priest, and give his
name to the year.  The manner of their burial, too, shall be different from
that of the other citizens.  The colour of their funeral array shall be
white, and, instead of the voice of lamentation, around the bier shall
stand a chorus of fifteen boys and fifteen maidens, chanting hymns in
honour of the deceased in alternate strains during an entire day; and at
dawn a band of a hundred youths shall carry the bier to the grave, marching
in the garb of warriors, and the boys in front of the bier shall sing their
national hymn, while the maidens and women past child-bearing follow after.
Priests and priestesses may also follow, unless the Pythian oracle forbids.
The sepulchre shall be a vault built underground, which will last for ever,
having couches of stone placed side by side; on one of these they shall lay
the departed saint, and then cover the tomb with a mound, and plant trees
on every side except one, where an opening shall be left for other
interments.  Every year there shall be games--musical, gymnastic, or
equestrian, in honour of those who have passed every ordeal.  But if any of
them, after having been acquitted on any occasion, begin to show the
wickedness of human nature, he who pleases may bring them to trial before a
court composed of the guardians of the law, and of the select judges, and
of any of the examiners who are alive.  If he be convicted he shall be
deprived of his honours, and if the accuser do not obtain a fifth part of
the votes, he shall pay a fine according to his class.

What is called the judgment of Rhadamanthus is suited to 'ages of faith,'
but not to our days.  He knew that his contemporaries believed in the Gods,
for many of them were the sons of Gods; and he thought that the easiest and
surest method of ending litigation was to commit the decision to Heaven. 
In our own day, men either deny the existence of Gods or their care of men,
or maintain that they may be bribed by attentions and gifts; and the
procedure of Rhadamanthus would therefore be out of date.  When the
religious ideas of mankind change, their laws should also change.  Thus
oaths should no longer be taken from plaintiff and defendant; simple
statements of affirmation and denial should be substituted.  For there is
something dreadful in the thought, that nearly half the citizens of a state
are perjured men.  There is no objection to an oath, where a man has no
interest in forswearing himself; as, for example, when a judge is about to
give his decision, or in voting at an election, or in the judgment of games
and contests.  But where there would be a premium on perjury, oaths and
imprecations should be prohibited as irrelevant, like appeals to feeling. 
Let the principles of justice be learned and taught without words of evil
omen.  The oaths of a stranger against a stranger may be allowed, because
strangers are not permitted to become permanent residents in our state.

Trials in private causes are to be decided in the same manner as lesser
offences against the state.  The non-attendance at a chorus or sacrifice,
or the omission to pay a war-tax, may be regarded as in the first instance
remediable, and the defaulter may give security; but if he forfeits the
security, the goods pledged shall be sold and the money given to the state.
And for obstinate disobedience, the magistrate shall have the power of
inflicting greater penalties.

A city which is without trade or commerce must consider what it will do
about the going abroad of its own people and the admission of strangers. 
For out of intercourse with strangers there arises great confusion of
manners, which in most states is not of any consequence, because the
confusion exists already; but in a well-ordered state it may be a great
evil.  Yet the absolute prohibition of foreign travel, or the exclusion of
strangers, is impossible, and would appear barbarous to the rest of
mankind.  Public opinion should never be lightly regarded, for the many are
not so far wrong in their judgments as in their lives.  Even the worst of
men have often a divine instinct, which enables them to judge of the
differences between the good and bad.  States are rightly advised when they
desire to have the praise of men; and the greatest and truest praise is
that of virtue.  And our Cretan colony should, and probably will, have a
character for virtue, such as few cities have.  Let this, then, be our law
about foreign travel and the reception of strangers:--No one shall be
allowed to leave the country who is under forty years of age--of course
military service abroad is not included in this regulation--and no one at
all except in a public capacity.  To the Olympic, and Pythian, and Nemean,
and Isthmian games, shall be sent the fairest and best and bravest, who
shall support the dignity of the city in time of peace.  These, when they
come home, shall teach the youth the inferiority of all other governments.
Besides those who go on sacred missions, other persons shall be sent out by
permission of the guardians to study the institutions of foreign countries. 
For a people which has no experience, and no knowledge of the characters of
men or the reason of things, but lives by habit only, can never be
perfectly civilized.  Moreover, in all states, bad as well as good, there
are holy and inspired men; these the citizen of a well-ordered city should
be ever seeking out; he should go forth to find them over sea and over
land, that he may more firmly establish institutions in his own state which
are good already and amend the bad.  'What will be the best way of
accomplishing such an object?'  In the first place, let the visitor of
foreign countries be between fifty and sixty years of age, and let him be a
citizen of repute, especially in military matters.  On his return he shall
appear before the Nocturnal Council:  this is a body which sits from dawn
to sunrise, and includes amongst its members the priests who have gained
the prize of virtue, and the ten oldest guardians of the law, and the
director and past directors of education; each of whom has power to bring
with him a younger friend of his own selection, who is between thirty and
forty.  The assembly thus constituted shall consider the laws of their own
and other states, and gather information relating to them.  Anything of the
sort which is approved by the elder members of the council shall be studied
with all diligence by the younger; who are to be specially watched by the
rest of the citizens, and shall receive honour, if they are deserving of
honour, or dishonour, if they prove inferior.  This is the assembly to
which the visitor of foreign countries shall come and tell anything which
he has heard from others in the course of his travels, or which he has
himself observed.  If he be made neither better nor worse, let him at least
be praised for his zeal; and let him receive still more praise, and special
honour after death, if he be improved.  But if he be deteriorated by his
travels, let him be prohibited from speaking to any one; and if he submit,
he may live as a private individual:  but if he be convicted of attempting
to make innovations in education and the laws, let him die.

Next, as to the reception of strangers.  Of these there are four classes:--
First, merchants, who, like birds of passage, find their way over the sea
at a certain time of the year, that they may exhibit their wares.  These
should be received in markets and public buildings without the city, by
proper officers, who shall see that justice is done them, and shall also
watch against any political designs which they may entertain; no more
intercourse is to be held with them than is absolutely necessary. 
Secondly, there are the visitors at the festivals, who shall be entertained
by hospitable persons at the temples for a reasonable time; the priests and
ministers of the temples shall have a care of them.  In small suits brought
by them or against them, the priests shall be the judges; but in the more
important, the wardens of the agora.  Thirdly, there are ambassadors of
foreign states; these are to be honourably received by the generals and
commanders, and placed under the care of the Prytanes and of the persons
with whom they are lodged.  Fourthly, there is the philosophical stranger,
who, like our own spectators, from time to time goes to see what is rich
and rare in foreign countries.  Like them he must be fifty years of age: 
and let him go unbidden to the doors of the wise and rich, that he may
learn from them, and they from him.

These are the rules of missions into foreign countries, and of the
reception of strangers.  Let Zeus, the God of hospitality, be honoured; and
let not the stranger be excluded, as in Egypt, from meals and sacrifices,
or, (as at Sparta,) driven away by savage proclamations.

Let guarantees be clearly given in writing and before witnesses.  The
number of witnesses shall be three when the sum lent is under a thousand
drachmas, or five when above.  The agent and principal at a fraudulent sale
shall be equally liable.  He who would search another man's house for
anything must swear that he expects to find it there; and he shall enter
naked, or having on a single garment and no girdle.  The owner shall place
at the disposal of the searcher all his goods, sealed as well as unsealed;
if he refuse, he shall be liable in double the value of the property, if it
shall prove to be in his possession.  If the owner be absent, the searcher
may counter-seal the property which is under seal, and place watchers. if
the owner remain absent more than five days, the searcher shall take the
magistrates, and open the sealed property, and seal it up again in their
presence.  The recovery of goods disputed, except in the case of lands and
houses, (about which there can be no dispute in our state), is to be barred
by time.  The public and unimpeached use of anything for a year in the
city, or for five years in the country, or the private possession and
domestic use for three years in the city, or for ten years in the country,
is to give a right of ownership.  But if the possessor have the property in
a foreign country, there shall be no bar as to time.  The proceedings of
any trial are to be void, in which either the parties or the witnesses,
whether bond or free, have been prevented by violence from attending:--if a
slave be prevented, the suit shall be invalid; or if a freeman, he who is
guilty of the violence shall be imprisoned for a year, and shall also be
liable to an action for kidnapping.  If one competitor forcibly prevents
another from attending at the games, the other may be inscribed as victor
in the temples, and the first, whether victor or not, shall be liable to an
action for damages.  The receiver of stolen goods shall undergo the same
punishment as the thief.  The receiver of an exile shall be punished with
death.  A man ought to have the same friends and enemies as his country;
and he who makes war or peace for himself shall be put to death.  And if a
party in the state make war or peace, their leaders shall be indicted by
the generals, and, if convicted, they shall be put to death.  The ministers
and officers of a country ought not to receive gifts, even as the reward of
good deeds.  He who disobeys shall die.

With a view to taxation a man should have his property and income valued: 
and the government may, at their discretion, levy the tax upon the annual
return, or take a portion of the whole.

The good man will offer moderate gifts to the Gods; his land or hearth
cannot be offered, because they are already consecrated to all Gods.  Gold
and silver, which arouse envy, and ivory, which is taken from the dead body
of an animal, are unsuitable offerings; iron and brass are materials of
war.  Wood and stone of a single piece may be offered; also woven work
which has not occupied one woman more than a month in making.  White is a
colour which is acceptable to the Gods; figures of birds and similar
offerings are the best of gifts, but they must be such as the painter can
execute in a day.

Next concerning lawsuits.  Judges, or rather arbiters, may be agreed upon
by the plaintiff and defendant; and if no decision is obtained from them,
their fellow-tribesmen shall judge.  At this stage there shall be an
increase of the penalty:  the defendant, if he be cast, shall pay a fifth
more than the damages claimed.  If he further persist, and appeal a second
time, the case shall be heard before the select judges; and he shall pay,
if defeated, the penalty and half as much again.  And the pursuer, if on
the first appeal he is defeated, shall pay one fifth of the damages claimed
by him; and if on the second, one half.  Other matters relating to trials,
such as the assignment of judges to courts, the times of sitting, the
number of judges, the modes of pleading and procedure, as we have already
said, may be determined by younger legislators.

These are to be the rules of private courts.  As regards public courts,
many states have excellent modes of procedure which may serve for models;
these, when duly tested by experience, should be ratified and made
permanent by us.

Let the judge be accomplished in the laws.  He should possess writings
about them, and make a study of them; for laws are the highest instrument
of mental improvement, and derive their name from mind (nous, nomos).  They
afford a measure of all censure and praise, whether in verse or prose, in
conversation or in books, and are an antidote to the vain disputes of men
and their equally vain acquiescence in each other's opinions.  The just
judge, who imbibes their spirit, makes the city and himself to stand
upright.  He establishes justice for the good, and cures the tempers of the
bad, if they can be cured; but denounces death, which is the only remedy,
to the incurable, the threads of whose life cannot be reversed.

When the suits of the year are completed, execution is to follow.  The
court is to award to the plaintiff the property of the defendant, if he is
cast, reserving to him only his lot of land.  If the plaintiff is not
satisfied within a month, the court shall put into his hands the property
of the defendant.  If the defendant fails in payment to the amount of a
drachma, he shall lose the use and protection of the court; or if he rebel
against the authority of the court, he shall be brought before the
guardians of the law, and if found guilty he shall be put to death.

Man having been born, educated, having begotten and brought up children,
and gone to law, fulfils the debt of nature.  The rites which are to be
celebrated after death in honour of the Gods above and below shall be
determined by the Interpreters.  The dead shall be buried in uncultivated
places, where they will be out of the way and do least injury to the
living.  For no one either in life or after death has any right to deprive
other men of the sustenance which mother earth provides for them.  No
sepulchral mound is to be piled higher than five men can raise it in five
days, and the grave-stone shall not be larger than is sufficient to contain
an inscription of four heroic verses.  The dead are only to be exposed for
three days, which is long enough to test the reality of death.  The
legislator will instruct the people that the body is a mere shadow or
image, and that the soul, which is our true being, is gone to give an
account of herself before the Gods below.  When they hear this, the good
are full of hope, and the evil are terrified.  It is also said that not
much can be done for any one after death.  And therefore while in life all
man should be helped by their kindred to pass their days justly and holily,
that they may depart in peace.  When a man loses a son or a brother, he
should consider that the beloved one has gone away to fulfil his destiny in
another place, and should not waste money over his lifeless remains.  Let
the law then order a moderate funeral of five minae for the first class, of
three for the second, of two for the third, of one for the fourth.  One of
the guardians of the law, to be selected by the relatives, shall assist
them in arranging the affairs of the deceased.  There would be a want of
delicacy in prescribing that there should or should not be mourning for the
dead.  But, at any rate, such mourning is to be confined to the house;
there must be no processions in the streets, and the dead body shall be
taken out of the city before daybreak.  Regulations about other forms of
burial and about the non-burial of parricides and other sacrilegious
persons have already been laid down.  The work of legislation is therefore
nearly completed; its end will be finally accomplished when we have
provided for the continuance of the state.

Do you remember the names of the Fates?  Lachesis, the giver of the lots,
is the first of them; Clotho, the spinster, the second; Atropos, the
unchanging one, is the third and last, who makes the threads of the web
irreversible.  And we too want to make our laws irreversible, for the
unchangeable quality in them will be the salvation of the state, and the
source of health and order in the bodies and souls of our citizens.  'But
can such a quality be implanted?'  I think that it may; and at any rate we
must try; for, after all our labour, to have been piling up a fabric which
has no foundation would be too ridiculous.  'What foundation would you
lay?'  We have already instituted an assembly which was composed of the ten
oldest guardians of the law, and secondly, of those who had received prizes
of virtue, and thirdly, of the travellers who had gone abroad to enquire
into the laws of other countries.  Moreover, each of the members was to
choose a young man, of not less than thirty years of age, to be approved by
the rest; and they were to meet at dawn, when all the world is at leisure.
This assembly will be an anchor to the vessel of state, and provide the
means of permanence; for the constitutions of states, like all other
things, have their proper saviours, which are to them what the head and
soul are to the living being.  'How do you mean?'  Mind in the soul, and
sight and hearing in the head, or rather, the perfect union of mind and
sense, may be justly called every man's salvation.  'Certainly.'  Yes; but
of what nature is this union?  In the case of a ship, for example, the
senses of the sailors are added to the intelligence of the pilot, and the
two together save the ship and the men in the ship.  Again, the physician
and the general have their objects; and the object of the one is health, of
the other victory.  States, too, have their objects, and the ruler must
understand, first, their nature, and secondly, the means of attaining them,
whether in laws or men.  The state which is wanting in this knowledge
cannot be expected to be wise when the time for action arrives.  Now what
class or institution is there in our state which has such a saving power? 
'I suspect that you are referring to the Nocturnal Council.'  Yes, to that
council which is to have all virtue, and which should aim directly at the
mark.  'Very true.'  The inconsistency of legislation in most states is not
surprising, when the variety of their objects is considered.  One of them
makes their rule of justice the government of a class; another aims at
wealth; another at freedom, or at freedom and power; and some who call
themselves philosophers maintain that you should seek for all of them at
once.  But our object is unmistakeably virtue, and virtue is of four kinds. 
'Yes; and we said that mind is the chief and ruler of the three other kinds
of virtue and of all else.'  True, Cleinias; and now, having already
declared the object which is present to the mind of the pilot, the general,
the physician, we will interrogate the mind of the statesman.  Tell me, I
say, as the physician and general have told us their object, what is the
object of the statesman.  Can you tell me?  'We cannot.'  Did we not say
that there are four virtues--courage, wisdom, and two others, all of which
are called by the common name of virtue, and are in a sense one? 
'Certainly we did.'  The difficulty is, not in understanding the
differences of the virtues, but in apprehending their unity.  Why do we
call virtue, which is a single thing, by the two names of wisdom and
courage?  The reason is that courage is concerned with fear, and is found
both in children and in brutes; for the soul may be courageous without
reason, but no soul was, or ever will be, wise without reason.  'That is
true.'  I have explained to you the difference, and do you in return
explain to me the unity.  But first let us consider whether any one who
knows the name of a thing without the definition has any real knowledge of
it.  Is not such knowledge a disgrace to a man of sense, especially where
great and glorious truths are concerned? and can any subject be more worthy
of the attention of our legislators than the four virtues of which we are
speaking--courage, temperance, justice, wisdom?  Ought not the magistrates
and officers of the state to instruct the citizens in the nature of virtue
and vice, instead of leaving them to be taught by some chance poet or
sophist?  A city which is without instruction suffers the usual fate of
cities in our day.  What then shall we do?  How shall we perfect the ideas
of our guardians about virtue? how shall we give our state a head and eyes? 
'Yes, but how do you apply the figure?'  The city will be the body or
trunk; the best of our young men will mount into the head or acropolis and
be our eyes; they will look about them, and inform the elders, who are the
mind and use the younger men as their instruments:  together they will save
the state.  Shall this be our constitution, or shall all be educated alike,
and the special training be given up?  'That is impossible.'  Let us then
endeavour to attain to some more exact idea of education.  Did we not say
that the true artist or guardian ought to have an eye, not only to the
many, but to the one, and to order all things with a view to the one?  Can
there be any more philosophical speculation than how to reduce many things
which are unlike to one idea?  'Perhaps not.'  Say rather, 'Certainly not.' 
And the rulers of our divine state ought to have an exact knowledge of the
common principle in courage, temperance, justice, wisdom, which is called
by the name of virtue; and unless we know whether virtue is one or many, we
shall hardly know what virtue is.  Shall we contrive some means of
engrafting this knowledge on our state, or give the matter up?  'Anything
rather than that.'  Let us begin by making an agreement.  'By all means, if
we can.'  Well, are we not agreed that our guardians ought to know, not
only how the good and the honourable are many, but also how they are one? 
'Yes, certainly.'  The true guardian of the laws ought to know their truth,
and should also be able to interpret and execute them?  'He should.'  And
is there any higher knowledge than the knowledge of the existence and power
of the Gods?  The people may be excused for following tradition; but the
guardian must be able to give a reason of the faith which is in him.  And
there are two great evidences of religion--the priority of the soul and the
order of the heavens.  For no man of sense, when he contemplates the
universe, will be likely to substitute necessity for reason and will. 
Those who maintain that the sun and the stars are inanimate beings are
utterly wrong in their opinions.  The men of a former generation had a
suspicion, which has been confirmed by later thinkers, that things
inanimate could never without mind have attained such scientific accuracy;
and some (Anaxagoras) even in those days ventured to assert that mind had
ordered all things in heaven; but they had no idea of the priority of mind,
and they turned the world, or more properly themselves, upside down, and
filled the universe with stones, and earth, and other inanimate bodies. 
This led to great impiety, and the poets said many foolish things against
the philosophers, whom they compared to 'yelping she-dogs,' besides making
other abusive remarks.  No man can now truly worship the Gods who does not
believe that the soul is eternal, and prior to the body, and the ruler of
all bodies, and does not perceive also that there is mind in the stars; or
who has not heard the connexion of these things with music, and has not
harmonized them with manners and laws, giving a reason of things which are
matters of reason.  He who is unable to acquire this knowledge, as well as
the ordinary virtues of a citizen, can only be a servant, and not a ruler
in the state.

Let us then add another law to the effect that the Nocturnal Council shall
be a guard set for the salvation of the state.  'Very good.'  To establish
this will be our aim, and I hope that others besides myself will assist. 
'Let us proceed along the road in which God seems to guide us.'  We cannot,
Megillus and Cleinias, anticipate the details which will hereafter be
needed; they must be supplied by experience.  'What do you mean?'  First of
all a register will have to be made of all those whose age, character, or
education would qualify them to be guardians.  The subjects which they are
to learn, and the order in which they are to be learnt, are mysteries which
cannot be explained beforehand, but not mysteries in any other sense.  'If
that is the case, what is to be done?'  We must stake our all on a lucky
throw, and I will share the risk by stating my views on education.  And I
would have you, Cleinias, who are the founder of the Magnesian state, and
will obtain the greatest glory if you succeed, and will at least be praised
for your courage, if you fail, take especial heed of this matter.  If we
can only establish the Nocturnal Council, we will hand over the city to its
keeping; none of the present company will hesitate about that.  Our dream
will then become a reality; and our citizens, if they are carefully chosen
and well educated, will be saviours and guardians such as the world
hitherto has never seen.

The want of completeness in the Laws becomes more apparent in the later
books.  There is less arrangement in them, and the transitions are more
abrupt from one subject to another.  Yet they contain several noble
passages, such as the 'prelude to the discourse concerning the honour and
dishonour of parents,' or the picture of the dangers attending the
'friendly intercourse of young men and maidens with one another,' or the
soothing remonstrance which is addressed to the dying man respecting his
right to do what he will with his own, or the fine description of the
burial of the dead.  The subject of religion in Book X is introduced as a
prelude to offences against the Gods, and this portion of the work appears
to be executed in Plato's best manner.

In the last four books, several questions occur for consideration:  among
them are (I) the detection and punishment of offences; (II) the nature of
the voluntary and involuntary; (III) the arguments against atheism, and
against the opinion that the Gods have no care of human affairs; (IV) the
remarks upon retail trade; (V) the institution of the Nocturnal Council.

I.  A weak point in the Laws of Plato is the amount of inquisition into
private life which is to be made by the rulers.  The magistrate is always
watching and waylaying the citizens.  He is constantly to receive
information against improprieties of life.  Plato does not seem to be aware
that espionage can only have a negative effect.  He has not yet discovered
the boundary line which parts the domain of law from that of morality or
social life.  Men will not tell of one another; nor will he ever be the
most honoured citizen, who gives the most frequent information about
offenders to the magistrates.

As in some writers of fiction, so also in philosophers, we may observe the
effect of age.  Plato becomes more conservative as he grows older, and he
would govern the world entirely by men like himself, who are above fifty
years of age; for in them he hopes to find a principle of stability.  He
does not remark that, in destroying the freedom he is destroying also the
life of the State.  In reducing all the citizens to rule and measure, he
would have been depriving the Magnesian colony of those great men 'whose
acquaintance is beyond all price;' and he would have found that in the
worst-governed Hellenic State, there was more of a carriere ouverte for
extraordinary genius and virtue than in his own.

Plato has an evident dislike of the Athenian dicasteries; he prefers a few
judges who take a leading part in the conduct of trials to a great number
who only listen in silence.  He allows of two appeals--in each case however
with an increase of the penalty.  Modern jurists would disapprove of the
redress of injustice being purchased only at an increasing risk; though
indirectly the burden of legal expenses, which seems to have been little
felt among the Athenians, has a similar effect.  The love of litigation,
which is a remnant of barbarism quite as much as a corruption of
civilization, and was innate in the Athenian people, is diminished in the
new state by the imposition of severe penalties.  If persevered in, it is
to be punished with death.

In the Laws murder and homicide besides being crimes, are also pollutions.
Regarded from this point of view, the estimate of such offences is apt to
depend on accidental circumstances, such as the shedding of blood, and not
on the real guilt of the offender or the injury done to society.  They are
measured by the horror which they arouse in a barbarous age.  For there is
a superstition in law as well as in religion, and the feelings of a
primitive age have a traditional hold on the mass of the people.  On the
other hand, Plato is innocent of the barbarity which would visit the sins
of the fathers upon the children, and he is quite aware that punishment has
an eye to the future, and not to the past.  Compared with that of most
European nations in the last century his penal code, though sometimes
capricious, is reasonable and humane.

A defect in Plato's criminal jurisprudence is his remission of the
punishment when the homicide has obtained the forgiveness of the murdered
person; as if crime were a personal affair between individuals, and not an
offence against the State.  There is a ridiculous disproportion in his
punishments.  Because a slave may fairly receive a blow for stealing one
fig or one bunch of grapes, or a tradesman for selling adulterated goods to
the value of one drachma, it is rather hard upon the slave that he should
receive as many blows as he has taken grapes or figs, or upon the tradesman
who has sold adulterated goods to the value of a thousand drachmas that he
should receive a thousand blows.

II.  But before punishment can be inflicted at all, the legislator must
determine the nature of the voluntary and involuntary.  The great question
of the freedom of the will, which in modern times has been worn threadbare
with purely abstract discussion, was approached both by Plato and
Aristotle--first, from the judicial; secondly, from the sophistical point
of view.  They were puzzled by the degrees and kinds of crime; they
observed also that the law only punished hurts which are inflicted by a
voluntary agent on an involuntary patient.

In attempting to distinguish between hurt and injury, Plato says that mere
hurt is not injury; but that a benefit when done in a wrong spirit may
sometimes injure, e.g. when conferred without regard to right and wrong, or
to the good or evil consequences which may follow.  He means to say that
the good or evil disposition of the agent is the principle which
characterizes actions; and this is not sufficiently described by the terms
voluntary and involuntary.  You may hurt another involuntarily, and no one
would suppose that you had injured him; and you may hurt him voluntarily,
as in inflicting punishment--neither is this injury; but if you hurt him
from motives of avarice, ambition, or cowardly fear, this is injury. 
Injustice is also described as the victory of desire or passion or self-
conceit over reason, as justice is the subordination of them to reason.  In
some paradoxical sense Plato is disposed to affirm all injustice to be
involuntary; because no man would do injustice who knew that it never paid
and could calculate the consequences of what he was doing.  Yet, on the
other hand, he admits that the distinction of voluntary and involuntary,
taken in another and more obvious sense, is the basis of legislation.  His
conception of justice and injustice is complicated (1) by the want of a
distinction between justice and virtue, that is to say, between the quality
which primarily regards others, and the quality in which self and others
are equally regarded; (2) by the confusion of doing and suffering justice;
(3) by the unwillingness to renounce the old Socratic paradox, that evil is
involuntary.

III.  The Laws rest on a religious foundation; in this respect they bear
the stamp of primitive legislation.  They do not escape the almost
inevitable consequence of making irreligion penal.  If laws are based upon
religion, the greatest offence against them must be irreligion.  Hence the
necessity for what in modern language, and according to a distinction which
Plato would scarcely have understood, might be termed persecution.  But the
spirit of persecution in Plato, unlike that of modern religious bodies,
arises out of the desire to enforce a true and simple form of religion, and
is directed against the superstitions which tend to degrade mankind.  Sir
Thomas More, in his Utopia, is in favour of tolerating all except the
intolerant, though he would not promote to high offices those who
disbelieved in the immortality of the soul.  Plato has not advanced quite
so far as this in the path of toleration.  But in judging of his
enlightenment, we must remember that the evils of necromancy and divination
were far greater than those of intolerance in the ancient world.  Human
nature is always having recourse to the first; but only when organized into
some form of priesthood falls into the other; although in primitive as in
later ages the institution of a priesthood may claim probably to be an
advance on some form of religion which preceded.  The Laws would have
rested on a sounder foundation, if Plato had ever distinctly realized to
his mind the difference between crime and sin or vice.  Of this, as of many
other controversies, a clear definition might have been the end.  But such
a definition belongs to a later age of philosophy.

The arguments which Plato uses for the being of a God, have an extremely
modern character:  first, the consensus gentium; secondly, the argument
which has already been adduced in the Phaedrus, of the priority of the
self-moved.  The answer to those who say that God 'cares not,' is, that He
governs by general laws; and that he who takes care of the great will
assuredly take care of the small.  Plato did not feel, and has not
attempted to consider, the difficulty of reconciling the special with the
general providence of God.  Yet he is on the road to a solution, when he
regards the world as a whole, of which all the parts work together towards
the final end.

We are surprised to find that the scepticism, which we attribute to young
men in our own day, existed then (compare Republic); that the Epicureanism
expressed in the line of Horace (borrowed from Lucretius)--

'Namque Deos didici securum agere aevum,'

was already prevalent in the age of Plato; and that the terrors of another
world were freely used in order to gain advantages over other men in this. 
The same objection which struck the Psalmist--'when I saw the prosperity of
the wicked'--is supposed to lie at the root of the better sort of unbelief. 
And the answer is substantially the same which the modern theologian would
offer:--that the ways of God in this world cannot be justified unless there
be a future state of rewards and punishments.  Yet this future state of
rewards and punishments is in Plato's view not any addition of happiness or
suffering imposed from without, but the permanence of good and evil in the
soul:  here he is in advance of many modern theologians.  The Greek, too,
had his difficulty about the existence of evil, which in one solitary
passage, remarkable for being inconsistent with his general system, Plato
explains, after the Magian fashion, by a good and evil spirit (compare
Theaet., Statesman).  This passage is also remarkable for being at variance
with the general optimism of the Tenth Book--not 'all things are ordered by
God for the best,' but some things by a good, others by an evil spirit.

The Tenth Book of the Laws presents a picture of the state of belief among
the Greeks singularly like that of the world in which we live.  Plato is
disposed to attribute the incredulity of his own age to several causes. 
First, to the bad effect of mythological tales, of which he retains his
disapproval; but he has a weak side for antiquity, and is unwilling, as in
the Republic, wholly to proscribe them.  Secondly, he remarks the self-
conceit of a newly-fledged generation of philosophers, who declare that the
sun, moon, and stars, are earth and stones only; and who also maintain that
the Gods are made by the laws of the state.  Thirdly, he notes a confusion
in the minds of men arising out of their misinterpretation of the
appearances of the world around them:  they do not always see the righteous
rewarded and the wicked punished.  So in modern times there are some whose
infidelity has arisen from doubts about the inspiration of ancient
writings; others who have been made unbelievers by physical science, or
again by the seemingly political character of religion; while there is a
third class to whose minds the difficulty of 'justifying the ways of God to
man' has been the chief stumblingblock.  Plato is very much out of temper
at the impiety of some of his contemporaries; yet he is determined to
reason with the victims, as he regards them, of these illusions before he
punishes them.  His answer to the unbelievers is twofold:  first, that the
soul is prior to the body; secondly, that the ruler of the universe being
perfect has made all things with a view to their perfection.  The
difficulties arising out of ancient sacred writings were far less serious
in the age of Plato than in our own.

We too have our popular Epicureanism, which would allow the world to go on
as if there were no God.  When the belief in Him, whether of ancient or
modern times, begins to fade away, men relegate Him, either in theory or
practice, into a distant heaven.  They do not like expressly to deny God
when it is more convenient to forget Him; and so the theory of the
Epicurean becomes the practice of mankind in general.  Nor can we be said
to be free from that which Plato justly considers to be the worst unbelief
--of those who put superstition in the place of true religion.  For the
larger half of Christians continue to assert that the justice of God may be
turned aside by gifts, and, if not by the 'odour of fat, and the sacrifice
steaming to heaven,' still by another kind of sacrifice placed upon the
altar--by masses for the quick and dead, by dispensations, by building
churches, by rites and ceremonies--by the same means which the heathen
used, taking other names and shapes.  And the indifference of Epicureanism
and unbelief is in two ways the parent of superstition, partly because it
permits, and also because it creates, a necessity for its development in
religious and enthusiastic temperaments.  If men cannot have a rational
belief, they will have an irrational.  And hence the most superstitious
countries are also at a certain point of civilization the most unbelieving,
and the revolution which takes one direction is quickly followed by a
reaction in the other.  So we may read 'between the lines' ancient history
and philosophy into modern, and modern into ancient.  Whether we compare
the theory of Greek philosophy with the Christian religion, or the practice
of the Gentile world with the practice of the Christian world, they will be
found to differ more in words and less in reality than we might have
supposed.  The greater opposition which is sometimes made between them
seems to arise chiefly out of a comparison of the ideal of the one with the
practice of the other.

To the errors of superstition and unbelief Plato opposes the simple and
natural truth of religion; the best and highest, whether conceived in the
form of a person or a principle--as the divine mind or as the idea of good
--is believed by him to be the basis of human life.  That all things are
working together for good to the good and evil to the evil in this or in
some other world to which human actions are transferred, is the sum of his
faith or theology.  Unlike Socrates, he is absolutely free from
superstition.  Religion and morality are one and indivisible to him.  He
dislikes the 'heathen mythology,' which, as he significantly remarks, was
not tolerated in Crete, and perhaps (for the meaning of his words is not
quite clear) at Sparta.  He gives no encouragement to individual
enthusiasm; 'the establishment of religion could only be the work of a
mighty intellect.'  Like the Hebrews, he prohibits private rites; for the
avoidance of superstition, he would transfer all worship of the Gods to the
public temples.  He would not have men and women consecrating the accidents
of their lives.  He trusts to human punishments and not to divine
judgments; though he is not unwilling to repeat the old tradition that
certain kinds of dishonesty 'prevent a man from having a family.'  He
considers that the 'ages of faith' have passed away and cannot now be
recalled.  Yet he is far from wishing to extirpate the sentiment of
religion, which he sees to be common to all mankind--Barbarians as well as
Hellenes.  He remarks that no one passes through life without, sooner or
later, experiencing its power.  To which we may add the further remark that
the greater the irreligion, the more violent has often been the religious
reaction.

It is remarkable that Plato's account of mind at the end of the Laws goes
beyond Anaxagoras, and beyond himself in any of his previous writings. 
Aristotle, in a well-known passage (Met.) which is an echo of the Phaedo,
remarks on the inconsistency of Anaxagoras in introducing the agency of
mind, and yet having recourse to other and inferior, probably material
causes.  But Plato makes the further criticism, that the error of
Anaxagoras consisted, not in denying the universal agency of mind, but in
denying the priority, or, as we should say, the eternity of it.  Yet in the
Timaeus he had himself allowed that God made the world out of pre-existing
materials:  in the Statesman he says that there were seeds of evil in the
world arising out of the remains of a former chaos which could not be got
rid of; and even in the Tenth Book of the Laws he has admitted that there
are two souls, a good and evil.  In the Meno, the Phaedrus, and the Phaedo,
he had spoken of the recovery of ideas from a former state of existence. 
But now he has attained to a clearer point of view:  he has discarded these
fancies.  From meditating on the priority of the human soul to the body, he
has learnt the nature of soul absolutely.  The power of the best, of which
he gave an intimation in the Phaedo and in the Republic, now, as in the
Philebus, takes the form of an intelligence or person.  He no longer, like
Anaxagoras, supposes mind to be introduced at a certain time into the world
and to give order to a pre-existing chaos, but to be prior to the chaos,
everlasting and evermoving, and the source of order and intelligence in all
things.  This appears to be the last form of Plato's religious philosophy,
which might almost be summed up in the words of Kant, 'the starry heaven
above and the moral law within.'  Or rather, perhaps, 'the starry heaven
above and mind prior to the world.'

IV.  The remarks about retail trade, about adulteration, and about
mendicity, have a very modern character.  Greek social life was more like
our own than we are apt to suppose.  There was the same division of ranks,
the same aristocratic and democratic feeling, and, even in a democracy, the
same preference for land and for agricultural pursuits.  Plato may be
claimed as the first free trader, when he prohibits the imposition of
customs on imports and exports, though he was clearly not aware of the
importance of the principle which he enunciated.  The discredit of retail
trade he attributes to the rogueries of traders, and is inclined to believe
that if a nobleman would keep a shop, which heaven forbid! retail trade
might become honourable.  He has hardly lighted upon the true reason, which
appears to be the essential distinction between buyers and sellers, the one
class being necessarily in some degree dependent on the other.  When he
proposes to fix prices 'which would allow a moderate gain,' and to regulate
trade in several minute particulars, we must remember that this is by no
means so absurd in a city consisting of 5040 citizens, in which almost
every one would know and become known to everybody else, as in our own vast
population.  Among ourselves we are very far from allowing every man to
charge what he pleases.  Of many things the prices are fixed by law.  Do we
not often hear of wages being adjusted in proportion to the profits of
employers?  The objection to regulating them by law and thus avoiding the
conflicts which continually arise between the buyers and sellers of labour,
is not so much the undesirableness as the impossibility of doing so. 
Wherever free competition is not reconcileable either with the order of
society, or, as in the case of adulteration, with common honesty, the
government may lawfully interfere.  The only question is,--Whether the
interference will be effectual, and whether the evil of interference may
not be greater than the evil which is prevented by it.

He would prohibit beggars, because in a well-ordered state no good man
would be left to starve.  This again is a prohibition which might have been
easily enforced, for there is no difficulty in maintaining the poor when
the population is small.  In our own times the difficulty of pauperism is
rendered far greater, (1) by the enormous numbers, (2) by the facility of
locomotion, (3) by the increasing tenderness for human life and suffering. 
And the only way of meeting the difficulty seems to be by modern nations
subdividing themselves into small bodies having local knowledge and acting
together in the spirit of ancient communities (compare Arist. Pol.)

V.  Regarded as the framework of a polity the Laws are deemed by Plato to
be a decline from the Republic, which is the dream of his earlier years. 
He nowhere imagines that he has reached a higher point of speculation.  He
is only descending to the level of human things, and he often returns to
his original idea.  For the guardians of the Republic, who were the elder
citizens, and were all supposed to be philosophers, is now substituted a
special body, who are to review and amend the laws, preserving the spirit
of the legislator.  These are the Nocturnal Council, who, although they are
not specially trained in dialectic, are not wholly destitute of it; for
they must know the relation of particular virtues to the general principle
of virtue.  Plato has been arguing throughout the Laws that temperance is
higher than courage, peace than war, that the love of both must enter into
the character of the good citizen.  And at the end the same thought is
summed up by him in an abstract form.  The true artist or guardian must be
able to reduce the many to the one, than which, as he says with an
enthusiasm worthy of the Phaedrus or Philebus, 'no more philosophical
method was ever devised by the wit of man.'  But the sense of unity in
difference can only be acquired by study; and Plato does not explain to us
the nature of this study, which we may reasonably infer, though there is a
remarkable omission of the word, to be akin to the dialectic of the
Republic.

The Nocturnal Council is to consist of the priests who have obtained the
rewards of virtue, of the ten eldest guardians of the law, and of the
director and ex-directors of education; each of whom is to select for
approval a younger coadjutor.  To this council the 'Spectator,' who is sent
to visit foreign countries, has to make his report.  It is not an
administrative body, but an assembly of sages who are to make legislation
their study.  Plato is not altogether disinclined to changes in the law
where experience shows them to be necessary; but he is also anxious that
the original spirit of the constitution should never be lost sight of.

The Laws of Plato contain the latest phase of his philosophy, showing in
many respects an advance, and in others a decline, in his views of life and
the world.  His Theory of Ideas in the next generation passed into one of
Numbers, the nature of which we gather chiefly from the Metaphysics of
Aristotle.  Of the speculative side of this theory there are no traces in
the Laws, but doubtless Plato found the practical value which he attributed
to arithmetic greatly confirmed by the possibility of applying number and
measure to the revolution of the heavens, and to the regulation of human
life.  In the return to a doctrine of numbers there is a retrogression
rather than an advance; for the most barren logical abstraction is of a
higher nature than number and figure.  Philosophy fades away into the
distance; in the Laws it is confined to the members of the Nocturnal
Council.  The speculative truth which was the food of the guardians in the
Republic, is for the majority of the citizens to be superseded by practical
virtues.  The law, which is the expression of mind written down, takes the
place of the living word of the philosopher.  (Compare the contrast of
Phaedrus, and Laws; also the plays on the words nous, nomos, nou dianome;
and the discussion in the Statesman of the difference between the personal
rule of a king and the impersonal reign of law.)  The State is based on
virtue and religion rather than on knowledge; and virtue is no longer
identified with knowledge, being of the commoner sort, and spoken of in the
sense generally understood.  Yet there are many traces of advance as well
as retrogression in the Laws of Plato.  The attempt to reconcile the ideal
with actual life is an advance; to 'have brought philosophy down from
heaven to earth,' is a praise which may be claimed for him as well as for
his master Socrates.  And the members of the Nocturnal Council are to
continue students of the 'one in many' and of the nature of God.  Education
is the last word with which Plato supposes the theory of the Laws to end
and the reality to begin.

Plato's increasing appreciation of the difficulties of human affairs, and
of the element of chance which so largely influences them, is an indication
not of a narrower, but of a maturer mind, which had become more conversant
with realities.  Nor can we fairly attribute any want of originality to
him, because he has borrowed many of his provisions from Sparta and Athens.
Laws and institutions grow out of habits and customs; and they have 'better
opinion, better confirmation,' if they have come down from antiquity and
are not mere literary inventions.  Plato would have been the first to
acknowledge that the Book of Laws was not the creation of his fancy, but a
collection of enactments which had been devised by inspired legislators,
like Minos, Lycurgus, and Solon, to meet the actual needs of men, and had
been approved by time and experience.

In order to do justice therefore to the design of the work, it is necessary
to examine how far it rests on an historical foundation and coincides with
the actual laws of Sparta and Athens.  The consideration of the historical
aspect of the Laws has been reserved for this place.  In working out the
comparison the writer has been greatly assisted by the excellent essays of
C.F. Hermann ('De vestigiis institutorum veterum, imprimis Atticorum, per
Platonis de Legibus libros indagandis,' and 'Juris domestici et familiaris
apud Platonem in Legibus cum veteris Graeciae inque primis Athenarum
institutis comparatio':  Marburg, 1836), and by J.B. Telfy's 'Corpus Juris
Attici' (Leipzig, 1868).

EXCURSUS ON THE RELATION OF THE LAWS OF PLATO TO THE INSTITUTIONS OF CRETE
AND LACEDAEMON AND TO THE LAWS AND CONSTITUTION OF ATHENS.

The Laws of Plato are essentially Greek:  unlike Xenophon's Cyropaedia,
they contain nothing foreign or oriental.  Their aim is to reconstruct the
work of the great lawgivers of Hellas in a literary form.  They partake
both of an Athenian and a Spartan character.  Some of them too are derived
from Crete, and are appropriately transferred to a Cretan colony.  But of
Crete so little is known to us, that although, as Montesquieu (Esprit des
Lois) remarks, 'the Laws of Crete are the original of those of Sparta and
the Laws of Plato the correction of these latter,' there is only one point,
viz. the common meals, in which they can be compared.  Most of Plato's
provisions resemble the laws and customs which prevailed in these three
states (especially in the two former), and which the personifying instinct
of the Greeks attributed to Minos, Lycurgus, and Solon.  A very few
particulars may have been borrowed from Zaleucus (Cic. de Legibus), and
Charondas, who is said to have first made laws against perjury (Arist.
Pol.) and to have forbidden credit (Stob. Florileg., Gaisford).  Some
enactments are Plato's own, and were suggested by his experience of defects
in the Athenian and other Greek states.  The Laws also contain many lesser
provisions, which are not found in the ordinary codes of nations, because
they cannot be properly defined, and are therefore better left to custom
and common sense.  'The greater part of the work,' as Aristotle remarks
(Pol.), 'is taken up with laws':  yet this is not wholly true, and applies
to the latter rather than to the first half of it.  The book rests on an
ethical and religious foundation:  the actual laws begin with a hymn of
praise in honour of the soul.  And the same lofty aspiration after the good
is perpetually recurring, especially in Books X, XI, XII, and whenever
Plato's mind is filled with his highest themes.  In prefixing to most of
his laws a prooemium he has two ends in view, to persuade and also to
threaten.  They are to have the sanction of laws and the effect of sermons. 
And Plato's 'Book of Laws,' if described in the language of modern
philosophy, may be said to be as much an ethical and educational, as a
political or legal treatise.

But although the Laws partake both of an Athenian and a Spartan character,
the elements which are borrowed from either state are necessarily very
different, because the character and origin of the two governments
themselves differed so widely.  Sparta was the more ancient and primitive: 
Athens was suited to the wants of a later stage of society.  The relation
of the two states to the Laws may be conceived in this manner:--The
foundation and ground-plan of the work are more Spartan, while the
superstructure and details are more Athenian.  At Athens the laws were
written down and were voluminous; more than a thousand fragments of them
have been collected by Telfy.  Like the Roman or English law, they
contained innumerable particulars.  Those of them which regulated daily
life were familiarly known to the Athenians; for every citizen was his own
lawyer, and also a judge, who decided the rights of his fellow-citizens
according to the laws, often after hearing speeches from the parties
interested or from their advocates.  It is to Rome and not to Athens that
the invention of law, in the modern sense of the term, is commonly
ascribed.  But it must be remembered that long before the times of the
Twelve Tables (B.C. 451), regular courts and forms of law had existed at
Athens and probably in the Greek colonies.  And we may reasonably suppose,
though without any express proof of the fact, that many Roman institutions
and customs, like Latin literature and mythology, were partly derived from
Hellas and had imperceptibly drifted from one shore of the Ionian Sea to
the other (compare especially the constitutions of Servius Tullius and of
Solon).

It is not proved that the laws of Sparta were in ancient times either
written down in books or engraved on tablets of marble or brass.  Nor is it
certain that, if they had been, the Spartans could have read them.  They
were ancient customs, some of them older probably than the settlement in
Laconia, of which the origin is unknown; they occasionally received the
sanction of the Delphic oracle, but there was a still stronger obligation
by which they were enforced,--the necessity of self-defence:  the Spartans
were always living in the presence of their enemies.  They belonged to an
age when written law had not yet taken the place of custom and tradition. 
The old constitution was very rarely affected by new enactments, and these
only related to the duties of the Kings or Ephors, or the new relations of
classes which arose as time went on.  Hence there was as great a difference
as could well be conceived between the Laws of Athens and Sparta:  the one
was the creation of a civilized state, and did not differ in principle from
our modern legislation, the other of an age in which the people were held
together and also kept down by force of arms, and which afterwards retained
many traces of its barbaric origin 'surviving in culture.'

Nevertheless the Lacedaemonian was the ideal of a primitive Greek state. 
According to Thucydides it was the first which emerged out of confusion and
became a regular government.  It was also an army devoted to military
exercises, but organized with a view to self-defence and not to conquest. 
It was not quick to move or easily excited; but stolid, cautious,
unambitious, procrastinating.  For many centuries it retained the same
character which was impressed upon it by the hand of the legislator.  This
singular fabric was partly the result of circumstances, partly the
invention of some unknown individual in prehistoric times, whose ideal of
education was military discipline, and who, by the ascendency of his
genius, made a small tribe into a nation which became famous in the world's
history.  The other Hellenes wondered at the strength and stability of his
work.  The rest of Hellas, says Thucydides, undertook the colonisation of
Heraclea the more readily, having a feeling of security now that they saw
the Lacedaemonians taking part in it.  The Spartan state appears to us in
the dawn of history as a vision of armed men, irresistible by any other
power then existing in the world.  It can hardly be said to have understood
at all the rights or duties of nations to one another, or indeed to have
had any moral principle except patriotism and obedience to commanders.  Men
were so trained to act together that they lost the freedom and spontaneity
of human life in cultivating the qualities of the soldier and ruler.  The
Spartan state was a composite body in which kings, nobles, citizens,
perioeci, artisans, slaves, had to find a 'modus vivendi' with one another. 
All of them were taught some use of arms.  The strength of the family tie
was diminished among them by an enforced absence from home and by common
meals.  Sparta had no life or growth; no poetry or tradition of the past;
no art, no thought.  The Athenians started on their great career some
centuries later, but the Spartans would have been easily conquered by them,
if Athens had not been deficient in the qualities which constituted the
strength (and also the weakness) of her rival.

The ideal of Athens has been pictured for all time in the speech which
Thucydides puts into the mouth of Pericles, called the Funeral Oration.  He
contrasts the activity and freedom and pleasantness of Athenian life with
the immobility and severe looks and incessant drill of the Spartans.  The
citizens of no city were more versatile, or more readily changed from land
to sea or more quickly moved about from place to place.  They 'took their
pleasures' merrily, and yet, when the time for fighting arrived, were not a
whit behind the Spartans, who were like men living in a camp, and, though
always keeping guard, were often too late for the fray.  Any foreigner
might visit Athens; her ships found a way to the most distant shores; the
riches of the whole earth poured in upon her.  Her citizens had their
theatres and festivals; they 'provided their souls with many relaxations';
yet they were not less manly than the Spartans or less willing to sacrifice
this enjoyable existence for their country's good.  The Athenian was a
nobler form of life than that of their rivals, a life of music as well as
of gymnastic, the life of a citizen as well as of a soldier.  Such is the
picture which Thucydides has drawn of the Athenians in their glory.  It is
the spirit of this life which Plato would infuse into the Magnesian state
and which he seeks to combine with the common meals and gymnastic
discipline of Sparta.

The two great types of Athens and Sparta had deeply entered into his mind.
He had heard of Sparta at a distance and from common Hellenic fame:  he was
a citizen of Athens and an Athenian of noble birth.  He must often have sat
in the law-courts, and may have had personal experience of the duties of
offices such as he is establishing.  There is no need to ask the question,
whence he derived his knowledge of the Laws of Athens:  they were a part of
his daily life.  Many of his enactments are recognized to be Athenian laws
from the fragments preserved in the Orators and elsewhere:  many more would
be found to be so if we had better information.  Probably also still more
of them would have been incorporated in the Magnesian code, if the work had
ever been finally completed.  But it seems to have come down to us in a
form which is partly finished and partly unfinished, having a beginning and
end, but wanting arrangement in the middle.  The Laws answer to Plato's own
description of them, in the comparison which he makes of himself and his
two friends to gatherers of stones or the beginners of some composite work,
'who are providing materials and partly putting them together:--having some
of their laws, like stones, already fixed in their places, while others lie
about.'

Plato's own life coincided with the period at which Athens rose to her
greatest heights and sank to her lowest depths.  It was impossible that he
should regard the blessings of democracy in the same light as the men of a
former generation, whose view was not intercepted by the evil shadow of the
taking of Athens, and who had only the glories of Marathon and Salamis and
the administration of Pericles to look back upon.  On the other hand the
fame and prestige of Sparta, which had outlived so many crimes and
blunders, was not altogether lost at the end of the life of Plato.  Hers
was the only great Hellenic government which preserved something of its
ancient form; and although the Spartan citizens were reduced to almost one-
tenth of their original number (Arist. Pol.), she still retained, until the
rise of Thebes and Macedon, a certain authority and predominance due to her
final success in the struggle with Athens and to the victories which
Agesilaus won in Asia Minor.

Plato, like Aristotle, had in his mind some form of a mean state which
should escape the evils and secure the advantages of both aristocracy and
democracy.  It may however be doubted whether the creation of such a state
is not beyond the legislator's art, although there have been examples in
history of forms of government, which through some community of interest or
of origin, through a balance of parties in the state itself, or through the
fear of a common enemy, have for a while preserved such a character of
moderation.  But in general there arises a time in the history of a state
when the struggle between the few and the many has to be fought out.  No
system of checks and balances, such as Plato has devised in the Laws, could
have given equipoise and stability to an ancient state, any more than the
skill of the legislator could have withstood the tide of democracy in
England or France during the last hundred years, or have given life to
China or India.

The basis of the Magnesian constitution is the equal division of land.  In
the new state, as in the Republic, there was to be neither poverty nor
riches.  Every citizen under all circumstances retained his lot, and as
much money as was necessary for the cultivation of it, and no one was
allowed to accumulate property to the amount of more than five times the
value of the lot, inclusive of it.  The equal division of land was a
Spartan institution, not known to have existed elsewhere in Hellas.  The
mention of it in the Laws of Plato affords considerable presumption that it
was of ancient origin, and not first introduced, as Mr. Grote and others
have imagined, in the reformation of Cleomenes III.  But at Sparta, if we
may judge from the frequent complaints of the accumulation of property in
the hands of a few persons (Arist. Pol.), no provision could have been made
for the maintenance of the lot.  Plutarch indeed speaks of a law introduced
by the Ephor Epitadeus soon after the Peloponnesian War, which first
allowed the Spartans to sell their land (Agis):  but from the manner in
which Aristotle refers to the subject, we should imagine this evil in the
state to be of a much older standing.  Like some other countries in which
small proprietors have been numerous, the original equality passed into
inequality, and, instead of a large middle class, there was probably at
Sparta greater disproportion in the property of the citizens than in any
other state of Hellas.  Plato was aware of the danger, and has improved on
the Spartan custom.  The land, as at Sparta, must have been tilled by
slaves, since other occupations were found for the citizens.  Bodies of
young men between the ages of twenty-five and thirty were engaged in making
biennial peregrinations of the country.  They and their officers are to be
the magistrates, police, engineers, aediles, of the twelve districts into
which the colony was divided.  Their way of life may be compared with that
of the Spartan secret police or Crypteia, a name which Plato freely applies
to them without apparently any consciousness of the odium which has
attached to the word in history.

Another great institution which Plato borrowed from Sparta (or Crete) is
the Syssitia or common meals.  These were established in both states, and
in some respects were considered by Aristotle to be better managed in Crete
than at Lacedaemon (Pol.).  In the Laws the Cretan custom appears to be
adopted (This is not proved, as Hermann supposes ('De Vestigiis,' etc.)): 
that is to say, if we may interpret Plato by Aristotle, the cost of them
was defrayed by the state and not by the individuals (Arist. Pol); so that
the members of the mess, who could not pay their quota, still retained
their rights of citizenship.  But this explanation is hardly consistent
with the Laws, where contributions to the Syssitia from private estates are
expressly mentioned.  Plato goes further than the legislators of Sparta and
Crete, and would extend the common meals to women as well as men:  he
desires to curb the disorders, which existed among the female sex in both
states, by the application to women of the same military discipline to
which the men were already subject.  It was an extension of the custom of
Syssitia from which the ancient legislators shrank, and which Plato himself
believed to be very difficult of enforcement.

Like Sparta, the new colony was not to be surrounded by walls,--a state
should learn to depend upon the bravery of its citizens only--a fallacy or
paradox, if it is not to be regarded as a poetical fancy, which is fairly
enough ridiculed by Aristotle (Pol.).  Women, too, must be ready to assist
in the defence of their country:  they are not to rush to the temples and
altars, but to arm themselves with shield and spear.  In the regulation of
the Syssitia, in at least one of his enactments respecting property, and in
the attempt to correct the licence of women, Plato shows, that while he
borrowed from the institutions of Sparta and favoured the Spartan mode of
life, he also sought to improve upon them.

The enmity to the sea is another Spartan feature which is transferred by
Plato to the Magnesian state.  He did not reflect that a non-maritime power
would always be at the mercy of one which had a command of the great
highway.  Their many island homes, the vast extent of coast which had to be
protected by them, their struggles first of all with the Phoenicians and
Carthaginians, and secondly with the Persian fleets, forced the Greeks,
mostly against their will, to devote themselves to the sea.  The islanders
before the inhabitants of the continent, the maritime cities before the
inland, the Corinthians and Athenians before the Spartans, were compelled
to fit out ships:  last of all the Spartans, by the pressure of the
Peloponnesian War, were driven to establish a naval force, which, after the
battle of Aegospotami, for more than a generation commanded the Aegean. 
Plato, like the Spartans, had a prejudice against a navy, because he
regarded it as the nursery of democracy.  But he either never considered,
or did not care to explain, how a city, set upon an island and 'distant not
more than ten miles from the sea, having a seaboard provided with excellent
harbours,' could have safely subsisted without one.

Neither the Spartans nor the Magnesian colonists were permitted to engage
in trade or commerce.  In order to limit their dealings as far as possible
to their own country, they had a separate coinage; the Magnesians were only
allowed to use the common currency of Hellas when they travelled abroad,
which they were forbidden to do unless they received permission from the
government.  Like the Spartans, Plato was afraid of the evils which might
be introduced into his state by intercourse with foreigners; but he also
shrinks from the utter exclusiveness of Sparta, and is not unwilling to
allow visitors of a suitable age and rank to come from other states to his
own, as he also allows citizens of his own state to go to foreign countries
and bring back a report of them.  Such international communication seemed
to him both honourable and useful.

We may now notice some points in which the commonwealth of the Laws
approximates to the Athenian model.  These are much more numerous than the
previous class of resemblances; we are better able to compare the laws of
Plato with those of Athens, because a good deal more is known to us of
Athens than of Sparta.

The information which we possess about Athenian law, though comparatively
fuller, is still fragmentary.  The sources from which our knowledge is
derived are chiefly the following:--

(1)  The Orators,--Antiphon, Andocides, Lysias, Isocrates, Demosthenes,
Aeschines, Lycurgus, and others.

(2)  Herodotus, Thucydides, Xenophon, Plato, Aristotle, as well as later
writers, such as Cicero de Legibus, Plutarch, Aelian, Pausanias.

(3)  Lexicographers, such as Harpocration, Pollux, Hesychius, Suidas, and
the compiler of the Etymologicum Magnum, many of whom are of uncertain
date, and to a great extent based upon one another.  Their writings extend
altogether over more than eight hundred years, from the second to the tenth
century.

(4)  The Scholia on Aristophanes, Plato, Demosthenes.

(5)  A few inscriptions.

Our knowledge of a subject derived from such various sources and for the
most part of uncertain date and origin, is necessarily precarious.  No
critic can separate the actual laws of Solon from those which passed under
his name in later ages.  Nor do the Scholiasts and Lexicographers attempt
to distinguish how many of these laws were still in force at the time when
they wrote, or when they fell into disuse and were to be found in books
only.  Nor can we hastily assume that enactments which occur in the Laws of
Plato were also a part of Athenian law, however probable this may appear.

There are two classes of similarities between Plato's Laws and those of
Athens:  (i) of institutions (ii) of minor enactments.

(i)  The constitution of the Laws in its general character resembles much
more nearly the Athenian constitution of Solon's time than that which
succeeded it, or the extreme democracy which prevailed in Plato's own day. 
It was a mean state which he hoped to create, equally unlike a Syracusan
tyranny or the mob-government of the Athenian assembly.  There are various
expedients by which he sought to impart to it the quality of moderation. 
(1) The whole people were to be educated:  they could not be all trained in
philosophy, but they were to acquire the simple elements of music,
arithmetic, geometry, astronomy; they were also to be subject to military
discipline, archontes kai archomenoi.  (2) The majority of them were, or
had been at some time in their lives, magistrates, and had the experience
which is given by office.  (3) The persons who held the highest offices
were to have a further education, not much inferior to that provided for
the guardians in the Republic, though the range of their studies is
narrowed to the nature and divisions of virtue:  here their philosophy
comes to an end.  (4) The entire number of the citizens (5040) rarely, if
ever, assembled, except for purposes of elections.  The whole people were
divided into four classes, each having the right to be represented by the
same number of members in the Council.  The result of such an arrangement
would be, as in the constitution of Servius Tullius, to give a
disproportionate share of power to the wealthier classes, who may be
supposed to be always much fewer in number than the poorer.  This tendency
was qualified by the complicated system of selection by vote, previous to
the final election by lot, of which the object seems to be to hand over to
the wealthy few the power of selecting from the many poor, and vice versa. 
(5) The most important body in the state was the Nocturnal Council, which
is borrowed from the Areopagus at Athens, as it existed, or was supposed to
have existed, in the days before Ephialtes and the Eumenides of Aeschylus,
when its power was undiminished.  In some particulars Plato appears to have
copied exactly the customs and procedure of the Areopagus:  both assemblies
sat at night (Telfy).  There was a resemblance also in more important
matters.  Like the Areopagus, the Nocturnal Council was partly composed of
magistrates and other state officials, whose term of office had expired. 
(7) The constitution included several diverse and even opposing elements,
such as the Assembly and the Nocturnal Council.  (8)  There was much less
exclusiveness than at Sparta; the citizens were to have an interest in the
government of neighbouring states, and to know what was going on in the
rest of the world.--All these were moderating influences.

A striking similarity between Athens and the constitution of the Magnesian
colony is the use of the lot in the election of judges and other
magistrates.  That such a mode of election should have been resorted to in
any civilized state, or that it should have been transferred by Plato to an
ideal or imaginary one, is very singular to us.  The most extreme democracy
of modern times has never thought of leaving government wholly to chance. 
It was natural that Socrates should scoff at it, and ask, 'Who would choose
a pilot or carpenter or flute-player by lot' (Xen. Mem.)?  Yet there were
many considerations which made this mode of choice attractive both to the
oligarch and to the democrat:--(1) It seemed to recognize that one man was
as good as another, and that all the members of the governing body, whether
few or many, were on a perfect equality in every sense of the word.  (2) To
the pious mind it appeared to be a choice made, not by man, but by heaven
(compare Laws).  (3) It afforded a protection against corruption and
intrigue...It must also be remembered that, although elected by lot, the
persons so elected were subject to a scrutiny before they entered on their
office, and were therefore liable, after election, if disqualified, to be
rejected (Laws).  They were, moreover, liable to be called to account after
the expiration of their office.  In the election of councillors Plato
introduces a further check:  they are not to be chosen directly by lot from
all the citizens, but from a select body previously elected by vote.  In
Plato's state at least, as we may infer from his silence on this point,
judges and magistrates performed their duties without pay, which was a
guarantee both of their disinterestedness and of their belonging probably
to the higher class of citizens (compare Arist. Pol.).  Hence we are not
surprised that the use of the lot prevailed, not only in the election of
the Athenian Council, but also in many oligarchies, and even in Plato's
colony.  The evil consequences of the lot are to a great extent avoided, if
the magistrates so elected do not, like the dicasts at Athens, receive pay
from the state.

Another parallel is that of the Popular Assembly, which at Athens was
omnipotent, but in the Laws has only a faded and secondary existence.  In
Plato it was chiefly an elective body, having apparently no judicial and
little political power entrusted to it.  At Athens it was the mainspring of
the democracy; it had the decision of war or peace, of life and death; the
acts of generals or statesmen were authorized or condemned by it; no office
or person was above its control.  Plato was far from allowing such a
despotic power to exist in his model community, and therefore he minimizes
the importance of the Assembly and narrows its functions.  He probably
never asked himself a question, which naturally occurs to the modern
reader, where was to be the central authority in this new community, and by
what supreme power would the differences of inferior powers be decided.  At
the same time he magnifies and brings into prominence the Nocturnal Council
(which is in many respects a reflection of the Areopagus), but does not
make it the governing body of the state.

Between the judicial system of the Laws and that of Athens there was very
great similarity, and a difference almost equally great.  Plato not
unfrequently adopts the details when he rejects the principle.  At Athens
any citizen might be a judge and member of the great court of the Heliaea. 
This was ordinarily subdivided into a number of inferior courts, but an
occasion is recorded on which the whole body, in number six thousand, met
in a single court (Andoc. de Myst.).  Plato significantly remarks that a
few judges, if they are good, are better than a great number.  He also, at
least in capital cases, confines the plaintiff and defendant to a single
speech each, instead of allowing two apiece, as was the common practice at
Athens.  On the other hand, in all private suits he gives two appeals, from
the arbiters to the courts of the tribes, and from the courts of the tribes
to the final or supreme court.  There was nothing answering to this at
Athens.  The three courts were appointed in the following manner:--the
arbiters were to be agreed upon by the parties to the cause; the judges of
the tribes to be elected by lot; the highest tribunal to be chosen at the
end of each year by the great officers of state out of their own number--
they were to serve for a year, to undergo a scrutiny, and, unlike the
Athenian judges, to vote openly.  Plato does not dwell upon methods of
procedure:  these are the lesser matters which he leaves to the younger
legislators.  In cases of murder and some other capital offences, the cause
was to be tried by a special tribunal, as was the custom at Athens: 
military offences, too, as at Athens, were decided by the soldiers.  Public
causes in the Laws, as sometimes at Athens, were voted upon by the whole
people:  because, as Plato remarks, they are all equally concerned in them.
They were to be previously investigated by three of the principal
magistrates.  He believes also that in private suits all should take part;
'for he who has no share in the administration of justice is apt to imagine
that he has no share in the state at all.'  The wardens of the country,
like the Forty at Athens, also exercised judicial power in small matters,
as well as the wardens of the agora and city.  The department of justice is
better organized in Plato than in an ordinary Greek state, proceeding more
by regular methods, and being more restricted to distinct duties.

The executive of Plato's Laws, like the Athenian, was different from that
of a modern civilized state.  The difference chiefly consists in this, that
whereas among ourselves there are certain persons or classes of persons set
apart for the execution of the duties of government, in ancient Greece, as
in all other communities in the earlier stages of their development, they
were not equally distinguished from the rest of the citizens.  The
machinery of government was never so well organized as in the best modern
states.  The judicial department was not so completely separated from the
legislative, nor the executive from the judicial, nor the people at large
from the professional soldier, lawyer, or priest.  To Aristotle (Pol.) it
was a question requiring serious consideration--Who should execute a
sentence?  There was probably no body of police to whom were entrusted the
lives and properties of the citizens in any Hellenic state.  Hence it might
be reasonably expected that every man should be the watchman of every
other, and in turn be watched by him.  The ancients do not seem to have
remembered the homely adage that, 'What is every man's business is no man's
business,' or always to have thought of applying the principle of a
division of labour to the administration of law and to government.  Every
Athenian was at some time or on some occasion in his life a magistrate,
judge, advocate, soldier, sailor, policeman.  He had not necessarily any
private business; a good deal of his time was taken up with the duties of
office and other public occupations.  So, too, in Plato's Laws.  A citizen
was to interfere in a quarrel, if older than the combatants, or to defend
the outraged party, if his junior.  He was especially bound to come to the
rescue of a parent who was ill-treated by his children.  He was also
required to prosecute the murderer of a kinsman.  In certain cases he was
allowed to arrest an offender.  He might even use violence to an abusive
person.  Any citizen who was not less than thirty years of age at times
exercised a magisterial authority, to be enforced even by blows.  Both in
the Magnesian state and at Athens many thousand persons must have shared in
the highest duties of government, if a section only of the Council,
consisting of thirty or of fifty persons, as in the Laws, or at Athens
after the days of Cleisthenes, held office for a month, or for thirty-five
days only.  It was almost as if, in our own country, the Ministry or the
Houses of Parliament were to change every month.  The average ability of
the Athenian and Magnesian councillors could not have been very high,
considering there were so many of them.  And yet they were entrusted with
the performance of the most important executive duties.  In these respects
the constitution of the Laws resembles Athens far more than Sparta.  All
the citizens were to be, not merely soldiers, but politicians and
administrators.

(ii)  There are numerous minor particulars in which the Laws of Plato
resemble those of Athens.  These are less interesting than the preceding,
but they show even more strikingly how closely in the composition of his
work Plato has followed the laws and customs of his own country.

(1)  Evidence.  (a) At Athens a child was not allowed to give evidence
(Telfy).  Plato has a similar law:  'A child shall be allowed to give
evidence only in cases of murder.'  (b) At Athens an unwilling witness
might be summoned; but he was not required to appear if he was ready to
declare on oath that he knew nothing about the matter in question (Telfy). 
So in the Laws.  (c) Athenian law enacted that when more than half the
witnesses in a case had been convicted of perjury, there was to be a new
trial (anadikos krisis--Telfy).  There is a similar provision in the Laws. 
(d) False-witness was punished at Athens by atimia and a fine (Telfy). 
Plato is at once more lenient and more severe:  'If a man be twice
convicted of false-witness, he shall not be required, and if thrice, he
shall not be allowed to bear witness; and if he dare to witness after he
has been convicted three times,...he shall be punished with death.'

(2)  Murder.  (a) Wilful murder was punished in Athenian law by death,
perpetual exile, and confiscation of property (Telfy).  Plato, too, has the
alternative of death or exile, but he does not confiscate the murderer's
property.  (b) The Parricide was not allowed to escape by going into exile
at Athens (Telfy), nor, apparently, in the Laws.  (c) A homicide, if
forgiven by his victim before death, received no punishment, either at
Athens (Telfy), or in the Magnesian state.  In both (Telfy) the contriver
of a murder is punished as severely as the doer; and persons accused of the
crime are forbidden to enter temples or the agora until they have been
tried (Telfy).  (d) At Athens slaves who killed their masters and were
caught red-handed, were not to be put to death by the relations of the
murdered man, but to be handed over to the magistrates (Telfy).  So in the
Laws, the slave who is guilty of wilful murder has a public execution:  but
if the murder is committed in anger, it is punished by the kinsmen of the
victim.

(3)  Involuntary homicide.  (a) The guilty person, according to the
Athenian law, had to go into exile, and might not return, until the family
of the man slain were conciliated.  Then he must be purified (Telfy).  If
he is caught before he has obtained forgiveness, he may be put to death. 
These enactments reappear in the Laws.  (b) The curious provision of Plato,
that a stranger who has been banished for involuntary homicide and is
subsequently wrecked upon the coast, must 'take up his abode on the sea-
shore, wetting his feet in the sea, and watching for an opportunity of
sailing,' recalls the procedure of the Judicium Phreatteum at Athens,
according to which an involuntary homicide, who, having gone into exile, is
accused of a wilful murder, was tried at Phreatto for this offence in a
boat by magistrates on the shore.  (c) A still more singular law, occurring
both in the Athenian and Magnesian code, enacts that a stone or other
inanimate object which kills a man is to be tried, and cast over the border
(Telfy).

(4)  Justifiable or excusable homicide.  Plato and Athenian law agree in
making homicide justifiable or excusable in the following cases:--(1) at
the games (Telfy); (2) in war (Telfy); (3) if the person slain was found
doing violence to a free woman (Telfy); (4) if a doctor's patient dies; (5)
in the case of a robber (Telfy); (6) in self-defence (Telfy).

(5)  Impiety.  Death or expulsion was the Athenian penalty for impiety
(Telfy).  In the Laws it is punished in various cases by imprisonment for
five years, for life, and by death.

(6)  Sacrilege.  Robbery of temples at Athens was punished by death,
refusal of burial in the land, and confiscation of property (Telfy).  In
the Laws the citizen who is guilty of such a crime is to 'perish
ingloriously and be cast beyond the borders of the land,' but his property
is not confiscated.

(7)  Sorcery.  The sorcerer at Athens was to be executed (Telfy):  compare
Laws, where it is enacted that the physician who poisons and the
professional sorcerer shall be punished with death.

(8)  Treason.  Both at Athens and in the Laws the penalty for treason was
death (Telfy), and refusal of burial in the country (Telfy).

(9)  Sheltering exiles.  'If a man receives an exile, he shall be punished
with death.'  So, too, in Athenian law (Telfy.).

(10)  Wounding.  Athenian law compelled a man who had wounded another to go
into exile; if he returned, he was to be put to death (Telfy).  Plato only
punishes the offence with death when children wound their parents or one
another, or a slave wounds his master.

(11)  Bribery.  Death was the punishment for taking a bribe, both at Athens
(Telfy) and in the Laws; but Athenian law offered an alternative--the
payment of a fine of ten times the amount of the bribe.

(12)  Theft.  Plato, like Athenian law (Telfy), punishes the theft of
public property by death; the theft of private property in both involves a
fine of double the value of the stolen goods (Telfy).

(13)  Suicide.  He 'who slays him who of all men, as they say, is his own
best friend,' is regarded in the same spirit by Plato and by Athenian law.
Plato would have him 'buried ingloriously on the borders of the twelve
portions of the land, in such places as are uncultivated and nameless,' and
'no column or inscription is to mark the place of his interment.'  Athenian
law enacted that the hand which did the deed should be separated from the
body and be buried apart (Telfy).

(14)  Injury.  In cases of wilful injury, Athenian law compelled the guilty
person to pay double the damage; in cases of involuntary injury, simple
damages (Telfy).  Plato enacts that if a man wounds another in passion, and
the wound is curable, he shall pay double the damage, if incurable or
disfiguring, fourfold damages.  If, however, the wounding is accidental, he
shall simply pay for the harm done.

(15)  Treatment of parents.  Athenian law allowed any one to indict another
for neglect or illtreatment of parents (Telfy).  So Plato bids bystanders
assist a father who is assaulted by his son, and allows any one to give
information against children who neglect their parents.

(16)  Execution of sentences.  Both Plato and Athenian law give to the
winner of a suit power to seize the goods of the loser, if he does not pay
within the appointed time (Telfy).  At Athens the penalty was also doubled
(Telfy); not so in Plato.  Plato however punishes contempt of court by
death, which at Athens seems only to have been visited with a further fine
(Telfy).

(17)  Property.  (a) Both at Athens and in the Laws a man who has disputed
property in his possession must give the name of the person from whom he
received it (Telfy); and any one searching for lost property must enter a
house naked (Telfy), or, as Plato says, 'naked, or wearing only a short
tunic and without a girdle.  (b) Athenian law, as well as Plato, did not
allow a father to disinherit his son without good reason and the consent of
impartial persons (Telfy).  Neither grants to the eldest son any special
claim on the paternal estate (Telfy).  In the law of inheritance both
prefer males to females (Telfy).  (c) Plato and Athenian law enacted that a
tree should be planted at a fair distance from a neighbour's property
(Telfy), and that when a man could not get water, his neighbour must supply
him (Telfy).  Both at Athens and in Plato there is a law about bees, the
former providing that a beehive must be set up at not less a distance than
300 feet from a neighbour's (Telfy), and the latter forbidding the decoying
of bees.

(18)  Orphans.  A ward must proceed against a guardian whom he suspects of
fraud within five years of the expiration of the guardianship.  This
provision is common to Plato and to Athenian law (Telfy).  Further, the
latter enacted that the nearest male relation should marry or provide a
husband for an heiress (Telfy),--a point in which Plato follows it closely.

(19)  Contracts.  Plato's law that 'when a man makes an agreement which he
does not fulfil, unless the agreement be of a nature which the law or a
vote of the assembly does not allow, or which he has made under the
influence of some unjust compulsion, or which he is prevented from
fulfilling against his will by some unexpected chance,--the other party may
go to law with him,' according to Pollux (quoted in Telfy's note) prevailed
also at Athens.

(20)  Trade regulations.  (a) Lying was forbidden in the agora both by
Plato and at Athens (Telfy).  (b) Athenian law allowed an action of
recovery against a man who sold an unsound slave as sound (Telfy).  Plato's
enactment is more explicit:  he allows only an unskilled person (i.e. one
who is not a trainer or physician) to take proceedings in such a case.  (c)
Plato diverges from Athenian practice in the disapproval of credit, and
does not even allow the supply of goods on the deposit of a percentage of
their value (Telfy).  He enacts that 'when goods are exchanged by buying
and selling, a man shall deliver them and receive the price of them at a
fixed place in the agora, and have done with the matter,' and that 'he who
gives credit must be satisfied whether he obtain his money or not, for in
such exchanges he will not be protected by law.  (d) Athenian law forbad an
extortionate rate of interest (Telfy); Plato allows interest in one case
only--if a contractor does not receive the price of his work within a year
of the time agreed--and at the rate of 200 per cent. per annum ('for every
drachma a monthly interest of an obol.  (e) Both at Athens and in the Laws
sales were to be registered (Telfy), as well as births (Telfy).

(21)  Sumptuary laws.  Extravagance at weddings (Telfy), and at funerals
(Telfy) was forbidden at Athens and also in the Magnesian state.

There remains the subject of family life, which in Plato's Laws partakes
both of an Athenian and Spartan character.  Under this head may
conveniently be included the condition of women and of slaves.  To family
life may be added citizenship.

As at Sparta, marriages are to be contracted for the good of the state; and
they may be dissolved on the same ground, where there is a failure of
issue,--the interest of the state requiring that every one of the 5040 lots
should have an heir.  Divorces are likewise permitted by Plato where there
is an incompatibility of temper, as at Athens by mutual consent.  The duty
of having children is also enforced by a still higher motive, expressed by
Plato in the noble words:--'A man should cling to immortality, and leave
behind him children's children to be the servants of God in his place.' 
Again, as at Athens, the father is allowed to put away his undutiful son,
but only with the consent of impartial persons (Telfy), and the only suit
which may be brought by a son against a father is for imbecility.  The
class of elder and younger men and women are still to regard one another,
as in the Republic, as standing in the relation of parents and children. 
This is a trait of Spartan character rather than of Athenian.  A peculiar
sanctity and tenderness was to be shown towards the aged; the parent or
grandparent stricken with years was to be loved and worshipped like the
image of a God, and was to be deemed far more able than any lifeless statue
to bring good or ill to his descendants.  Great care is to be taken of
orphans:  they are entrusted to the fifteen eldest Guardians of the Law,
who are to be 'lawgivers and fathers to them not inferior to their natural
fathers,' as at Athens they were entrusted to the Archons.  Plato wishes to
make the misfortune of orphanhood as little sad to them as possible.

Plato, seeing the disorder into which half the human race had fallen at
Athens and Sparta, is minded to frame for them a new rule of life.  He
renounces his fanciful theory of communism, but still desires to place
women as far as possible on an equality with men.  They were to be trained
in the use of arms, they are to live in public.  Their time was partly
taken up with gymnastic exercises; there could have been little family or
private life among them.  Their lot was to be neither like that of Spartan
women, who were made hard and common by excessive practice of gymnastic and
the want of all other education,--nor yet like that of Athenian women, who,
at least among the upper classes, retired into a sort of oriental
seclusion,--but something better than either.  They were to be the perfect
mothers of perfect children, yet not wholly taken up with the duties of
motherhood, which were to be made easy to them as far as possible (compare
Republic), but able to share in the perils of war and to be the companions
of their husbands.  Here, more than anywhere else, the spirit of the Laws
reverts to the Republic.  In speaking of them as the companions of their
husbands we must remember that it is an Athenian and not a Spartan way of
life which they are invited to share, a life of gaiety and brightness, not
of austerity and abstinence, which often by a reaction degenerated into
licence and grossness.

In Plato's age the subject of slavery greatly interested the minds of
thoughtful men; and how best to manage this 'troublesome piece of goods'
exercised his own mind a good deal.  He admits that they have often been
found better than brethren or sons in the hour of danger, and are capable
of rendering important public services by informing against offenders--for
this they are to be rewarded; and the master who puts a slave to death for
the sake of concealing some crime which he has committed, is held guilty of
murder.  But they are not always treated with equal consideration.  The
punishments inflicted on them bear no proportion to their crimes.  They are
to be addressed only in the language of command.  Their masters are not to
jest with them, lest they should increase the hardship of their lot.  Some
privileges were granted to them by Athenian law of which there is no
mention in Plato; they were allowed to purchase their freedom from their
master, and if they despaired of being liberated by him they could demand
to be sold, on the chance of falling into better hands.  But there is no
suggestion in the Laws that a slave who tried to escape should be branded
with the words--kateche me, pheugo, or that evidence should be extracted
from him by torture, that the whole household was to be executed if the
master was murdered and the perpetrator remained undetected:  all these
were provisions of Athenian law.  Plato is more consistent than either the
Athenians or the Spartans; for at Sparta too the Helots were treated in a
manner almost unintelligible to us.  On the one hand, they had arms put
into their hands, and served in the army, not only, as at Plataea, in
attendance on their masters, but, after they had been manumitted, as a
separate body of troops called Neodamodes:  on the other hand, they were
the victims of one of the greatest crimes recorded in Greek history
(Thucyd.).  The two great philosophers of Hellas sought to extricate
themselves from this cruel condition of human life, but acquiesced in the
necessity of it.  A noble and pathetic sentiment of Plato, suggested by the
thought of their misery, may be quoted in this place:--'The right treatment
of slaves is to behave properly to them, and to do to them, if possible,
even more justice than to those who are our equals; for he who naturally
and genuinely reverences justice, and hates injustice, is discovered in his
dealings with any class of men to whom he can easily be unjust.  And he who
in regard to the natures and actions of his slaves is undefiled by impiety
and injustice, will best sow the seeds of virtue in them; and this may be
truly said of every master, and tyrant, and of every other having authority
in relation to his inferiors.'

All the citizens of the Magnesian state were free and equal; there was no
distinction of rank among them, such as is believed to have prevailed at
Sparta.  Their number was a fixed one, corresponding to the 5040 lots.  One
of the results of this is the requirement that younger sons or those who
have been disinherited shall go out to a colony.  At Athens, where there
was not the same religious feeling against increasing the size of the city,
the number of citizens must have been liable to considerable fluctuations.
Several classes of persons, who were not citizens by birth, were admitted
to the privilege.  Perpetual exiles from other countries, people who
settled there to practise a trade (Telfy), any one who had shown
distinguished valour in the cause of Athens, the Plataeans who escaped from
the siege, metics and strangers who offered to serve in the army, the
slaves who fought at Arginusae,--all these could or did become citizens. 
Even those who were only on one side of Athenian parentage were at more
than one period accounted citizens.  But at times there seems to have
arisen a feeling against this promiscuous extension of the citizen body, an
expression of which is to be found in the law of Pericles--monous
Athenaious einai tous ek duoin Athenaion gegonotas (Plutarch, Pericles);
and at no time did the adopted citizen enjoy the full rights of
citizenship--e.g. he might not be elected archon or to the office of priest
(Telfy), although this prohibition did not extend to his children, if born
of a citizen wife.  Plato never thinks of making the metic, much less the
slave, a citizen.  His treatment of the former class is at once more gentle
and more severe than that which prevailed at Athens.  He imposes upon them
no tax but good behaviour, whereas at Athens they were required to pay
twelve drachmae per annum, and to have a patron:  on the other hand, he
only allows them to reside in the Magnesian state on condition of following
a trade; they were required to depart when their property exceeded that of
the third class, and in any case after a residence of twenty years, unless
they could show that they had conferred some great benefit on the state. 
This privileged position reflects that of the isoteleis at Athens, who were
excused from the metoikion.  It is Plato's greatest concession to the
metic, as the bestowal of freedom is his greatest concession to the slave.

Lastly, there is a more general point of view under which the Laws of Plato
may be considered,--the principles of Jurisprudence which are contained in
them.  These are not formally announced, but are scattered up and down, to
be observed by the reflective reader for himself.  Some of them are only
the common principles which all courts of justice have gathered from
experience; others are peculiar and characteristic.  That judges should sit
at fixed times and hear causes in a regular order, that evidence should be
laid before them, that false witnesses should be disallowed, and corruption
punished, that defendants should be heard before they are convicted,--these
are the rules, not only of the Hellenic courts, but of courts of law in all
ages and countries.  But there are also points which are peculiar, and in
which ancient jurisprudence differs considerably from modern; some of them
are of great importance...It could not be said at Athens, nor was it ever
contemplated by Plato, that all men, including metics and slaves, should be
equal 'in the eye of the law.'  There was some law for the slave, but not
much; no adequate protection was given him against the cruelty of his
master...It was a singular privilege granted, both by the Athenian and
Magnesian law, to a murdered man, that he might, before he died, pardon his
murderer, in which case no legal steps were afterwards to be taken against
him.  This law is the remnant of an age in which the punishment of offences
against the person was the concern rather of the individual and his kinsmen
than of the state...Plato's division of crimes into voluntary and
involuntary and those done from passion, only partially agrees with the
distinction which modern law has drawn between murder and manslaughter; his
attempt to analyze them is confused by the Socratic paradox, that 'All vice
is involuntary'...It is singular that both in the Laws and at Athens theft
is commonly punished by a twofold restitution of the article stolen.  The
distinction between civil and criminal courts or suits was not yet
recognized...Possession gives a right of property after a certain
time...The religious aspect under which certain offences were regarded
greatly interfered with a just and natural estimate of their guilt...As
among ourselves, the intent to murder was distinguished by Plato from
actual murder...We note that both in Plato and the laws of Athens, libel in
the market-place and personality in the theatre were forbidden...Both in
Plato and Athenian law, as in modern times, the accomplice of a crime is to
be punished as well as the principal...Plato does not allow a witness in a
cause to act as a judge of it...Oaths are not to be taken by the parties to
a suit...Both at Athens and in Plato's Laws capital punishment for murder
was not to be inflicted, if the offender was willing to go into
exile...Respect for the dead, duty towards parents, are to be enforced by
the law as well as by public opinion...Plato proclaims the noble sentiment
that the object of all punishment is the improvement of the offender...
Finally, he repeats twice over, as with the voice of a prophet, that the
crimes of the fathers are not to be visited upon the children.  In this
respect he is nobly distinguished from the Oriental, and indeed from the
spirit of Athenian law (compare Telfy,--dei kai autous kai tous ek touton
atimous einai), as the Hebrew in the age of Ezekial is from the Jewish
people of former ages.

Of all Plato's provisions the object is to bring the practice of the law
more into harmony with reason and philosophy; to secure impartiality, and
while acknowledging that every citizen has a right to share in the
administration of justice, to counteract the tendency of the courts to
become mere popular assemblies.

...

Thus we have arrived at the end of the writings of Plato, and at the last
stage of philosophy which was really his.  For in what followed, which we
chiefly gather from the uncertain intimations of Aristotle, the spirit of
the master no longer survived.  The doctrine of Ideas passed into one of
numbers; instead of advancing from the abstract to the concrete, the
theories of Plato were taken out of their context, and either asserted or
refuted with a provoking literalism; the Socratic or Platonic element in
his teaching was absorbed into the Pythagorean or Megarian.  His poetry was
converted into mysticism; his unsubstantial visions were assailed secundum
artem by the rules of logic.  His political speculations lost their
interest when the freedom of Hellas had passed away.  Of all his writings
the Laws were the furthest removed from the traditions of the Platonic
school in the next generation.  Both his political and his metaphysical
philosophy are for the most part misinterpreted by Aristotle.  The best of
him--his love of truth, and his 'contemplation of all time and all
existence,' was soonest lost; and some of his greatest thoughts have slept
in the ear of mankind almost ever since they were first uttered.

We have followed him during his forty or fifty years of authorship, from
the beginning when he first attempted to depict the teaching of Socrates in
a dramatic form, down to the time at which the character of Socrates had
disappeared, and we have the latest reflections of Plato's own mind upon
Hellas and upon philosophy.  He, who was 'the last of the poets,' in his
book of Laws writes prose only; he has himself partly fallen under the
rhetorical influences which in his earlier dialogues he was combating.  The
progress of his writings is also the history of his life; we have no other
authentic life of him.  They are the true self of the philosopher, stripped
of the accidents of time and place.  The great effort which he makes is,
first, to realize abstractions, secondly, to connect them.  In the attempt
to realize them, he was carried into a transcendental region in which he
isolated them from experience, and we pass out of the range of science into
poetry or fiction.  The fancies of mythology for a time cast a veil over
the gulf which divides phenomena from onta (Meno, Phaedrus, Symposium,
Phaedo).  In his return to earth Plato meets with a difficulty which has
long ceased to be a difficulty to us.  He cannot understand how these
obstinate, unmanageable ideas, residing alone in their heaven of
abstraction, can be either combined with one another, or adapted to
phenomena (Parmenides, Philebus, Sophist).  That which is the most familiar
process of our own minds, to him appeared to be the crowning achievement of
the dialectical art.  The difficulty which in his own generation threatened
to be the destruction of philosophy, he has rendered unmeaning and
ridiculous.  For by his conquests in the world of mind our thoughts are
widened, and he has furnished us with new dialectical instruments which are
of greater compass and power.  We have endeavoured to see him as he truly
was, a great original genius struggling with unequal conditions of
knowledge, not prepared with a system nor evolving in a series of dialogues
ideas which he had long conceived, but contradictory, enquiring as he goes
along, following the argument, first from one point of view and then from
another, and therefore arriving at opposite conclusions, hovering around
the light, and sometimes dazzled with excess of light, but always moving in
the same element of ideal truth.  We have seen him also in his decline,
when the wings of his imagination have begun to droop, but his experience
of life remains, and he turns away from the contemplation of the eternal to
take a last sad look at human affairs.

...

And so having brought into the world 'noble children' (Phaedr.), he rests
from the labours of authorship.  More than two thousand two hundred years
have passed away since he returned to the place of Apollo and the Muses. 
Yet the echo of his words continues to be heard among men, because of all
philosophers he has the most melodious voice.  He is the inspired prophet
or teacher who can never die, the only one in whom the outward form
adequately represents the fair soul within; in whom the thoughts of all who
went before him are reflected and of all who come after him are partly
anticipated.  Other teachers of philosophy are dried up and withered,--
after a few centuries they have become dust; but he is fresh and blooming,
and is always begetting new ideas in the minds of men.  They are one-sided
and abstract; but he has many sides of wisdom.  Nor is he always consistent
with himself, because he is always moving onward, and knows that there are
many more things in philosophy than can be expressed in words, and that
truth is greater than consistency.  He who approaches him in the most
reverent spirit shall reap most of the fruit of his wisdom; he who reads
him by the light of ancient commentators will have the least understanding
of him.

We may see him with the eye of the mind in the groves of the Academy, or on
the banks of the Ilissus, or in the streets of Athens, alone or walking
with Socrates, full of those thoughts which have since become the common
possession of mankind.  Or we may compare him to a statue hid away in some
temple of Zeus or Apollo, no longer existing on earth, a statue which has a
look as of the God himself.  Or we may once more imagine him following in
another state of being the great company of heaven which he beheld of old
in a vision (Phaedr.).  So, 'partly trifling, but with a certain degree of
seriousness' (Symp.), we linger around the memory of a world which has
passed away (Phaedr.).




LAWS

by

Plato

Translated by Benjamin Jowett


BOOK I.

PERSONS OF THE DIALOGUE:  An Athenian Stranger, Cleinias (a Cretan),
Megillus (a Lacedaemonian).


ATHENIAN:  Tell me, Strangers, is a God or some man supposed to be the
author of your laws?

CLEINIAS:  A God, Stranger; in very truth a God:  among us Cretans he is
said to have been Zeus, but in Lacedaemon, whence our friend here comes, I
believe they would say that Apollo is their lawgiver:  would they not,
Megillus?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And do you, Cleinias, believe, as Homer tells, that every ninth
year Minos went to converse with his Olympian sire, and was inspired by him
to make laws for your cities?

CLEINIAS:  Yes, that is our tradition; and there was Rhadamanthus, a
brother of his, with whose name you are familiar; he is reputed to have
been the justest of men, and we Cretans are of opinion that he earned this
reputation from his righteous administration of justice when he was alive.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, and a noble reputation it was, worthy of a son of Zeus.  As
you and Megillus have been trained in these institutions, I dare say that
you will not be unwilling to give an account of your government and laws;
on our way we can pass the time pleasantly in talking about them, for I am
told that the distance from Cnosus to the cave and temple of Zeus is
considerable; and doubtless there are shady places under the lofty trees,
which will protect us from this scorching sun.  Being no longer young, we
may often stop to rest beneath them, and get over the whole journey without
difficulty, beguiling the time by conversation.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, Stranger, and if we proceed onward we shall come to groves
of cypresses, which are of rare height and beauty, and there are green
meadows, in which we may repose and converse.

ATHENIAN:  Very good.

CLEINIAS:  Very good, indeed; and still better when we see them; let us
move on cheerily.

ATHENIAN:  I am willing--And first, I want to know why the law has ordained
that you shall have common meals and gymnastic exercises, and wear arms.

CLEINIAS:  I think, Stranger, that the aim of our institutions is easily
intelligible to any one.  Look at the character of our country:  Crete is
not like Thessaly, a large plain; and for this reason they have horsemen in
Thessaly, and we have runners--the inequality of the ground in our country
is more adapted to locomotion on foot; but then, if you have runners you
must have light arms--no one can carry a heavy weight when running, and
bows and arrows are convenient because they are light.  Now all these
regulations have been made with a view to war, and the legislator appears
to me to have looked to this in all his arrangements:--the common meals, if
I am not mistaken, were instituted by him for a similar reason, because he
saw that while they are in the field the citizens are by the nature of the
case compelled to take their meals together for the sake of mutual
protection.  He seems to me to have thought the world foolish in not
understanding that all men are always at war with one another; and if in
war there ought to be common meals and certain persons regularly appointed
under others to protect an army, they should be continued in peace.  For
what men in general term peace would be said by him to be only a name; in
reality every city is in a natural state of war with every other, not
indeed proclaimed by heralds, but everlasting.  And if you look closely,
you will find that this was the intention of the Cretan legislator; all
institutions, private as well as public, were arranged by him with a view
to war; in giving them he was under the impression that no possessions or
institutions are of any value to him who is defeated in battle; for all the
good things of the conquered pass into the hands of the conquerors.

ATHENIAN:  You appear to me, Stranger, to have been thoroughly trained in
the Cretan institutions, and to be well informed about them; will you tell
me a little more explicitly what is the principle of government which you
would lay down?  You seem to imagine that a well-governed state ought to be
so ordered as to conquer all other states in war:  am I right in supposing
this to be your meaning?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly; and our Lacedaemonian friend, if I am not mistaken,
will agree with me.

MEGILLUS:  Why, my good friend, how could any Lacedaemonian say anything
else?

ATHENIAN:  And is what you say applicable only to states, or also to
villages?

CLEINIAS:  To both alike.

ATHENIAN:  The case is the same?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And in the village will there be the same war of family against
family, and of individual against individual?

CLEINIAS:  The same.

ATHENIAN:  And should each man conceive himself to be his own enemy:--what
shall we say?

CLEINIAS:  O Athenian Stranger--inhabitant of Attica I will not call you,
for you seem to deserve rather to be named after the goddess herself,
because you go back to first principles,--you have thrown a light upon the
argument, and will now be better able to understand what I was just saying,
--that all men are publicly one another's enemies, and each man privately
his own.

(ATHENIAN:  My good sir, what do you mean?)--

CLEINIAS:...Moreover, there is a victory and defeat--the first and best of
victories, the lowest and worst of defeats--which each man gains or
sustains at the hands, not of another, but of himself; this shows that
there is a war against ourselves going on within every one of us.

ATHENIAN:  Let us now reverse the order of the argument:  Seeing that every
individual is either his own superior or his own inferior, may we say that
there is the same principle in the house, the village, and the state?

CLEINIAS:  You mean that in each of them there is a principle of
superiority or inferiority to self?

ATHENIAN:  Yes.

CLEINIAS:  You are quite right in asking the question, for there certainly
is such a principle, and above all in states; and the state in which the
better citizens win a victory over the mob and over the inferior classes
may be truly said to be better than itself, and may be justly praised,
where such a victory is gained, or censured in the opposite case.

ATHENIAN:  Whether the better is ever really conquered by the worse, is a
question which requires more discussion, and may be therefore left for the
present.  But I now quite understand your meaning when you say that
citizens who are of the same race and live in the same cities may unjustly
conspire, and having the superiority in numbers may overcome and enslave
the few just; and when they prevail, the state may be truly called its own
inferior and therefore bad; and when they are defeated, its own superior
and therefore good.

CLEINIAS:  Your remark, Stranger, is a paradox, and yet we cannot possibly
deny it.

ATHENIAN:  Here is another case for consideration;--in a family there may
be several brothers, who are the offspring of a single pair; very possibly
the majority of them may be unjust, and the just may be in a minority.

CLEINIAS:  Very possibly.

ATHENIAN:  And you and I ought not to raise a question of words as to
whether this family and household are rightly said to be superior when they
conquer, and inferior when they are conquered; for we are not now
considering what may or may not be the proper or customary way of speaking,
but we are considering the natural principles of right and wrong in laws.

CLEINIAS:  What you say, Stranger, is most true.

MEGILLUS:  Quite excellent, in my opinion, as far as we have gone.

ATHENIAN:  Again; might there not be a judge over these brethren, of whom
we were speaking?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Now, which would be the better judge--one who destroyed the bad
and appointed the good to govern themselves; or one who, while allowing the
good to govern, let the bad live, and made them voluntarily submit?  Or
third, I suppose, in the scale of excellence might be placed a judge, who,
finding the family distracted, not only did not destroy any one, but
reconciled them to one another for ever after, and gave them laws which
they mutually observed, and was able to keep them friends.

CLEINIAS:  The last would be by far the best sort of judge and legislator.

ATHENIAN:  And yet the aim of all the laws which he gave would be the
reverse of war.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And will he who constitutes the state and orders the life of man
have in view external war, or that kind of intestine war called civil,
which no one, if he could prevent, would like to have occurring in his own
state; and when occurring, every one would wish to be quit of as soon as
possible?

CLEINIAS:  He would have the latter chiefly in view.

ATHENIAN:  And would he prefer that this civil war should be terminated by
the destruction of one of the parties, and by the victory of the other, or
that peace and friendship should be re-established, and that, being
reconciled, they should give their attention to foreign enemies?

CLEINIAS:  Every one would desire the latter in the case of his own state.

ATHENIAN:  And would not that also be the desire of the legislator?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And would not every one always make laws for the sake of the
best?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  But war, whether external or civil, is not the best, and the
need of either is to be deprecated; but peace with one another, and good
will, are best.  Nor is the victory of the state over itself to be regarded
as a really good thing, but as a necessity; a man might as well say that
the body was in the best state when sick and purged by medicine, forgetting
that there is also a state of the body which needs no purge.  And in like
manner no one can be a true statesman, whether he aims at the happiness of
the individual or state, who looks only, or first of all, to external
warfare; nor will he ever be a sound legislator who orders peace for the
sake of war, and not war for the sake of peace.

CLEINIAS:  I suppose that there is truth, Stranger, in that remark of
yours; and yet I am greatly mistaken if war is not the entire aim and
object of our own institutions, and also of the Lacedaemonian.

ATHENIAN:  I dare say; but there is no reason why we should rudely quarrel
with one another about your legislators, instead of gently questioning
them, seeing that both we and they are equally in earnest.  Please follow
me and the argument closely:--And first I will put forward Tyrtaeus, an
Athenian by birth, but also a Spartan citizen, who of all men was most
eager about war:  Well, he says,

'I sing not, I care not, about any man,

even if he were the richest of men, and possessed every good (and then he
gives a whole list of them), if he be not at all times a brave warrior.'  I
imagine that you, too, must have heard his poems; our Lacedaemonian friend
has probably heard more than enough of them.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

CLEINIAS:  And they have found their way from Lacedaemon to Crete.

ATHENIAN:  Come now and let us all join in asking this question of
Tyrtaeus:  O most divine poet, we will say to him, the excellent praise
which you have bestowed on those who excel in war sufficiently proves that
you are wise and good, and I and Megillus and Cleinias of Cnosus do, as I
believe, entirely agree with you.  But we should like to be quite sure that
we are speaking of the same men; tell us, then, do you agree with us in
thinking that there are two kinds of war; or what would you say?  A far
inferior man to Tyrtaeus would have no difficulty in replying quite truly,
that war is of two kinds,--one which is universally called civil war, and
is, as we were just now saying, of all wars the worst; the other, as we
should all admit, in which we fall out with other nations who are of a
different race, is a far milder form of warfare.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly, far milder.

ATHENIAN:  Well, now, when you praise and blame war in this high-flown
strain, whom are you praising or blaming, and to which kind of war are you
referring?  I suppose that you must mean foreign war, if I am to judge from
expressions of yours in which you say that you abominate those

'Who refuse to look upon fields of blood, and will not draw near and strike
at their enemies.'

And we shall naturally go on to say to him,--You, Tyrtaeus, as it seems,
praise those who distinguish themselves in external and foreign war; and he
must admit this.

CLEINIAS:  Evidently.

ATHENIAN:  They are good; but we say that there are still better men whose
virtue is displayed in the greatest of all battles.  And we too have a poet
whom we summon as a witness, Theognis, citizen of Megara in Sicily:

'Cyrnus,' he says, 'he who is faithful in a civil broil is worth his weight
in gold and silver.'

And such an one is far better, as we affirm, than the other in a more
difficult kind of war, much in the same degree as justice and temperance
and wisdom, when united with courage, are better than courage only; for a
man cannot be faithful and good in civil strife without having all virtue. 
But in the war of which Tyrtaeus speaks, many a mercenary soldier will take
his stand and be ready to die at his post, and yet they are generally and
almost without exception insolent, unjust, violent men, and the most
senseless of human beings.  You will ask what the conclusion is, and what I
am seeking to prove:  I maintain that the divine legislator of Crete, like
any other who is worthy of consideration, will always and above all things
in making laws have regard to the greatest virtue; which, according to
Theognis, is loyalty in the hour of danger, and may be truly called perfect
justice.  Whereas, that virtue which Tyrtaeus highly praises is well
enough, and was praised by the poet at the right time, yet in place and
dignity may be said to be only fourth rate (i.e., it ranks after justice,
temperance, and wisdom.).

CLEINIAS:  Stranger, we are degrading our inspired lawgiver to a rank which
is far beneath him.

ATHENIAN:  Nay, I think that we degrade not him but ourselves, if we
imagine that Lycurgus and Minos laid down laws both in Lacedaemon and Crete
mainly with a view to war.

CLEINIAS:  What ought we to say then?

ATHENIAN:  What truth and what justice require of us, if I am not mistaken,
when speaking in behalf of divine excellence;--that the legislator when
making his laws had in view not a part only, and this the lowest part of
virtue, but all virtue, and that he devised classes of laws answering to
the kinds of virtue; not in the way in which modern inventors of laws make
the classes, for they only investigate and offer laws whenever a want is
felt, and one man has a class of laws about allotments and heiresses,
another about assaults; others about ten thousand other such matters.  But
we maintain that the right way of examining into laws is to proceed as we
have now done, and I admired the spirit of your exposition; for you were
quite right in beginning with virtue, and saying that this was the aim of
the giver of the law, but I thought that you went wrong when you added that
all his legislation had a view only to a part, and the least part of
virtue, and this called forth my subsequent remarks.  Will you allow me
then to explain how I should have liked to have heard you expound the
matter?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  You ought to have said, Stranger--The Cretan laws are with
reason famous among the Hellenes; for they fulfil the object of laws, which
is to make those who use them happy; and they confer every sort of good. 
Now goods are of two kinds:  there are human and there are divine goods,
and the human hang upon the divine; and the state which attains the
greater, at the same time acquires the less, or, not having the greater,
has neither.  Of the lesser goods the first is health, the second beauty,
the third strength, including swiftness in running and bodily agility
generally, and the fourth is wealth, not the blind god (Pluto), but one who
is keen of sight, if only he has wisdom for his companion.  For wisdom is
chief and leader of the divine class of goods, and next follows temperance;
and from the union of these two with courage springs justice, and fourth in
the scale of virtue is courage.  All these naturally take precedence of the
other goods, and this is the order in which the legislator must place them,
and after them he will enjoin the rest of his ordinances on the citizens
with a view to these, the human looking to the divine, and the divine
looking to their leader mind.  Some of his ordinances will relate to
contracts of marriage which they make one with another, and then to the
procreation and education of children, both male and female; the duty of
the lawgiver will be to take charge of his citizens, in youth and age, and
at every time of life, and to give them punishments and rewards; and in
reference to all their intercourse with one another, he ought to consider
their pains and pleasures and desires, and the vehemence of all their
passions; he should keep a watch over them, and blame and praise them
rightly by the mouth of the laws themselves.  Also with regard to anger and
terror, and the other perturbations of the soul, which arise out of
misfortune, and the deliverances from them which prosperity brings, and the
experiences which come to men in diseases, or in war, or poverty, or the
opposite of these; in all these states he should determine and teach what
is the good and evil of the condition of each.  In the next place, the
legislator has to be careful how the citizens make their money and in what
way they spend it, and to have an eye to their mutual contracts and
dissolutions of contracts, whether voluntary or involuntary:  he should see
how they order all this, and consider where justice as well as injustice is
found or is wanting in their several dealings with one another; and honour
those who obey the law, and impose fixed penalties on those who disobey,
until the round of civil life is ended, and the time has come for the
consideration of the proper funeral rites and honours of the dead.  And the
lawgiver reviewing his work, will appoint guardians to preside over these
things,--some who walk by intelligence, others by true opinion only, and
then mind will bind together all his ordinances and show them to be in
harmony with temperance and justice, and not with wealth or ambition.  This
is the spirit, Stranger, in which I was and am desirous that you should
pursue the subject.  And I want to know the nature of all these things, and
how they are arranged in the laws of Zeus, as they are termed, and in those
of the Pythian Apollo, which Minos and Lycurgus gave; and how the order of
them is discovered to his eyes, who has experience in laws gained either by
study or habit, although they are far from being self-evident to the rest
of mankind like ourselves.

CLEINIAS:  How shall we proceed, Stranger?

ATHENIAN:  I think that we must begin again as before, and first consider
the habit of courage; and then we will go on and discuss another and then
another form of virtue, if you please.  In this way we shall have a model
of the whole; and with these and similar discourses we will beguile the
way.  And when we have gone through all the virtues, we will show, by the
grace of God, that the institutions of which I was speaking look to virtue.

MEGILLUS:  Very good; and suppose that you first criticize this praiser of
Zeus and the laws of Crete.

ATHENIAN:  I will try to criticize you and myself, as well as him, for the
argument is a common concern.  Tell me,--were not first the syssitia, and
secondly the gymnasia, invented by your legislator with a view to war?

MEGILLUS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And what comes third, and what fourth?  For that, I think, is
the sort of enumeration which ought to be made of the remaining parts of
virtue, no matter whether you call them parts or what their name is,
provided the meaning is clear.

MEGILLUS:  Then I, or any other Lacedaemonian, would reply that hunting is
third in order.

ATHENIAN:  Let us see if we can discover what comes fourth and fifth.

MEGILLUS:  I think that I can get as far as the fourth head, which is the
frequent endurance of pain, exhibited among us Spartans in certain hand-to-
hand fights; also in stealing with the prospect of getting a good beating;
there is, too, the so-called Crypteia, or secret service, in which
wonderful endurance is shown,--our people wander over the whole country by
day and by night, and even in winter have not a shoe to their foot, and are
without beds to lie upon, and have to attend upon themselves.  Marvellous,
too, is the endurance which our citizens show in their naked exercises,
contending against the violent summer heat; and there are many similar
practices, to speak of which in detail would be endless.

ATHENIAN:  Excellent, O Lacedaemonian Stranger.  But how ought we to define
courage?  Is it to be regarded only as a combat against fears and pains, or
also against desires and pleasures, and against flatteries; which exercise
such a tremendous power, that they make the hearts even of respectable
citizens to melt like wax?

MEGILLUS:  I should say the latter.

ATHENIAN:  In what preceded, as you will remember, our Cnosian friend was
speaking of a man or a city being inferior to themselves:--Were you not,
Cleinias?

CLEINIAS:  I was.

ATHENIAN:  Now, which is in the truest sense inferior, the man who is
overcome by pleasure or by pain?

CLEINIAS:  I should say the man who is overcome by pleasure; for all men
deem him to be inferior in a more disgraceful sense, than the other who is
overcome by pain.

ATHENIAN:  But surely the lawgivers of Crete and Lacedaemon have not
legislated for a courage which is lame of one leg, able only to meet
attacks which come from the left, but impotent against the insidious
flatteries which come from the right?

CLEINIAS:  Able to meet both, I should say.

ATHENIAN:  Then let me once more ask, what institutions have you in either
of your states which give a taste of pleasures, and do not avoid them any
more than they avoid pains; but which set a person in the midst of them,
and compel or induce him by the prospect of reward to get the better of
them?  Where is an ordinance about pleasure similar to that about pain to
be found in your laws?  Tell me what there is of this nature among you:--
What is there which makes your citizen equally brave against pleasure and
pain, conquering what they ought to conquer, and superior to the enemies
who are most dangerous and nearest home?

MEGILLUS:  I was able to tell you, Stranger, many laws which were directed
against pain; but I do not know that I can point out any great or obvious
examples of similar institutions which are concerned with pleasure; there
are some lesser provisions, however, which I might mention.

CLEINIAS:  Neither can I show anything of that sort which is at all equally
prominent in the Cretan laws.

ATHENIAN:  No wonder, my dear friends; and if, as is very likely, in our
search after the true and good, one of us may have to censure the laws of
the others, we must not be offended, but take kindly what another says.

CLEINIAS:  You are quite right, Athenian Stranger, and we will do as you
say.

ATHENIAN:  At our time of life, Cleinias, there should be no feeling of
irritation.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  I will not at present determine whether he who censures the
Cretan or Lacedaemonian polities is right or wrong.  But I believe that I
can tell better than either of you what the many say about them.  For
assuming that you have reasonably good laws, one of the best of them will
be the law forbidding any young men to enquire which of them are right or
wrong; but with one mouth and one voice they must all agree that the laws
are all good, for they came from God; and any one who says the contrary is
not to be listened to.  But an old man who remarks any defect in your laws
may communicate his observation to a ruler or to an equal in years when no
young man is present.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly so, Stranger; and like a diviner, although not there at
the time, you seem to me quite to have hit the meaning of the legislator,
and to say what is most true.

ATHENIAN:  As there are no young men present, and the legislator has given
old men free licence, there will be no impropriety in our discussing these
very matters now that we are alone.

CLEINIAS:  True.  And therefore you may be as free as you like in your
censure of our laws, for there is no discredit in knowing what is wrong; he
who receives what is said in a generous and friendly spirit will be all the
better for it.

ATHENIAN:  Very good; however, I am not going to say anything against your
laws until to the best of my ability I have examined them, but I am going
to raise doubts about them.  For you are the only people known to us,
whether Greek or barbarian, whom the legislator commanded to eschew all
great pleasures and amusements and never to touch them; whereas in the
matter of pains or fears which we have just been discussing, he thought
that they who from infancy had always avoided pains and fears and sorrows,
when they were compelled to face them would run away from those who were
hardened in them, and would become their subjects.  Now the legislator
ought to have considered that this was equally true of pleasure; he should
have said to himself, that if our citizens are from their youth upward
unacquainted with the greatest pleasures, and unused to endure amid the
temptations of pleasure, and are not disciplined to refrain from all things
evil, the sweet feeling of pleasure will overcome them just as fear would
overcome the former class; and in another, and even a worse manner, they
will be the slaves of those who are able to endure amid pleasures, and have
had the opportunity of enjoying them, they being often the worst of
mankind.  One half of their souls will be a slave, the other half free; and
they will not be worthy to be called in the true sense men and freemen. 
Tell me whether you assent to my words?

CLEINIAS:  On first hearing, what you say appears to be the truth; but to
be hasty in coming to a conclusion about such important matters would be
very childish and simple.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose, Cleinias and Megillus, that we consider the virtue
which follows next of those which we intended to discuss (for after courage
comes temperance), what institutions shall we find relating to temperance,
either in Crete or Lacedaemon, which, like your military institutions,
differ from those of any ordinary state.

MEGILLUS:  That is not an easy question to answer; still I should say that
the common meals and gymnastic exercises have been excellently devised for
the promotion both of temperance and courage.

ATHENIAN:  There seems to be a difficulty, Stranger, with regard to states,
in making words and facts coincide so that there can be no dispute about
them.  As in the human body, the regimen which does good in one way does
harm in another; and we can hardly say that any one course of treatment is
adapted to a particular constitution.  Now the gymnasia and common meals do
a great deal of good, and yet they are a source of evil in civil troubles;
as is shown in the case of the Milesian, and Boeotian, and Thurian youth,
among whom these institutions seem always to have had a tendency to degrade
the ancient and natural custom of love below the level, not only of man,
but of the beasts.  The charge may be fairly brought against your cities
above all others, and is true also of most other states which especially
cultivate gymnastics.  Whether such matters are to be regarded jestingly or
seriously, I think that the pleasure is to be deemed natural which arises
out of the intercourse between men and women; but that the intercourse of
men with men, or of women with women, is contrary to nature, and that the
bold attempt was originally due to unbridled lust.  The Cretans are always
accused of having invented the story of Ganymede and Zeus because they
wanted to justify themselves in the enjoyment of unnatural pleasures by the
practice of the god whom they believe to have been their lawgiver.  Leaving
the story, we may observe that any speculation about laws turns almost
entirely on pleasure and pain, both in states and in individuals:  these
are two fountains which nature lets flow, and he who draws from them where
and when, and as much as he ought, is happy; and this holds of men and
animals--of individuals as well as states; and he who indulges in them
ignorantly and at the wrong time, is the reverse of happy.

MEGILLUS:  I admit, Stranger, that your words are well spoken, and I hardly
know what to say in answer to you; but still I think that the Spartan
lawgiver was quite right in forbidding pleasure.  Of the Cretan laws, I
shall leave the defence to my Cnosian friend.  But the laws of Sparta, in
as far as they relate to pleasure, appear to me to be the best in the
world; for that which leads mankind in general into the wildest pleasure
and licence, and every other folly, the law has clean driven out; and
neither in the country nor in towns which are under the control of Sparta,
will you find revelries and the many incitements of every kind of pleasure
which accompany them; and any one who meets a drunken and disorderly
person, will immediately have him most severely punished, and will not let
him off on any pretence, not even at the time of a Dionysiac festival;
although I have remarked that this may happen at your performances 'on the
cart,' as they are called; and among our Tarentine colonists I have seen
the whole city drunk at a Dionysiac festival; but nothing of the sort
happens among us.

ATHENIAN:  O Lacedaemonian Stranger, these festivities are praiseworthy
where there is a spirit of endurance, but are very senseless when they are
under no regulations.  In order to retaliate, an Athenian has only to point
out the licence which exists among your women.  To all such accusations,
whether they are brought against the Tarentines, or us, or you, there is
one answer which exonerates the practice in question from impropriety. 
When a stranger expresses wonder at the singularity of what he sees, any
inhabitant will naturally answer him:--Wonder not, O stranger; this is our
custom, and you may very likely have some other custom about the same
things.  Now we are speaking, my friends, not about men in general, but
about the merits and defects of the lawgivers themselves.  Let us then
discourse a little more at length about intoxication, which is a very
important subject, and will seriously task the discrimination of the
legislator.  I am not speaking of drinking, or not drinking, wine at all,
but of intoxication.  Are we to follow the custom of the Scythians, and
Persians, and Carthaginians, and Celts, and Iberians, and Thracians, who
are all warlike nations, or that of your countrymen, for they, as you say,
altogether abstain?  But the Scythians and Thracians, both men and women,
drink unmixed wine, which they pour on their garments, and this they think
a happy and glorious institution.  The Persians, again, are much given to
other practices of luxury which you reject, but they have more moderation
in them than the Thracians and Scythians.

MEGILLUS:  O best of men, we have only to take arms into our hands, and we
send all these nations flying before us.

ATHENIAN:  Nay, my good friend, do not say that; there have been, as there
always will be, flights and pursuits of which no account can be given, and
therefore we cannot say that victory or defeat in battle affords more than
a doubtful proof of the goodness or badness of institutions.  For when the
greater states conquer and enslave the lesser, as the Syracusans have done
the Locrians, who appear to be the best-governed people in their part of
the world, or as the Athenians have done the Ceans (and there are ten
thousand other instances of the same sort of thing), all this is not to the
point; let us endeavour rather to form a conclusion about each institution
in itself and say nothing, at present, of victories and defeats.  Let us
only say that such and such a custom is honourable, and another not.  And
first permit me to tell you how good and bad are to be estimated in
reference to these very matters.

MEGILLUS:  How do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  All those who are ready at a moment's notice to praise or
censure any practice which is matter of discussion, seem to me to proceed
in a wrong way.  Let me give you an illustration of what I mean:--You may
suppose a person to be praising wheat as a good kind of food, whereupon
another person instantly blames wheat, without ever enquiring into its
effect or use, or in what way, or to whom, or with what, or in what state
and how, wheat is to be given.  And that is just what we are doing in this
discussion.  At the very mention of the word intoxication, one side is
ready with their praises and the other with their censures; which is
absurd.  For either side adduce their witnesses and approvers, and some of
us think that we speak with authority because we have many witnesses; and
others because they see those who abstain conquering in battle, and this
again is disputed by us.  Now I cannot say that I shall be satisfied, if we
go on discussing each of the remaining laws in the same way.  And about
this very point of intoxication I should like to speak in another way,
which I hold to be the right one; for if number is to be the criterion, are
there not myriads upon myriads of nations ready to dispute the point with
you, who are only two cities?

MEGILLUS:  I shall gladly welcome any method of enquiry which is right.

ATHENIAN:  Let me put the matter thus:--Suppose a person to praise the
keeping of goats, and the creatures themselves as capital things to have,
and then some one who had seen goats feeding without a goatherd in
cultivated spots, and doing mischief, were to censure a goat or any other
animal who has no keeper, or a bad keeper, would there be any sense or
justice in such censure?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  Does a captain require only to have nautical knowledge in order
to be a good captain, whether he is sea-sick or not?  What do you say?

MEGILLUS:  I say that he is not a good captain if, although he have
nautical skill, he is liable to sea-sickness.

ATHENIAN:  And what would you say of the commander of an army?  Will he be
able to command merely because he has military skill if he be a coward,
who, when danger comes, is sick and drunk with fear?

MEGILLUS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  And what if besides being a coward he has no skill?

MEGILLUS:  He is a miserable fellow, not fit to be a commander of men, but
only of old women.

ATHENIAN:  And what would you say of some one who blames or praises any
sort of meeting which is intended by nature to have a ruler, and is well
enough when under his presidency?  The critic, however, has never seen the
society meeting together at an orderly feast under the control of a
president, but always without a ruler or with a bad one:--when observers of
this class praise or blame such meetings, are we to suppose that what they
say is of any value?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly not, if they have never seen or been present at such a
meeting when rightly ordered.

ATHENIAN:  Reflect; may not banqueters and banquets be said to constitute a
kind of meeting?

MEGILLUS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And did any one ever see this sort of convivial meeting rightly
ordered?  Of course you two will answer that you have never seen them at
all, because they are not customary or lawful in your country; but I have
come across many of them in many different places, and moreover I have made
enquiries about them wherever I went, as I may say, and never did I see or
hear of anything of the kind which was carried on altogether rightly; in
some few particulars they might be right, but in general they were utterly
wrong.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean, Stranger, by this remark?  Explain.  For we,
as you say, from our inexperience in such matters, might very likely not
know, even if they came in our way, what was right or wrong in such
societies.

ATHENIAN:  Likely enough; then let me try to be your instructor:  You would
acknowledge, would you not, that in all gatherings of mankind, of whatever
sort, there ought to be a leader?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly I should.

ATHENIAN:  And we were saying just now, that when men are at war the leader
ought to be a brave man?

CLEINIAS:  We were.

ATHENIAN:  The brave man is less likely than the coward to be disturbed by
fears?

CLEINIAS:  That again is true.

ATHENIAN:  And if there were a possibility of having a general of an army
who was absolutely fearless and imperturbable, should we not by all means
appoint him?

CLEINIAS:  Assuredly.

ATHENIAN:  Now, however, we are speaking not of a general who is to command
an army, when foe meets foe in time of war, but of one who is to regulate
meetings of another sort, when friend meets friend in time of peace.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And that sort of meeting, if attended with drunkenness, is apt
to be unquiet.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly; the reverse of quiet.

ATHENIAN:  In the first place, then, the revellers as well as the soldiers
will require a ruler?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure; no men more so.

ATHENIAN:  And we ought, if possible, to provide them with a quiet ruler?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And he should be a man who understands society; for his duty is
to preserve the friendly feelings which exist among the company at the
time, and to increase them for the future by his use of the occasion.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Must we not appoint a sober man and a wise to be our master of
the revels?  For if the ruler of drinkers be himself young and drunken, and
not over-wise, only by some special good fortune will he be saved from
doing some great evil.

CLEINIAS:  It will be by a singular good fortune that he is saved.

ATHENIAN:  Now suppose such associations to be framed in the best way
possible in states, and that some one blames the very fact of their
existence--he may very likely be right.  But if he blames a practice which
he only sees very much mismanaged, he shows in the first place that he is
not aware of the mismanagement, and also not aware that everything done in
this way will turn out to be wrong, because done without the
superintendence of a sober ruler.  Do you not see that a drunken pilot or a
drunken ruler of any sort will ruin ship, chariot, army--anything, in
short, of which he has the direction?

CLEINIAS:  The last remark is very true, Stranger; and I see quite clearly
the advantage of an army having a good leader--he will give victory in war
to his followers, which is a very great advantage; and so of other things. 
But I do not see any similar advantage which either individuals or states
gain from the good management of a feast; and I want you to tell me what
great good will be effected, supposing that this drinking ordinance is duly
established.

ATHENIAN:  If you mean to ask what great good accrues to the state from the
right training of a single youth, or of a single chorus--when the question
is put in that form, we cannot deny that the good is not very great in any
particular instance.  But if you ask what is the good of education in
general, the answer is easy--that education makes good men, and that good
men act nobly, and conquer their enemies in battle, because they are good. 
Education certainly gives victory, although victory sometimes produces
forgetfulness of education; for many have grown insolent from victory in
war, and this insolence has engendered in them innumerable evils; and many
a victory has been and will be suicidal to the victors; but education is
never suicidal.

CLEINIAS:  You seem to imply, my friend, that convivial meetings, when
rightly ordered, are an important element of education.

ATHENIAN:  Certainly I do.

CLEINIAS:  And can you show that what you have been saying is true?

ATHENIAN:  To be absolutely sure of the truth of matters concerning which
there are many opinions, is an attribute of the Gods not given to man,
Stranger; but I shall be very happy to tell you what I think, especially as
we are now proposing to enter on a discussion concerning laws and
constitutions.

CLEINIAS:  Your opinion, Stranger, about the questions which are now being
raised, is precisely what we want to hear.

ATHENIAN:  Very good; I will try to find a way of explaining my meaning,
and you shall try to have the gift of understanding me.  But first let me
make an apology.  The Athenian citizen is reputed among all the Hellenes to
be a great talker, whereas Sparta is renowned for brevity, and the Cretans
have more wit than words.  Now I am afraid of appearing to elicit a very
long discourse out of very small materials.  For drinking indeed may appear
to be a slight matter, and yet is one which cannot be rightly ordered
according to nature, without correct principles of music; these are
necessary to any clear or satisfactory treatment of the subject, and music
again runs up into education generally, and there is much to be said about
all this.  What would you say then to leaving these matters for the
present, and passing on to some other question of law?

MEGILLUS:  O Athenian Stranger, let me tell you what perhaps you do not
know, that our family is the proxenus of your state.  I imagine that from
their earliest youth all boys, when they are told that they are the proxeni
of a particular state, feel kindly towards their second country; and this
has certainly been my own feeling.  I can well remember from the days of my
boyhood, how, when any Lacedaemonians praised or blamed the Athenians, they
used to say to me,--'See, Megillus, how ill or how well,' as the case might
be, 'has your state treated us'; and having always had to fight your
battles against detractors when I heard you assailed, I became warmly
attached to you.  And I always like to hear the Athenian tongue spoken; the
common saying is quite true, that a good Athenian is more than ordinarily
good, for he is the only man who is freely and genuinely good by the divine
inspiration of his own nature, and is not manufactured.  Therefore be
assured that I shall like to hear you say whatever you have to say.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, Stranger; and when you have heard me speak, say boldly what
is in your thoughts.  Let me remind you of a tie which unites you to Crete. 
You must have heard here the story of the prophet Epimenides, who was of my
family, and came to Athens ten years before the Persian war, in accordance
with the response of the Oracle, and offered certain sacrifices which the
God commanded.  The Athenians were at that time in dread of the Persian
invasion; and he said that for ten years they would not come, and that when
they came, they would go away again without accomplishing any of their
objects, and would suffer more evil than they inflicted.  At that time my
forefathers formed ties of hospitality with you; thus ancient is the
friendship which I and my parents have had for you.

ATHENIAN:  You seem to be quite ready to listen; and I am also ready to
perform as much as I can of an almost impossible task, which I will
nevertheless attempt.  At the outset of the discussion, let me define the
nature and power of education; for this is the way by which our argument
must travel onwards to the God Dionysus.

CLEINIAS:  Let us proceed, if you please.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, if I tell you what are my notions of education, will
you consider whether they satisfy you?

CLEINIAS:  Let us hear.

ATHENIAN:  According to my view, any one who would be good at anything must
practise that thing from his youth upwards, both in sport and earnest, in
its several branches:  for example, he who is to be a good builder, should
play at building children's houses; he who is to be a good husbandman, at
tilling the ground; and those who have the care of their education should
provide them when young with mimic tools.  They should learn beforehand the
knowledge which they will afterwards require for their art.  For example,
the future carpenter should learn to measure or apply the line in play; and
the future warrior should learn riding, or some other exercise, for
amusement, and the teacher should endeavour to direct the children's
inclinations and pleasures, by the help of amusements, to their final aim
in life.  The most important part of education is right training in the
nursery.  The soul of the child in his play should be guided to the love of
that sort of excellence in which when he grows up to manhood he will have
to be perfected.  Do you agree with me thus far?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us not leave the meaning of education ambiguous or ill-
defined.  At present, when we speak in terms of praise or blame about the
bringing-up of each person, we call one man educated and another
uneducated, although the uneducated man may be sometimes very well educated
for the calling of a retail trader, or of a captain of a ship, and the
like.  For we are not speaking of education in this narrower sense, but of
that other education in virtue from youth upwards, which makes a man
eagerly pursue the ideal perfection of citizenship, and teaches him how
rightly to rule and how to obey.  This is the only education which, upon
our view, deserves the name; that other sort of training, which aims at the
acquisition of wealth or bodily strength, or mere cleverness apart from
intelligence and justice, is mean and illiberal, and is not worthy to be
called education at all.  But let us not quarrel with one another about a
word, provided that the proposition which has just been granted hold good: 
to wit, that those who are rightly educated generally become good men. 
Neither must we cast a slight upon education, which is the first and
fairest thing that the best of men can ever have, and which, though liable
to take a wrong direction, is capable of reformation.  And this work of
reformation is the great business of every man while he lives.

CLEINIAS:  Very true; and we entirely agree with you.

ATHENIAN:  And we agreed before that they are good men who are able to rule
themselves, and bad men who are not.

CLEINIAS:  You are quite right.

ATHENIAN:  Let me now proceed, if I can, to clear up the subject a little
further by an illustration which I will offer you.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Do we not consider each of ourselves to be one?

CLEINIAS:  We do.

ATHENIAN:  And each one of us has in his bosom two counsellors, both
foolish and also antagonistic; of which we call the one pleasure, and the
other pain.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  Also there are opinions about the future, which have the general
name of expectations; and the specific name of fear, when the expectation
is of pain; and of hope, when of pleasure; and further, there is reflection
about the good or evil of them, and this, when embodied in a decree by the
State, is called Law.

CLEINIAS:  I am hardly able to follow you; proceed, however, as if I were.

MEGILLUS:  I am in the like case.

ATHENIAN:  Let us look at the matter thus:  May we not conceive each of us
living beings to be a puppet of the Gods, either their plaything only, or
created with a purpose--which of the two we cannot certainly know?  But we
do know, that these affections in us are like cords and strings, which pull
us different and opposite ways, and to opposite actions; and herein lies
the difference between virtue and vice.  According to the argument there is
one among these cords which every man ought to grasp and never let go, but
to pull with it against all the rest; and this is the sacred and golden
cord of reason, called by us the common law of the State; there are others
which are hard and of iron, but this one is soft because golden; and there
are several other kinds.  Now we ought always to cooperate with the lead of
the best, which is law.  For inasmuch as reason is beautiful and gentle,
and not violent, her rule must needs have ministers in order to help the
golden principle in vanquishing the other principles.  And thus the moral
of the tale about our being puppets will not have been lost, and the
meaning of the expression 'superior or inferior to a man's self' will
become clearer; and the individual, attaining to right reason in this
matter of pulling the strings of the puppet, should live according to its
rule; while the city, receiving the same from some god or from one who has
knowledge of these things, should embody it in a law, to be her guide in
her dealings with herself and with other states.  In this way virtue and
vice will be more clearly distinguished by us.  And when they have become
clearer, education and other institutions will in like manner become
clearer; and in particular that question of convivial entertainment, which
may seem, perhaps, to have been a very trifling matter, and to have taken a
great many more words than were necessary.

CLEINIAS:  Perhaps, however, the theme may turn out not to be unworthy of
the length of discourse.

ATHENIAN:  Very good; let us proceed with any enquiry which really bears on
our present object.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose that we give this puppet of ours drink,--what will be
the effect on him?

CLEINIAS:  Having what in view do you ask that question?

ATHENIAN:  Nothing as yet; but I ask generally, when the puppet is brought
to the drink, what sort of result is likely to follow.  I will endeavour to
explain my meaning more clearly:  what I am now asking is this--Does the
drinking of wine heighten and increase pleasures and pains, and passions
and loves?

CLEINIAS:  Very greatly.

ATHENIAN:  And are perception and memory, and opinion and prudence,
heightened and increased?  Do not these qualities entirely desert a man if
he becomes saturated with drink?

CLEINIAS:  Yes, they entirely desert him.

ATHENIAN:  Does he not return to the state of soul in which he was when a
young child?

CLEINIAS:  He does.

ATHENIAN:  Then at that time he will have the least control over himself?

CLEINIAS:  The least.

ATHENIAN:  And will he not be in a most wretched plight?

CLEINIAS:  Most wretched.

ATHENIAN:  Then not only an old man but also a drunkard becomes a second
time a child?

CLEINIAS:  Well said, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Is there any argument which will prove to us that we ought to
encourage the taste for drinking instead of doing all we can to avoid it?

CLEINIAS:  I suppose that there is; you at any rate, were just now saying
that you were ready to maintain such a doctrine.

ATHENIAN:  True, I was; and I am ready still, seeing that you have both
declared that you are anxious to hear me.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure we are, if only for the strangeness of the paradox,
which asserts that a man ought of his own accord to plunge into utter
degradation.

ATHENIAN:  Are you speaking of the soul?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And what would you say about the body, my friend?  Are you not
surprised at any one of his own accord bringing upon himself deformity,
leanness, ugliness, decrepitude?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Yet when a man goes of his own accord to a doctor's shop, and
takes medicine, is he not aware that soon, and for many days afterwards, he
will be in a state of body which he would die rather than accept as the
permanent condition of his life?  Are not those who train in gymnasia, at
first beginning reduced to a state of weakness?

CLEINIAS:  Yes, all that is well known.

ATHENIAN:  Also that they go of their own accord for the sake of the
subsequent benefit?

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  And we may conceive this to be true in the same way of other
practices?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And the same view may be taken of the pastime of drinking wine,
if we are right in supposing that the same good effect follows?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  If such convivialities should turn out to have any advantage
equal in importance to that of gymnastic, they are in their very nature to
be preferred to mere bodily exercise, inasmuch as they have no
accompaniment of pain.

CLEINIAS:  True; but I hardly think that we shall be able to discover any
such benefits to be derived from them.

ATHENIAN:  That is just what we must endeavour to show.  And let me ask you
a question:--Do we not distinguish two kinds of fear, which are very
different?

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  There is the fear of expected evil.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And there is the fear of an evil reputation; we are afraid of
being thought evil, because we do or say some dishonourable thing, which
fear we and all men term shame.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  These are the two fears, as I called them; one of which is the
opposite of pain and other fears, and the opposite also of the greatest and
most numerous sort of pleasures.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And does not the legislator and every one who is good for
anything, hold this fear in the greatest honour?  This is what he terms
reverence, and the confidence which is the reverse of this he terms
insolence; and the latter he always deems to be a very great evil both to
individuals and to states.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Does not this kind of fear preserve us in many important ways? 
What is there which so surely gives victory and safety in war?  For there
are two things which give victory--confidence before enemies, and fear of
disgrace before friends.

CLEINIAS:  There are.

ATHENIAN:  Then each of us should be fearless and also fearful; and why we
should be either has now been determined.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And when we want to make any one fearless, we and the law bring
him face to face with many fears.

CLEINIAS:  Clearly.

ATHENIAN:  And when we want to make him rightly fearful, must we not
introduce him to shameless pleasures, and train him to take up arms against
them, and to overcome them?  Or does this principle apply to courage only,
and must he who would be perfect in valour fight against and overcome his
own natural character,--since if he be unpractised and inexperienced in
such conflicts, he will not be half the man which he might have been,--and
are we to suppose, that with temperance it is otherwise, and that he who
has never fought with the shameless and unrighteous temptations of his
pleasures and lusts, and conquered them, in earnest and in play, by word,
deed, and act, will still be perfectly temperate?

CLEINIAS:  A most unlikely supposition.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose that some God had given a fear-potion to men, and that
the more a man drank of this the more he regarded himself at every draught
as a child of misfortune, and that he feared everything happening or about
to happen to him; and that at last the most courageous of men utterly lost
his presence of mind for a time, and only came to himself again when he had
slept off the influence of the draught.

CLEINIAS:  But has such a draught, Stranger, ever really been known among
men?

ATHENIAN:  No; but, if there had been, might not such a draught have been
of use to the legislator as a test of courage?  Might we not go and say to
him, 'O legislator, whether you are legislating for the Cretan, or for any
other state, would you not like to have a touchstone of the courage and
cowardice of your citizens?'

CLEINIAS:  'I should,' will be the answer of every one.

ATHENIAN:  'And you would rather have a touchstone in which there is no
risk and no great danger than the reverse?'

CLEINIAS:  In that proposition every one may safely agree.

ATHENIAN:  'And in order to make use of the draught, you would lead them
amid these imaginary terrors, and prove them, when the affection of fear
was working upon them, and compel them to be fearless, exhorting and
admonishing them; and also honouring them, but dishonouring any one who
will not be persuaded by you to be in all respects such as you command him;
and if he underwent the trial well and manfully, you would let him go
unscathed; but if ill, you would inflict a punishment upon him?  Or would
you abstain from using the potion altogether, although you have no reason
for abstaining?'

CLEINIAS:  He would be certain, Stranger, to use the potion.

ATHENIAN:  This would be a mode of testing and training which would be
wonderfully easy in comparison with those now in use, and might be applied
to a single person, or to a few, or indeed to any number; and he would do
well who provided himself with the potion only, rather than with any number
of other things, whether he preferred to be by himself in solitude, and
there contend with his fears, because he was ashamed to be seen by the eye
of man until he was perfect; or trusting to the force of his own nature and
habits, and believing that he had been already disciplined sufficiently, he
did not hesitate to train himself in company with any number of others, and
display his power in conquering the irresistible change effected by the
draught--his virtue being such, that he never in any instance fell into any
great unseemliness, but was always himself, and left off before he arrived
at the last cup, fearing that he, like all other men, might be overcome by
the potion.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, Stranger, in that last case, too, he might equally show his
self-control.

ATHENIAN:  Let us return to the lawgiver, and say to him:--'Well, lawgiver,
there is certainly no such fear-potion which man has either received from
the Gods or himself discovered; for witchcraft has no place at our board. 
But is there any potion which might serve as a test of overboldness and
excessive and indiscreet boasting?

CLEINIAS:  I suppose that he will say, Yes,--meaning that wine is such a
potion.

ATHENIAN:  Is not the effect of this quite the opposite of the effect of
the other?  When a man drinks wine he begins to be better pleased with
himself, and the more he drinks the more he is filled full of brave hopes,
and conceit of his power, and at last the string of his tongue is loosened,
and fancying himself wise, he is brimming over with lawlessness, and has no
more fear or respect, and is ready to do or say anything.

CLEINIAS:  I think that every one will admit the truth of your description.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Now, let us remember, as we were saying, that there are two
things which should be cultivated in the soul:  first, the greatest
courage; secondly, the greatest fear--

CLEINIAS:  Which you said to be characteristic of reverence, if I am not
mistaken.

ATHENIAN:  Thank you for reminding me.  But now, as the habit of courage
and fearlessness is to be trained amid fears, let us consider whether the
opposite quality is not also to be trained among opposites.

CLEINIAS:  That is probably the case.

ATHENIAN:  There are times and seasons at which we are by nature more than
commonly valiant and bold; now we ought to train ourselves on these
occasions to be as free from impudence and shamelessness as possible, and
to be afraid to say or suffer or do anything that is base.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Are not the moments in which we are apt to be bold and shameless
such as these?--when we are under the influence of anger, love, pride,
ignorance, avarice, cowardice? or when wealth, beauty, strength, and all
the intoxicating workings of pleasure madden us?  What is better adapted
than the festive use of wine, in the first place to test, and in the second
place to train the character of a man, if care be taken in the use of it? 
What is there cheaper, or more innocent?  For do but consider which is the
greater risk:--Would you rather test a man of a morose and savage nature,
which is the source of ten thousand acts of injustice, by making bargains
with him at a risk to yourself, or by having him as a companion at the
festival of Dionysus?  Or would you, if you wanted to apply a touchstone to
a man who is prone to love, entrust your wife, or your sons, or daughters
to him, perilling your dearest interests in order to have a view of the
condition of his soul?  I might mention numberless cases, in which the
advantage would be manifest of getting to know a character in sport, and
without paying dearly for experience.  And I do not believe that either a
Cretan, or any other man, will doubt that such a test is a fair test, and
safer, cheaper, and speedier than any other.

CLEINIAS:  That is certainly true.

ATHENIAN:  And this knowledge of the natures and habits of men's souls will
be of the greatest use in that art which has the management of them; and
that art, if I am not mistaken, is politics.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly so.


BOOK II.

ATHENIAN:  And now we have to consider whether the insight into human
nature is the only benefit derived from well-ordered potations, or whether
there are not other advantages great and much to be desired.  The argument
seems to imply that there are.  But how and in what way these are to be
attained, will have to be considered attentively, or we may be entangled in
error.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Let me once more recall our doctrine of right education; which,
if I am not mistaken, depends on the due regulation of convivial
intercourse.

CLEINIAS:  You talk rather grandly.

ATHENIAN:  Pleasure and pain I maintain to be the first perceptions of
children, and I say that they are the forms under which virtue and vice are
originally present to them.  As to wisdom and true and fixed opinions,
happy is the man who acquires them, even when declining in years; and we
may say that he who possesses them, and the blessings which are contained
in them, is a perfect man.  Now I mean by education that training which is
given by suitable habits to the first instincts of virtue in children;--
when pleasure, and friendship, and pain, and hatred, are rightly implanted
in souls not yet capable of understanding the nature of them, and who find
them, after they have attained reason, to be in harmony with her.  This
harmony of the soul, taken as a whole, is virtue; but the particular
training in respect of pleasure and pain, which leads you always to hate
what you ought to hate, and love what you ought to love from the beginning
of life to the end, may be separated off; and, in my view, will be rightly
called education.

CLEINIAS:  I think, Stranger, that you are quite right in all that you have
said and are saying about education.

ATHENIAN:  I am glad to hear that you agree with me; for, indeed, the
discipline of pleasure and pain which, when rightly ordered, is a principle
of education, has been often relaxed and corrupted in human life.  And the
Gods, pitying the toils which our race is born to undergo, have appointed
holy festivals, wherein men alternate rest with labour; and have given them
the Muses and Apollo, the leader of the Muses, and Dionysus, to be
companions in their revels, that they may improve their education by taking
part in the festivals of the Gods, and with their help.  I should like to
know whether a common saying is in our opinion true to nature or not.  For
men say that the young of all creatures cannot be quiet in their bodies or
in their voices; they are always wanting to move and cry out; some leaping
and skipping, and overflowing with sportiveness and delight at something,
others uttering all sorts of cries.  But, whereas the animals have no
perception of order or disorder in their movements, that is, of rhythm or
harmony, as they are called, to us, the Gods, who, as we say, have been
appointed to be our companions in the dance, have given the pleasurable
sense of harmony and rhythm; and so they stir us into life, and we follow
them, joining hands together in dances and songs; and these they call
choruses, which is a term naturally expressive of cheerfulness.  Shall we
begin, then, with the acknowledgment that education is first given through
Apollo and the Muses?  What do you say?

CLEINIAS:  I assent.

ATHENIAN:  And the uneducated is he who has not been trained in the chorus,
and the educated is he who has been well trained?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And the chorus is made up of two parts, dance and song?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Then he who is well educated will be able to sing and dance
well?

CLEINIAS:  I suppose that he will.

ATHENIAN:  Let us see; what are we saying?

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  He sings well and dances well; now must we add that he sings
what is good and dances what is good?

CLEINIAS:  Let us make the addition.

ATHENIAN:  We will suppose that he knows the good to be good, and the bad
to be bad, and makes use of them accordingly:  which now is the better
trained in dancing and music--he who is able to move his body and to use
his voice in what is understood to be the right manner, but has no delight
in good or hatred of evil; or he who is incorrect in gesture and voice, but
is right in his sense of pleasure and pain, and welcomes what is good, and
is offended at what is evil?

CLEINIAS:  There is a great difference, Stranger, in the two kinds of
education.

ATHENIAN:  If we three know what is good in song and dance, then we truly
know also who is educated and who is uneducated; but if not, then we
certainly shall not know wherein lies the safeguard of education, and
whether there is any or not.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Let us follow the scent like hounds, and go in pursuit of beauty
of figure, and melody, and song, and dance; if these escape us, there will
be no use in talking about true education, whether Hellenic or barbarian.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And what is beauty of figure, or beautiful melody?  When a manly
soul is in trouble, and when a cowardly soul is in similar case, are they
likely to use the same figures and gestures, or to give utterance to the
same sounds?

CLEINIAS:  How can they, when the very colours of their faces differ?

ATHENIAN:  Good, my friend; I may observe, however, in passing, that in
music there certainly are figures and there are melodies:  and music is
concerned with harmony and rhythm, so that you may speak of a melody or
figure having good rhythm or good harmony--the term is correct enough; but
to speak metaphorically of a melody or figure having a 'good colour,' as
the masters of choruses do, is not allowable, although you can speak of the
melodies or figures of the brave and the coward, praising the one and
censuring the other.  And not to be tedious, let us say that the figures
and melodies which are expressive of virtue of soul or body, or of images
of virtue, are without exception good, and those which are expressive of
vice are the reverse of good.

CLEINIAS:  Your suggestion is excellent; and let us answer that these
things are so.

ATHENIAN:  Once more, are all of us equally delighted with every sort of
dance?

CLEINIAS:  Far otherwise.

ATHENIAN:  What, then, leads us astray?  Are beautiful things not the same
to us all, or are they the same in themselves, but not in our opinion of
them?  For no one will admit that forms of vice in the dance are more
beautiful than forms of virtue, or that he himself delights in the forms of
vice, and others in a muse of another character.  And yet most persons say,
that the excellence of music is to give pleasure to our souls.  But this is
intolerable and blasphemous; there is, however, a much more plausible
account of the delusion.

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  The adaptation of art to the characters of men.  Choric
movements are imitations of manners occurring in various actions, fortunes,
dispositions,--each particular is imitated, and those to whom the words, or
songs, or dances are suited, either by nature or habit or both, cannot help
feeling pleasure in them and applauding them, and calling them beautiful. 
But those whose natures, or ways, or habits are unsuited to them, cannot
delight in them or applaud them, and they call them base.  There are
others, again, whose natures are right and their habits wrong, or whose
habits are right and their natures wrong, and they praise one thing, but
are pleased at another.  For they say that all these imitations are
pleasant, but not good.  And in the presence of those whom they think wise,
they are ashamed of dancing and singing in the baser manner, or of
deliberately lending any countenance to such proceedings; and yet, they
have a secret pleasure in them.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And is any harm done to the lover of vicious dances or songs, or
any good done to the approver of the opposite sort of pleasure?

CLEINIAS:  I think that there is.

ATHENIAN:  'I think' is not the word, but I would say, rather, 'I am
certain.'  For must they not have the same effect as when a man associates
with bad characters, whom he likes and approves rather than dislikes, and
only censures playfully because he has a suspicion of his own badness?  In
that case, he who takes pleasure in them will surely become like those in
whom he takes pleasure, even though he be ashamed to praise them.  And what
greater good or evil can any destiny ever make us undergo?

CLEINIAS:  I know of none.

ATHENIAN:  Then in a city which has good laws, or in future ages is to have
them, bearing in mind the instruction and amusement which are given by
music, can we suppose that the poets are to be allowed to teach in the
dance anything which they themselves like, in the way of rhythm, or melody,
or words, to the young children of any well-conditioned parents?  Is the
poet to train his choruses as he pleases, without reference to virtue or
vice?

CLEINIAS:  That is surely quite unreasonable, and is not to be thought of.

ATHENIAN:  And yet he may do this in almost any state with the exception of
Egypt.

CLEINIAS:  And what are the laws about music and dancing in Egypt?

ATHENIAN:  You will wonder when I tell you:  Long ago they appear to have
recognized the very principle of which we are now speaking--that their
young citizens must be habituated to forms and strains of virtue.  These
they fixed, and exhibited the patterns of them in their temples; and no
painter or artist is allowed to innovate upon them, or to leave the
traditional forms and invent new ones.  To this day, no alteration is
allowed either in these arts, or in music at all.  And you will find that
their works of art are painted or moulded in the same forms which they had
ten thousand years ago;--this is literally true and no exaggeration,--their
ancient paintings and sculptures are not a whit better or worse than the
work of to-day, but are made with just the same skill.

CLEINIAS:  How extraordinary!

ATHENIAN:  I should rather say, How statesmanlike, how worthy of a
legislator!  I know that other things in Egypt are not so well.  But what I
am telling you about music is true and deserving of consideration, because
showing that a lawgiver may institute melodies which have a natural truth
and correctness without any fear of failure.  To do this, however, must be
the work of God, or of a divine person; in Egypt they have a tradition that
their ancient chants which have been preserved for so many ages are the
composition of the Goddess Isis.  And therefore, as I was saying, if a
person can only find in any way the natural melodies, he may confidently
embody them in a fixed and legal form.  For the love of novelty which
arises out of pleasure in the new and weariness of the old, has not
strength enough to corrupt the consecrated song and dance, under the plea
that they have become antiquated.  At any rate, they are far from being
corrupted in Egypt.

CLEINIAS:  Your arguments seem to prove your point.

ATHENIAN:  May we not confidently say that the true use of music and of
choral festivities is as follows:  We rejoice when we think that we
prosper, and again we think that we prosper when we rejoice?

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  And when rejoicing in our good fortune, we are unable to be
still?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Our young men break forth into dancing and singing, and we who
are their elders deem that we are fulfilling our part in life when we look
on at them.  Having lost our agility, we delight in their sports and merry-
making, because we love to think of our former selves; and gladly institute
contests for those who are able to awaken in us the memory of our youth.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Is it altogether unmeaning to say, as the common people do about
festivals, that he should be adjudged the wisest of men, and the winner of
the palm, who gives us the greatest amount of pleasure and mirth?  For on
such occasions, and when mirth is the order of the day, ought not he to be
honoured most, and, as I was saying, bear the palm, who gives most mirth to
the greatest number?  Now is this a true way of speaking or of acting?

CLEINIAS:  Possibly.

ATHENIAN:  But, my dear friend, let us distinguish between different cases,
and not be hasty in forming a judgment:  One way of considering the
question will be to imagine a festival at which there are entertainments of
all sorts, including gymnastic, musical, and equestrian contests:  the
citizens are assembled; prizes are offered, and proclamation is made that
any one who likes may enter the lists, and that he is to bear the palm who
gives the most pleasure to the spectators--there is to be no regulation
about the manner how; but he who is most successful in giving pleasure is
to be crowned victor, and deemed to be the pleasantest of the candidates: 
What is likely to be the result of such a proclamation?

CLEINIAS:  In what respect?

ATHENIAN:  There would be various exhibitions:  one man, like Homer, will
exhibit a rhapsody, another a performance on the lute; one will have a
tragedy, and another a comedy.  Nor would there be anything astonishing in
some one imagining that he could gain the prize by exhibiting a puppet-
show.  Suppose these competitors to meet, and not these only, but
innumerable others as well--can you tell me who ought to be the victor?

CLEINIAS:  I do not see how any one can answer you, or pretend to know,
unless he has heard with his own ears the several competitors; the question
is absurd.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, if neither of you can answer, shall I answer this
question which you deem so absurd?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  If very small children are to determine the question, they will
decide for the puppet show.

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  The older children will be advocates of comedy; educated women,
and young men, and people in general, will favour tragedy.

CLEINIAS:  Very likely.

ATHENIAN:  And I believe that we old men would have the greatest pleasure
in hearing a rhapsodist recite well the Iliad and Odyssey, or one of the
Hesiodic poems, and would award the victory to him.  But, who would really
be the victor?--that is the question.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Clearly you and I will have to declare that those whom we old
men adjudge victors ought to win; for our ways are far and away better than
any which at present exist anywhere in the world.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Thus far I too should agree with the many, that the excellence
of music is to be measured by pleasure.  But the pleasure must not be that
of chance persons; the fairest music is that which delights the best and
best educated, and especially that which delights the one man who is pre-
eminent in virtue and education.  And therefore the judges must be men of
character, for they will require both wisdom and courage; the true judge
must not draw his inspiration from the theatre, nor ought he to be unnerved
by the clamour of the many and his own incapacity; nor again, knowing the
truth, ought he through cowardice and unmanliness carelessly to deliver a
lying judgment, with the very same lips which have just appealed to the
Gods before he judged.  He is sitting not as the disciple of the theatre,
but, in his proper place, as their instructor, and he ought to be the enemy
of all pandering to the pleasure of the spectators.  The ancient and common
custom of Hellas, which still prevails in Italy and Sicily, did certainly
leave the judgment to the body of spectators, who determined the victor by
show of hands.  But this custom has been the destruction of the poets; for
they are now in the habit of composing with a view to please the bad taste
of their judges, and the result is that the spectators instruct
themselves;--and also it has been the ruin of the theatre; they ought to be
having characters put before them better than their own, and so receiving a
higher pleasure, but now by their own act the opposite result follows. 
What inference is to be drawn from all this?  Shall I tell you?

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  The inference at which we arrive for the third or fourth time
is, that education is the constraining and directing of youth towards that
right reason, which the law affirms, and which the experience of the eldest
and best has agreed to be truly right.  In order, then, that the soul of
the child may not be habituated to feel joy and sorrow in a manner at
variance with the law, and those who obey the law, but may rather follow
the law and rejoice and sorrow at the same things as the aged--in order, I
say, to produce this effect, chants appear to have been invented, which
really enchant, and are designed to implant that harmony of which we speak. 
And, because the mind of the child is incapable of enduring serious
training, they are called plays and songs, and are performed in play; just
as when men are sick and ailing in their bodies, their attendants give them
wholesome diet in pleasant meats and drinks, but unwholesome diet in
disagreeable things, in order that they may learn, as they ought, to like
the one, and to dislike the other.  And similarly the true legislator will
persuade, and, if he cannot persuade, will compel the poet to express, as
he ought, by fair and noble words, in his rhythms, the figures, and in his
melodies, the music of temperate and brave and in every way good men.

CLEINIAS:  But do you really imagine, Stranger, that this is the way in
which poets generally compose in States at the present day?  As far as I
can observe, except among us and among the Lacedaemonians, there are no
regulations like those of which you speak; in other places novelties are
always being introduced in dancing and in music, generally not under the
authority of any law, but at the instigation of lawless pleasures; and
these pleasures are so far from being the same, as you describe the
Egyptian to be, or having the same principles, that they are never the
same.

ATHENIAN:  Most true, Cleinias; and I daresay that I may have expressed
myself obscurely, and so led you to imagine that I was speaking of some
really existing state of things, whereas I was only saying what regulations
I would like to have about music; and hence there occurred a
misapprehension on your part.  For when evils are far gone and
irremediable, the task of censuring them is never pleasant, although at
times necessary.  But as we do not really differ, will you let me ask you
whether you consider such institutions to be more prevalent among the
Cretans and Lacedaemonians than among the other Hellenes?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly they are.

ATHENIAN:  And if they were extended to the other Hellenes, would it be an
improvement on the present state of things?

CLEINIAS:  A very great improvement, if the customs which prevail among
them were such as prevail among us and the Lacedaemonians, and such as you
were just now saying ought to prevail.

ATHENIAN:  Let us see whether we understand one another:--Are not the
principles of education and music which prevail among you as follows:  you
compel your poets to say that the good man, if he be temperate and just, is
fortunate and happy; and this whether he be great and strong or small and
weak, and whether he be rich or poor; and, on the other hand, if he have a
wealth passing that of Cinyras or Midas, and be unjust, he is wretched and
lives in misery?  As the poet says, and with truth:  I sing not, I care not
about him who accomplishes all noble things, not having justice; let him
who 'draws near and stretches out his hand against his enemies be a just
man.'  But if he be unjust, I would not have him 'look calmly upon bloody
death,' nor 'surpass in swiftness the Thracian Boreas;' and let no other
thing that is called good ever be his.  For the goods of which the many
speak are not really good:  first in the catalogue is placed health, beauty
next, wealth third; and then innumerable others, as for example to have a
keen eye or a quick ear, and in general to have all the senses perfect; or,
again, to be a tyrant and do as you like; and the final consummation of
happiness is to have acquired all these things, and when you have acquired
them to become at once immortal.  But you and I say, that while to the just
and holy all these things are the best of possessions, to the unjust they
are all, including even health, the greatest of evils.  For in truth, to
have sight, and hearing, and the use of the senses, or to live at all
without justice and virtue, even though a man be rich in all the so-called
goods of fortune, is the greatest of evils, if life be immortal; but not so
great, if the bad man lives only a very short time.  These are the truths
which, if I am not mistaken, you will persuade or compel your poets to
utter with suitable accompaniments of harmony and rhythm, and in these they
must train up your youth.  Am I not right?  For I plainly declare that
evils as they are termed are goods to the unjust, and only evils to the
just, and that goods are truly good to the good, but evil to the evil.  Let
me ask again, Are you and I agreed about this?

CLEINIAS:  I think that we partly agree and partly do not.

ATHENIAN:  When a man has health and wealth and a tyranny which lasts, and
when he is pre-eminent in strength and courage, and has the gift of
immortality, and none of the so-called evils which counter-balance these
goods, but only the injustice and insolence of his own nature--of such an
one you are, I suspect, unwilling to believe that he is miserable rather
than happy.

CLEINIAS:  That is quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Once more:  Suppose that he be valiant and strong, and handsome
and rich, and does throughout his whole life whatever he likes, still, if
he be unrighteous and insolent, would not both of you agree that he will of
necessity live basely?  You will surely grant so much?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And an evil life too?

CLEINIAS:  I am not equally disposed to grant that.

ATHENIAN:  Will he not live painfully and to his own disadvantage?

CLEINIAS:  How can I possibly say so?

ATHENIAN:  How!  Then may Heaven make us to be of one mind, for now we are
of two.  To me, dear Cleinias, the truth of what I am saying is as plain as
the fact that Crete is an island.  And, if I were a lawgiver, I would try
to make the poets and all the citizens speak in this strain, and I would
inflict the heaviest penalties on any one in all the land who should dare
to say that there are bad men who lead pleasant lives, or that the
profitable and gainful is one thing, and the just another; and there are
many other matters about which I should make my citizens speak in a manner
different from the Cretans and Lacedaemonians of this age, and I may say,
indeed, from the world in general.  For tell me, my good friends, by Zeus
and Apollo tell me, if I were to ask these same Gods who were your
legislators,--Is not the most just life also the pleasantest? or are there
two lives, one of which is the justest and the other the pleasantest?--and
they were to reply that there are two; and thereupon I proceeded to ask,
(that would be the right way of pursuing the enquiry), Which are the
happier--those who lead the justest, or those who lead the pleasantest
life? and they replied, Those who lead the pleasantest--that would be a
very strange answer, which I should not like to put into the mouth of the
Gods.  The words will come with more propriety from the lips of fathers and
legislators, and therefore I will repeat my former questions to one of
them, and suppose him to say again that he who leads the pleasantest life
is the happiest.  And to that I rejoin:--O my father, did you not wish me
to live as happily as possible?  And yet you also never ceased telling me
that I should live as justly as possible.  Now, here the giver of the rule,
whether he be legislator or father, will be in a dilemma, and will in vain
endeavour to be consistent with himself.  But if he were to declare that
the justest life is also the happiest, every one hearing him would enquire,
if I am not mistaken, what is that good and noble principle in life which
the law approves, and which is superior to pleasure.  For what good can the
just man have which is separated from pleasure?  Shall we say that glory
and fame, coming from Gods and men, though good and noble, are nevertheless
unpleasant, and infamy pleasant?  Certainly not, sweet legislator.  Or
shall we say that the not-doing of wrong and there being no wrong done is
good and honourable, although there is no pleasure in it, and that the
doing wrong is pleasant, but evil and base?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  The view which identifies the pleasant and the pleasant and the
just and the good and the noble has an excellent moral and religious
tendency.  And the opposite view is most at variance with the designs of
the legislator, and is, in his opinion, infamous; for no one, if he can
help, will be persuaded to do that which gives him more pain than pleasure. 
But as distant prospects are apt to make us dizzy, especially in childhood,
the legislator will try to purge away the darkness and exhibit the truth;
he will persuade the citizens, in some way or other, by customs and praises
and words, that just and unjust are shadows only, and that injustice, which
seems opposed to justice, when contemplated by the unjust and evil man
appears pleasant and the just most unpleasant; but that from the just man's
point of view, the very opposite is the appearance of both of them.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And which may be supposed to be the truer judgment--that of the
inferior or of the better soul?

CLEINIAS:  Surely, that of the better soul.

ATHENIAN:  Then the unjust life must not only be more base and depraved,
but also more unpleasant than the just and holy life?

CLEINIAS:  That seems to be implied in the present argument.

ATHENIAN:  And even supposing this were otherwise, and not as the argument
has proven, still the lawgiver, who is worth anything, if he ever ventures
to tell a lie to the young for their good, could not invent a more useful
lie than this, or one which will have a better effect in making them do
what is right, not on compulsion but voluntarily.

CLEINIAS:  Truth, Stranger, is a noble thing and a lasting, but a thing of
which men are hard to be persuaded.

ATHENIAN:  And yet the story of the Sidonian Cadmus, which is so
improbable, has been readily believed, and also innumerable other tales.

CLEINIAS:  What is that story?

ATHENIAN:  The story of armed men springing up after the sowing of teeth,
which the legislator may take as a proof that he can persuade the minds of
the young of anything; so that he has only to reflect and find out what
belief will be of the greatest public advantage, and then use all his
efforts to make the whole community utter one and the same word in their
songs and tales and discourses all their life long.  But if you do not
agree with me, there is no reason why you should not argue on the other
side.

CLEINIAS:  I do not see that any argument can fairly be raised by either of
us against what you are now saying.

ATHENIAN:  The next suggestion which I have to offer is, that all our three
choruses shall sing to the young and tender souls of children, reciting in
their strains all the noble thoughts of which we have already spoken, or
are about to speak; and the sum of them shall be, that the life which is by
the Gods deemed to be the happiest is also the best;--we shall affirm this
to be a most certain truth; and the minds of our young disciples will be
more likely to receive these words of ours than any others which we might
address to them.

CLEINIAS:  I assent to what you say.

ATHENIAN:  First will enter in their natural order the sacred choir
composed of children, which is to sing lustily the heaven-taught lay to the
whole city.  Next will follow the choir of young men under the age of
thirty, who will call upon the God Paean to testify to the truth of their
words, and will pray him to be gracious to the youth and to turn their
hearts.  Thirdly, the choir of elder men, who are from thirty to sixty
years of age, will also sing.  There remain those who are too old to sing,
and they will tell stories, illustrating the same virtues, as with the
voice of an oracle.

CLEINIAS:  Who are those who compose the third choir, Stranger? for I do
not clearly understand what you mean to say about them.

ATHENIAN:  And yet almost all that I have been saying has been said with a
view to them.

CLEINIAS:  Will you try to be a little plainer?

ATHENIAN:  I was speaking at the commencement of our discourse, as you will
remember, of the fiery nature of young creatures:  I said that they were
unable to keep quiet either in limb or voice, and that they called out and
jumped about in a disorderly manner; and that no other animal attained to
any perception of order, but man only.  Now the order of motion is called
rhythm, and the order of the voice, in which high and low are duly mingled,
is called harmony; and both together are termed choric song.  And I said
that the Gods had pity on us, and gave us Apollo and the Muses to be our
playfellows and leaders in the dance; and Dionysus, as I dare say that you
will remember, was the third.

CLEINIAS:  I quite remember.

ATHENIAN:  Thus far I have spoken of the chorus of Apollo and the Muses,
and I have still to speak of the remaining chorus, which is that of
Dionysus.

CLEINIAS:  How is that arranged?  There is something strange, at any rate
on first hearing, in a Dionysiac chorus of old men, if you really mean that
those who are above thirty, and may be fifty, or from fifty to sixty years
of age, are to dance in his honour.

ATHENIAN:  Very true; and therefore it must be shown that there is good
reason for the proposal.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Are we agreed thus far?

CLEINIAS:  About what?

ATHENIAN:  That every man and boy, slave and free, both sexes, and the
whole city, should never cease charming themselves with the strains of
which we have spoken; and that there should be every sort of change and
variation of them in order to take away the effect of sameness, so that the
singers may always receive pleasure from their hymns, and may never weary
of them?

CLEINIAS:  Every one will agree.

ATHENIAN:  Where, then, will that best part of our city which, by reason of
age and intelligence, has the greatest influence, sing these fairest of
strains, which are to do so much good?  Shall we be so foolish as to let
them off who would give us the most beautiful and also the most useful of
songs?

CLEINIAS:  But, says the argument, we cannot let them off.

ATHENIAN:  Then how can we carry out our purpose with decorum?  Will this
be the way?

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  When a man is advancing in years, he is afraid and reluctant to
sing;--he has no pleasure in his own performances; and if compulsion is
used, he will be more and more ashamed, the older and more discreet he
grows;--is not this true?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Well, and will he not be yet more ashamed if he has to stand up
and sing in the theatre to a mixed audience?--and if moreover when he is
required to do so, like the other choirs who contend for prizes, and have
been trained under a singing master, he is pinched and hungry, he will
certainly have a feeling of shame and discomfort which will make him very
unwilling to exhibit.

CLEINIAS:  No doubt.

ATHENIAN:  How, then, shall we reassure him, and get him to sing?  Shall we
begin by enacting that boys shall not taste wine at all until they are
eighteen years of age; we will tell them that fire must not be poured upon
fire, whether in the body or in the soul, until they begin to go to work--
this is a precaution which has to be taken against the excitableness of
youth;--afterwards they may taste wine in moderation up to the age of
thirty, but while a man is young he should abstain altogether from
intoxication and from excess of wine; when, at length, he has reached forty
years, after dinner at a public mess, he may invite not only the other
Gods, but Dionysus above all, to the mystery and festivity of the elder
men, making use of the wine which he has given men to lighten the sourness
of old age; that in age we may renew our youth, and forget our sorrows; and
also in order that the nature of the soul, like iron melted in the fire,
may become softer and so more impressible.  In the first place, will not
any one who is thus mellowed be more ready and less ashamed to sing--I do
not say before a large audience, but before a moderate company; nor yet
among strangers, but among his familiars, and, as we have often said, to
chant, and to enchant?

CLEINIAS:  He will be far more ready.

ATHENIAN:  There will be no impropriety in our using such a method of
persuading them to join with us in song.

CLEINIAS:  None at all.

ATHENIAN:  And what strain will they sing, and what muse will they hymn? 
The strain should clearly be one suitable to them.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And what strain is suitable for heroes?  Shall they sing a
choric strain?

CLEINIAS:  Truly, Stranger, we of Crete and Lacedaemon know no strain other
than that which we have learnt and been accustomed to sing in our chorus.

ATHENIAN:  I dare say; for you have never acquired the knowledge of the
most beautiful kind of song, in your military way of life, which is
modelled after the camp, and is not like that of dwellers in cities; and
you have your young men herding and feeding together like young colts.  No
one takes his own individual colt and drags him away from his fellows
against his will, raging and foaming, and gives him a groom to attend to
him alone, and trains and rubs him down privately, and gives him the
qualities in education which will make him not only a good soldier, but
also a governor of a state and of cities.  Such an one, as we said at
first, would be a greater warrior than he of whom Tyrtaeus sings; and he
would honour courage everywhere, but always as the fourth, and not as the
first part of virtue, either in individuals or states.

CLEINIAS:  Once more, Stranger, I must complain that you depreciate our
lawgivers.

ATHENIAN:  Not intentionally, if at all, my good friend; but whither the
argument leads, thither let us follow; for if there be indeed some strain
of song more beautiful than that of the choruses or the public theatres, I
should like to impart it to those who, as we say, are ashamed of these, and
want to have the best.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  When things have an accompanying charm, either the best thing in
them is this very charm, or there is some rightness or utility possessed by
them;--for example, I should say that eating and drinking, and the use of
food in general, have an accompanying charm which we call pleasure; but
that this rightness and utility is just the healthfulness of the things
served up to us, which is their true rightness.

CLEINIAS:  Just so.

ATHENIAN:  Thus, too, I should say that learning has a certain accompanying
charm which is the pleasure; but that the right and the profitable, the
good and the noble, are qualities which the truth gives to it.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  And so in the imitative arts--if they succeed in making
likenesses, and are accompanied by pleasure, may not their works be said to
have a charm?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  But equal proportions, whether of quality or quantity, and not
pleasure, speaking generally, would give them truth or rightness.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Then that only can be rightly judged by the standard of
pleasure, which makes or furnishes no utility or truth or likeness, nor on
the other hand is productive of any hurtful quality, but exists solely for
the sake of the accompanying charm; and the term 'pleasure' is most
appropriately applied to it when these other qualities are absent.

CLEINIAS:  You are speaking of harmless pleasure, are you not?

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and this I term amusement, when doing neither harm nor good
in any degree worth speaking of.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Then, if such be our principles, we must assert that imitation
is not to be judged of by pleasure and false opinion; and this is true of
all equality, for the equal is not equal or the symmetrical symmetrical,
because somebody thinks or likes something, but they are to be judged of by
the standard of truth, and by no other whatever.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Do we not regard all music as representative and imitative?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then, when any one says that music is to be judged of by
pleasure, his doctrine cannot be admitted; and if there be any music of
which pleasure is the criterion, such music is not to be sought out or
deemed to have any real excellence, but only that other kind of music which
is an imitation of the good.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And those who seek for the best kind of song and music ought not
to seek for that which is pleasant, but for that which is true; and the
truth of imitation consists, as we were saying, in rendering the thing
imitated according to quantity and quality.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And every one will admit that musical compositions are all
imitative and representative.  Will not poets and spectators and actors all
agree in this?

CLEINIAS:  They will.

ATHENIAN:  Surely then he who would judge correctly must know what each
composition is; for if he does not know what is the character and meaning
of the piece, and what it represents, he will never discern whether the
intention is true or false.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  And will he who does not know what is true be able to
distinguish what is good and bad?  My statement is not very clear; but
perhaps you will understand me better if I put the matter in another way.

CLEINIAS:  How?

ATHENIAN:  There are ten thousand likenesses of objects of sight?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And can he who does not know what the exact object is which is
imitated, ever know whether the resemblance is truthfully executed?  I
mean, for example, whether a statue has the proportions of a body, and the
true situation of the parts; what those proportions are, and how the parts
fit into one another in due order; also their colours and conformations, or
whether this is all confused in the execution:  do you think that any one
can know about this, who does not know what the animal is which has been
imitated?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  But even if we know that the thing pictured or sculptured is a
man, who has received at the hand of the artist all his proper parts and
colours and shapes, must we not also know whether the work is beautiful or
in any respect deficient in beauty?

CLEINIAS:  If this were not required, Stranger, we should all of us be
judges of beauty.

ATHENIAN:  Very true; and may we not say that in everything imitated,
whether in drawing, music, or any other art, he who is to be a competent
judge must possess three things;--he must know, in the first place, of what
the imitation is; secondly, he must know that it is true; and thirdly, that
it has been well executed in words and melodies and rhythms?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us not faint in discussing the peculiar difficulty of
music.  Music is more celebrated than any other kind of imitation, and
therefore requires the greatest care of them all.  For if a man makes a
mistake here, he may do himself the greatest injury by welcoming evil
dispositions, and the mistake may be very difficult to discern, because the
poets are artists very inferior in character to the Muses themselves, who
would never fall into the monstrous error of assigning to the words of men
the gestures and songs of women; nor after combining the melodies with the
gestures of freemen would they add on the rhythms of slaves and men of the
baser sort; nor, beginning with the rhythms and gestures of freemen, would
they assign to them a melody or words which are of an opposite character;
nor would they mix up the voices and sounds of animals and of men and
instruments, and every other sort of noise, as if they were all one.  But
human poets are fond of introducing this sort of inconsistent mixture, and
so make themselves ridiculous in the eyes of those who, as Orpheus says,
'are ripe for true pleasure.'  The experienced see all this confusion, and
yet the poets go on and make still further havoc by separating the rhythm
and the figure of the dance from the melody, setting bare words to metre,
and also separating the melody and the rhythm from the words, using the
lyre or the flute alone.  For when there are no words, it is very difficult
to recognize the meaning of the harmony and rhythm, or to see that any
worthy object is imitated by them.  And we must acknowledge that all this
sort of thing, which aims only at swiftness and smoothness and a brutish
noise, and uses the flute and the lyre not as the mere accompaniments of
the dance and song, is exceedingly coarse and tasteless.  The use of either
instrument, when unaccompanied, leads to every sort of irregularity and
trickery.  This is all rational enough.  But we are considering not how our
choristers, who are from thirty to fifty years of age, and may be over
fifty, are not to use the Muses, but how they are to use them.  And the
considerations which we have urged seem to show in what way these fifty
years' old choristers who are to sing, may be expected to be better
trained.  For they need to have a quick perception and knowledge of
harmonies and rhythms; otherwise, how can they ever know whether a melody
would be rightly sung to the Dorian mode, or to the rhythm which the poet
has assigned to it?

CLEINIAS:  Clearly they cannot.

ATHENIAN:  The many are ridiculous in imagining that they know what is in
proper harmony and rhythm, and what is not, when they can only be made to
sing and step in rhythm by force; it never occurs to them that they are
ignorant of what they are doing.  Now every melody is right when it has
suitable harmony and rhythm, and wrong when unsuitable.

CLEINIAS:  That is most certain.

ATHENIAN:  But can a man who does not know a thing, as we were saying, know
that the thing is right?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  Then now, as would appear, we are making the discovery that our
newly-appointed choristers, whom we hereby invite and, although they are
their own masters, compel to sing, must be educated to such an extent as to
be able to follow the steps of the rhythm and the notes of the song, that
they may know the harmonies and rhythms, and be able to select what are
suitable for men of their age and character to sing; and may sing them, and
have innocent pleasure from their own performance, and also lead younger
men to welcome with dutiful delight good dispositions.  Having such
training, they will attain a more accurate knowledge than falls to the lot
of the common people, or even of the poets themselves.  For the poet need
not know the third point, viz., whether the imitation is good or not,
though he can hardly help knowing the laws of melody and rhythm.  But the
aged chorus must know all the three, that they may choose the best, and
that which is nearest to the best; for otherwise they will never be able to
charm the souls of young men in the way of virtue.  And now the original
design of the argument which was intended to bring eloquent aid to the
Chorus of Dionysus, has been accomplished to the best of our ability, and
let us see whether we were right:--I should imagine that a drinking
assembly is likely to become more and more tumultuous as the drinking goes
on:  this, as we were saying at first, will certainly be the case.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Every man has a more than natural elevation; his heart is glad
within him, and he will say anything and will be restrained by nobody at
such a time; he fancies that he is able to rule over himself and all
mankind.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Were we not saying that on such occasions the souls of the
drinkers become like iron heated in the fire, and grow softer and younger,
and are easily moulded by him who knows how to educate and fashion them,
just as when they were young, and that this fashioner of them is the same
who prescribed for them in the days of their youth, viz., the good
legislator; and that he ought to enact laws of the banquet, which, when a
man is confident, bold, and impudent, and unwilling to wait his turn and
have his share of silence and speech, and drinking and music, will change
his character into the opposite--such laws as will infuse into him a just
and noble fear, which will take up arms at the approach of insolence, being
that divine fear which we have called reverence and shame?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And the guardians of these laws and fellow-workers with them are
the calm and sober generals of the drinkers; and without their help there
is greater difficulty in fighting against drink than in fighting against
enemies when the commander of an army is not himself calm; and he who is
unwilling to obey them and the commanders of Dionysiac feasts who are more
than sixty years of age, shall suffer a disgrace as great as he who
disobeys military leaders, or even greater.

CLEINIAS:  Right.

ATHENIAN:  If, then, drinking and amusement were regulated in this way,
would not the companions of our revels be improved? they would part better
friends than they were, and not, as now, enemies.  Their whole intercourse
would be regulated by law and observant of it, and the sober would be the
leaders of the drunken.

CLEINIAS:  I think so too, if drinking were regulated as you propose.

ATHENIAN:  Let us not then simply censure the gift of Dionysus as bad and
unfit to be received into the State.  For wine has many excellences, and
one pre-eminent one, about which there is a difficulty in speaking to the
many, from a fear of their misconceiving and misunderstanding what is said.

CLEINIAS:  To what do you refer?

ATHENIAN:  There is a tradition or story, which has somehow crept about the
world, that Dionysus was robbed of his wits by his stepmother Here, and
that out of revenge he inspires Bacchic furies and dancing madnesses in
others; for which reason he gave men wine.  Such traditions concerning the
Gods I leave to those who think that they may be safely uttered (compare
Euthyph.; Republic); I only know that no animal at birth is mature or
perfect in intelligence; and in the intermediate period, in which he has
not yet acquired his own proper sense, he rages and roars without rhyme or
reason; and when he has once got on his legs he jumps about without rhyme
or reason; and this, as you will remember, has been already said by us to
be the origin of music and gymnastic.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure, I remember.

ATHENIAN:  And did we not say that the sense of harmony and rhythm sprang
from this beginning among men, and that Apollo and the Muses and Dionysus
were the Gods whom we had to thank for them?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  The other story implied that wine was given man out of revenge,
and in order to make him mad; but our present doctrine, on the contrary,
is, that wine was given him as a balm, and in order to implant modesty in
the soul, and health and strength in the body.

CLEINIAS:  That, Stranger, is precisely what was said.

ATHENIAN:  Then half the subject may now be considered to have been
discussed; shall we proceed to the consideration of the other half?

CLEINIAS:  What is the other half, and how do you divide the subject?

ATHENIAN:  The whole choral art is also in our view the whole of education;
and of this art, rhythms and harmonies form the part which has to do with
the voice.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  The movement of the body has rhythm in common with the movement
of the voice, but gesture is peculiar to it, whereas song is simply the
movement of the voice.

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  And the sound of the voice which reaches and educates the soul,
we have ventured to term music.

CLEINIAS:  We were right.

ATHENIAN:  And the movement of the body, when regarded as an amusement, we
termed dancing; but when extended and pursued with a view to the excellence
of the body, this scientific training may be called gymnastic.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  Music, which was one half of the choral art, may be said to have
been completely discussed.  Shall we proceed to the other half or not? 
What would you like?

CLEINIAS:  My good friend, when you are talking with a Cretan and
Lacedaemonian, and we have discussed music and not gymnastic, what answer
are either of us likely to make to such an enquiry?

ATHENIAN:  An answer is contained in your question; and I understand and
accept what you say not only as an answer, but also as a command to proceed
with gymnastic.

CLEINIAS:  You quite understand me; do as you say.

ATHENIAN:  I will; and there will not be any difficulty in speaking
intelligibly to you about a subject with which both of you are far more
familiar than with music.

CLEINIAS:  There will not.

ATHENIAN:  Is not the origin of gymnastics, too, to be sought in the
tendency to rapid motion which exists in all animals; man, as we were
saying, having attained the sense of rhythm, created and invented dancing;
and melody arousing and awakening rhythm, both united formed the choral
art?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And one part of this subject has been already discussed by us,
and there still remains another to be discussed?

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  I have first a final word to add to my discourse about drink, if
you will allow me to do so.

CLEINIAS:  What more have you to say?

ATHENIAN:  I should say that if a city seriously means to adopt the
practice of drinking under due regulation and with a view to the
enforcement of temperance, and in like manner, and on the same principle,
will allow of other pleasures, designing to gain the victory over them--in
this way all of them may be used.  But if the State makes drinking an
amusement only, and whoever likes may drink whenever he likes, and with
whom he likes, and add to this any other indulgences, I shall never agree
or allow that this city or this man should practise drinking.  I would go
further than the Cretans and Lacedaemonians, and am disposed rather to the
law of the Carthaginians, that no one while he is on a campaign should be
allowed to taste wine at all, but that he should drink water during all
that time, and that in the city no slave, male or female, should ever drink
wine; and that no magistrates should drink during their year of office, nor
should pilots of vessels or judges while on duty taste wine at all, nor any
one who is going to hold a consultation about any matter of importance; nor
in the day-time at all, unless in consequence of exercise or as medicine;
nor again at night, when any one, either man or woman, is minded to get
children.  There are numberless other cases also in which those who have
good sense and good laws ought not to drink wine, so that if what I say is
true, no city will need many vineyards.  Their husbandry and their way of
life in general will follow an appointed order, and their cultivation of
the vine will be the most limited and the least common of their
employments.  And this, Stranger, shall be the crown of my discourse about
wine, if you agree.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent:  we agree.


BOOK III.

ATHENIAN:  Enough of this.  And what, then, is to be regarded as the origin
of government?  Will not a man be able to judge of it best from a point of
view in which he may behold the progress of states and their transitions to
good or evil?

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that he might watch them from the point of view of time,
and observe the changes which take place in them during infinite ages.

CLEINIAS:  How so?

ATHENIAN:  Why, do you think that you can reckon the time which has elapsed
since cities first existed and men were citizens of them?

CLEINIAS:  Hardly.

ATHENIAN:  But are sure that it must be vast and incalculable?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And have not thousands and thousands of cities come into being
during this period and as many perished?  And has not each of them had
every form of government many times over, now growing larger, now smaller,
and again improving or declining?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  Let us endeavour to ascertain the cause of these changes; for
that will probably explain the first origin and development of forms of
government.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.  You shall endeavour to impart your thoughts to us,
and we will make an effort to understand you.

ATHENIAN:  Do you believe that there is any truth in ancient traditions?

CLEINIAS:  What traditions?

ATHENIAN:  The traditions about the many destructions of mankind which have
been occasioned by deluges and pestilences, and in many other ways, and of
the survival of a remnant?

CLEINIAS:  Every one is disposed to believe them.

ATHENIAN:  Let us consider one of them, that which was caused by the famous
deluge.

CLEINIAS:  What are we to observe about it?

ATHENIAN:  I mean to say that those who then escaped would only be hill
shepherds,--small sparks of the human race preserved on the tops of
mountains.

CLEINIAS:  Clearly.

ATHENIAN:  Such survivors would necessarily be unacquainted with the arts
and the various devices which are suggested to the dwellers in cities by
interest or ambition, and with all the wrongs which they contrive against
one another.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Let us suppose, then, that the cities in the plain and on the
sea-coast were utterly destroyed at that time.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Would not all implements have then perished and every other
excellent invention of political or any other sort of wisdom have utterly
disappeared?

CLEINIAS:  Why, yes, my friend; and if things had always continued as they
are at present ordered, how could any discovery have ever been made even in
the least particular?  For it is evident that the arts were unknown during
ten thousand times ten thousand years.  And no more than a thousand or two
thousand years have elapsed since the discoveries of Daedalus, Orpheus and
Palamedes,--since Marsyas and Olympus invented music, and Amphion the lyre
--not to speak of numberless other inventions which are but of yesterday.

ATHENIAN:  Have you forgotten, Cleinias, the name of a friend who is really
of yesterday?

CLEINIAS:  I suppose that you mean Epimenides.

ATHENIAN:  The same, my friend; he does indeed far overleap the heads of
all mankind by his invention; for he carried out in practice, as you
declare, what of old Hesiod (Works and Days) only preached.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, according to our tradition.

ATHENIAN:  After the great destruction, may we not suppose that the state
of man was something of this sort:--In the beginning of things there was a
fearful illimitable desert and a vast expanse of land; a herd or two of
oxen would be the only survivors of the animal world; and there might be a
few goats, these too hardly enough to maintain the shepherds who tended
them?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And of cities or governments or legislation, about which we are
now talking, do you suppose that they could have any recollection at all?

CLEINIAS:  None whatever.

ATHENIAN:  And out of this state of things has there not sprung all that we
now are and have:  cities and governments, and arts and laws, and a great
deal of vice and a great deal of virtue?

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Why, my good friend, how can we possibly suppose that those who
knew nothing of all the good and evil of cities could have attained their
full development, whether of virtue or of vice?

CLEINIAS:  I understand your meaning, and you are quite right.

ATHENIAN:  But, as time advanced and the race multiplied, the world came to
be what the world is.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Doubtless the change was not made all in a moment, but little by
little, during a very long period of time.

CLEINIAS:  A highly probable supposition.

ATHENIAN:  At first, they would have a natural fear ringing in their ears
which would prevent their descending from the heights into the plain.

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  The fewness of the survivors at that time would have made them
all the more desirous of seeing one another; but then the means of
travelling either by land or sea had been almost entirely lost, as I may
say, with the loss of the arts, and there was great difficulty in getting
at one another; for iron and brass and all metals were jumbled together and
had disappeared in the chaos; nor was there any possibility of extracting
ore from them; and they had scarcely any means of felling timber.  Even if
you suppose that some implements might have been preserved in the
mountains, they must quickly have worn out and vanished, and there would be
no more of them until the art of metallurgy had again revived.

CLEINIAS:  There could not have been.

ATHENIAN:  In how many generations would this be attained?

CLEINIAS:  Clearly, not for many generations.

ATHENIAN:  During this period, and for some time afterwards, all the arts
which require iron and brass and the like would disappear.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Faction and war would also have died out in those days, and for
many reasons.

CLEINIAS:  How would that be?

ATHENIAN:  In the first place, the desolation of these primitive men would
create in them a feeling of affection and goodwill towards one another;
and, secondly, they would have no occasion to quarrel about their
subsistence, for they would have pasture in abundance, except just at
first, and in some particular cases; and from their pasture-land they would
obtain the greater part of their food in a primitive age, having plenty of
milk and flesh; moreover they would procure other food by the chase, not to
be despised either in quantity or quality.  They would also have abundance
of clothing, and bedding, and dwellings, and utensils either capable of
standing on the fire or not; for the plastic and weaving arts do not
require any use of iron:  and God has given these two arts to man in order
to provide him with all such things, that, when reduced to the last
extremity, the human race may still grow and increase.  Hence in those days
mankind were not very poor; nor was poverty a cause of difference among
them; and rich they could not have been, having neither gold nor silver:--
such at that time was their condition.  And the community which has neither
poverty nor riches will always have the noblest principles; in it there is
no insolence or injustice, nor, again, are there any contentions or
envyings.  And therefore they were good, and also because they were what is
called simple-minded; and when they were told about good and evil, they in
their simplicity believed what they heard to be very truth and practised
it.  No one had the wit to suspect another of a falsehood, as men do now;
but what they heard about Gods and men they believed to be true, and lived
accordingly; and therefore they were in all respects such as we have
described them.

CLEINIAS:  That quite accords with my views, and with those of my friend
here.

ATHENIAN:  Would not many generations living on in a simple manner,
although ruder, perhaps, and more ignorant of the arts generally, and in
particular of those of land or naval warfare, and likewise of other arts,
termed in cities legal practices and party conflicts, and including all
conceivable ways of hurting one another in word and deed;--although
inferior to those who lived before the deluge, or to the men of our day in
these respects, would they not, I say, be simpler and more manly, and also
more temperate and altogether more just?  The reason has been already
explained.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  I should wish you to understand that what has preceded and what
is about to follow, has been, and will be said, with the intention of
explaining what need the men of that time had of laws, and who was their
lawgiver.

CLEINIAS:  And thus far what you have said has been very well said.

ATHENIAN:  They could hardly have wanted lawgivers as yet; nothing of that
sort was likely to have existed in their days, for they had no letters at
this early period; they lived by habit and the customs of their ancestors,
as they are called.

CLEINIAS:  Probably.

ATHENIAN:  But there was already existing a form of government which, if I
am not mistaken, is generally termed a lordship, and this still remains in
many places, both among Hellenes and barbarians (compare Arist. Pol.), and
is the government which is declared by Homer to have prevailed among the
Cyclopes:--

'They have neither councils nor judgments, but they dwell in hollow caves
on the tops of high mountains, and every one gives law to his wife and
children, and they do not busy themselves about one another.'  (Odyss.)

CLEINIAS:  That seems to be a charming poet of yours; I have read some
other verses of his, which are very clever; but I do not know much of him,
for foreign poets are very little read among the Cretans.

MEGILLUS:  But they are in Lacedaemon, and he appears to be the prince of
them all; the manner of life, however, which he describes is not Spartan,
but rather Ionian, and he seems quite to confirm what you are saying, when
he traces up the ancient state of mankind by the help of tradition to
barbarism.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, he does confirm it; and we may accept his witness to the
fact that such forms of government sometimes arise.

CLEINIAS:  We may.

ATHENIAN:  And were not such states composed of men who had been dispersed 
in single habitations and families by the poverty which attended the
devastations; and did not the eldest then rule among them, because with
them government originated in the authority of a father and a mother, whom,
like a flock of birds, they followed, forming one troop under the
patriarchal rule and sovereignty of their parents, which of all
sovereignties is the most just?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  After this they came together in greater numbers, and increased
the size of their cities, and betook themselves to husbandry, first of all
at the foot of the mountains, and made enclosures of loose walls and works
of defence, in order to keep off wild beasts; thus creating a single large
and common habitation.

CLEINIAS:  Yes; at least we may suppose so.

ATHENIAN:  There is another thing which would probably happen.

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  When these larger habitations grew up out of the lesser original
ones, each of the lesser ones would survive in the larger; every family
would be under the rule of the eldest, and, owing to their separation from
one another, would have peculiar customs in things divine and human, which
they would have received from their several parents who had educated them;
and these customs would incline them to order, when the parents had the
element of order in their nature, and to courage, when they had the element
of courage.  And they would naturally stamp upon their children, and upon
their children's children, their own likings; and, as we are saying, they
would find their way into the larger society, having already their own
peculiar laws.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And every man surely likes his own laws best, and the laws of
others not so well.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Then now we seem to have stumbled upon the beginnings of
legislation.

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  The next step will be that these persons who have met together,
will select some arbiters, who will review the laws of all of them, and
will publicly present such as they approve to the chiefs who lead the
tribes, and who are in a manner their kings, allowing them to choose those
which they think best.  These persons will themselves be called
legislators, and will appoint the magistrates, framing some sort of
aristocracy, or perhaps monarchy, out of the dynasties or lordships, and in
this altered state of the government they will live.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, that would be the natural order of things.

ATHENIAN:  Then, now let us speak of a third form of government, in which
all other forms and conditions of polities and cities concur.

CLEINIAS:  What is that?

ATHENIAN:  The form which in fact Homer indicates as following the second. 
This third form arose when, as he says, Dardanus founded Dardania:--

'For not as yet had the holy Ilium been built on the plain to be a city of
speaking men; but they were still dwelling at the foot of many-fountained
Ida.'

For indeed, in these verses, and in what he said of the Cyclopes, he speaks
the words of God and nature; for poets are a divine race, and often in
their strains, by the aid of the Muses and the Graces, they attain truth.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Then now let us proceed with the rest of our tale, which will
probably be found to illustrate in some degree our proposed design:--Shall
we do so?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Ilium was built, when they descended from the mountain, in a
large and fair plain, on a sort of low hill, watered by many rivers
descending from Ida.

CLEINIAS:  Such is the tradition.

ATHENIAN:  And we must suppose this event to have taken place many ages
after the deluge?

ATHENIAN:  A marvellous forgetfulness of the former destruction would
appear to have come over them, when they placed their town right under
numerous streams flowing from the heights, trusting for their security to
not very high hills, either.

CLEINIAS:  There must have been a long interval, clearly.

ATHENIAN:  And, as population increased, many other cities would begin to
be inhabited.

CLEINIAS:  Doubtless.

ATHENIAN:  Those cities made war against Troy--by sea as well as land--for
at that time men were ceasing to be afraid of the sea.

CLEINIAS:  Clearly.

ATHENIAN:  The Achaeans remained ten years, and overthrew Troy.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And during the ten years in which the Achaeans were besieging
Ilium, the homes of the besiegers were falling into an evil plight.  Their
youth revolted; and when the soldiers returned to their own cities and
families, they did not receive them properly, and as they ought to have
done, and numerous deaths, murders, exiles, were the consequence.  The
exiles came again, under a new name, no longer Achaeans, but Dorians,--a
name which they derived from Dorieus; for it was he who gathered them
together.  The rest of the story is told by you Lacedaemonians as part of
the history of Sparta.

MEGILLUS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  Thus, after digressing from the original subject of laws into
music and drinking-bouts, the argument has, providentially, come back to
the same point, and presents to us another handle.  For we have reached the
settlement of Lacedaemon; which, as you truly say, is in laws and in
institutions the sister of Crete.  And we are all the better for the
digression, because we have gone through various governments and
settlements, and have been present at the foundation of a first, second,
and third state, succeeding one another in infinite time.  And now there
appears on the horizon a fourth state or nation which was once in process
of settlement and has continued settled to this day.  If, out of all this,
we are able to discern what is well or ill settled, and what laws are the
salvation and what are the destruction of cities, and what changes would
make a state happy, O Megillus and Cleinias, we may now begin again, unless
we have some fault to find with the previous discussion.

MEGILLUS:  If some God, Stranger, would promise us that our new enquiry
about legislation would be as good and full as the present, I would go a
great way to hear such another, and would think that a day as long as this
--and we are now approaching the longest day of the year--was too short for
the discussion.

ATHENIAN:  Then I suppose that we must consider this subject?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Let us place ourselves in thought at the moment when Lacedaemon
and Argos and Messene and the rest of the Peloponnesus were all in complete
subjection, Megillus, to your ancestors; for afterwards, as the legend
informs us, they divided their army into three portions, and settled three
cities, Argos, Messene, Lacedaemon.

MEGILLUS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Temenus was the king of Argos, Cresphontes of Messene, Procles
and Eurysthenes of Lacedaemon.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  To these kings all the men of that day made oath that they would
assist them, if any one subverted their kingdom.

MEGILLUS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  But can a kingship be destroyed, or was any other form of
government ever destroyed, by any but the rulers themselves?  No indeed, by
Zeus.  Have we already forgotten what was said a little while ago?

MEGILLUS:  No.

ATHENIAN:  And may we not now further confirm what was then mentioned?  For
we have come upon facts which have brought us back again to the same
principle; so that, in resuming the discussion, we shall not be enquiring
about an empty theory, but about events which actually happened.  The case
was as follows:--Three royal heroes made oath to three cities which were
under a kingly government, and the cities to the kings, that both rulers
and subjects should govern and be governed according to the laws which were
common to all of them:  the rulers promised that as time and the race went
forward they would not make their rule more arbitrary; and the subjects
said that, if the rulers observed these conditions, they would never
subvert or permit others to subvert those kingdoms; the kings were to
assist kings and peoples when injured, and the peoples were to assist
peoples and kings in like manner.  Is not this the fact?

MEGILLUS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And the three states to whom these laws were given, whether
their kings or any others were the authors of them, had therefore the
greatest security for the maintenance of their constitutions?

MEGILLUS:  What security?

ATHENIAN:  That the other two states were always to come to the rescue
against a rebellious third.

MEGILLUS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Many persons say that legislators ought to impose such laws as
the mass of the people will be ready to receive; but this is just as if one
were to command gymnastic masters or physicians to treat or cure their
pupils or patients in an agreeable manner.

MEGILLUS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  Whereas the physician may often be too happy if he can restore
health, and make the body whole, without any very great infliction of pain.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  There was also another advantage possessed by the men of that
day, which greatly lightened the task of passing laws.

MEGILLUS:  What advantage?

ATHENIAN:  The legislators of that day, when they equalized property,
escaped the great accusation which generally arises in legislation, if a
person attempts to disturb the possession of land, or to abolish debts,
because he sees that without this reform there can never be any real
equality.  Now, in general, when the legislator attempts to make a new
settlement of such matters, every one meets him with the cry, that 'he is
not to disturb vested interests,'--declaring with imprecations that he is
introducing agrarian laws and cancelling of debts, until a man is at his
wits' end; whereas no one could quarrel with the Dorians for distributing
the land,--there was nothing to hinder them; and as for debts, they had
none which were considerable or of old standing.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  But then, my good friends, why did the settlement and
legislation of their country turn out so badly?

MEGILLUS:  How do you mean; and why do you blame them?

ATHENIAN:  There were three kingdoms, and of these, two quickly corrupted
their original constitution and laws, and the only one which remained was
the Spartan.

MEGILLUS:  The question which you ask is not easily answered.

ATHENIAN:  And yet must be answered when we are enquiring about laws, this
being our old man's sober game of play, whereby we beguile the way, as I
was saying when we first set out on our journey.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly; and we must find out why this was.

ATHENIAN:  What laws are more worthy of our attention than those which have
regulated such cities? or what settlements of states are greater or more
famous?

MEGILLUS:  I know of none.

ATHENIAN:  Can we doubt that your ancestors intended these institutions not
only for the protection of Peloponnesus, but of all the Hellenes, in case
they were attacked by the barbarian?  For the inhabitants of the region
about Ilium, when they provoked by their insolence the Trojan war, relied
upon the power of the Assyrians and the Empire of Ninus, which still
existed and had a great prestige; the people of those days fearing the
united Assyrian Empire just as we now fear the Great King.  And the second
capture of Troy was a serious offence against them, because Troy was a
portion of the Assyrian Empire.  To meet the danger the single army was
distributed between three cities by the royal brothers, sons of Heracles,--
a fair device, as it seemed, and a far better arrangement than the
expedition against Troy.  For, firstly, the people of that day had, as they
thought, in the Heraclidae better leaders than the Pelopidae; in the next
place, they considered that their army was superior in valour to that which
went against Troy; for, although the latter conquered the Trojans, they
were themselves conquered by the Heraclidae--Achaeans by Dorians.  May we
not suppose that this was the intention with which the men of those days
framed the constitutions of their states?

MEGILLUS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  And would not men who had shared with one another many dangers,
and were governed by a single race of royal brothers, and had taken the
advice of oracles, and in particular of the Delphian Apollo, be likely to
think that such states would be firmly and lastingly established?

MEGILLUS:  Of course they would.

ATHENIAN:  Yet these institutions, of which such great expectations were
entertained, seem to have all rapidly vanished away; with the exception, as
I was saying, of that small part of them which existed in your land.  And
this third part has never to this day ceased warring against the two
others; whereas, if the original idea had been carried out, and they had
agreed to be one, their power would have been invincible in war.

MEGILLUS:  No doubt.

ATHENIAN:  But what was the ruin of this glorious confederacy?  Here is a
subject well worthy of consideration.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly, no one will ever find more striking instances of laws
or governments being the salvation or destruction of great and noble
interests, than are here presented to his view.

ATHENIAN:  Then now we seem to have happily arrived at a real and important
question.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Did you never remark, sage friend, that all men, and we
ourselves at this moment, often fancy that they see some beautiful thing
which might have effected wonders if any one had only known how to make a
right use of it in some way; and yet this mode of looking at things may
turn out after all to be a mistake, and not according to nature, either in
our own case or in any other?

MEGILLUS:  To what are you referring, and what do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I was thinking of my own admiration of the aforesaid Heracleid
expedition, which was so noble, and might have had such wonderful results
for the Hellenes, if only rightly used; and I was just laughing at myself.

MEGILLUS:  But were you not right and wise in speaking as you did, and we
in assenting to you?

ATHENIAN:  Perhaps; and yet I cannot help observing that any one who sees
anything great or powerful, immediately has the feeling that--'If the owner
only knew how to use his great and noble possession, how happy would he be,
and what great results would he achieve!'

MEGILLUS:  And would he not be justified?

ATHENIAN:  Reflect; in what point of view does this sort of praise appear
just:  First, in reference to the question in hand:--If the then commanders
had known how to arrange their army properly, how would they have attained
success?  Would not this have been the way?  They would have bound them all
firmly together and preserved them for ever, giving them freedom and
dominion at pleasure, combined with the power of doing in the whole world,
Hellenic and barbarian, whatever they and their descendants desired.  What
other aim would they have had?

MEGILLUS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose any one were in the same way to express his admiration
at the sight of great wealth or family honour, or the like, he would praise
them under the idea that through them he would attain either all or the
greater and chief part of what he desires.

MEGILLUS:  He would.

ATHENIAN:  Well, now, and does not the argument show that there is one
common desire of all mankind?

MEGILLUS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  The desire which a man has, that all things, if possible,--at
any rate, things human,--may come to pass in accordance with his soul's
desire.

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And having this desire always, and at every time of life, in
youth, in manhood, in age, he cannot help always praying for the fulfilment
of it.

MEGILLUS:  No doubt.

ATHENIAN:  And we join in the prayers of our friends, and ask for them what
they ask for themselves.

MEGILLUS:  We do.

ATHENIAN:  Dear is the son to the father--the younger to the elder.

MEGILLUS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And yet the son often prays to obtain things which the father
prays that he may not obtain.

MEGILLUS:  When the son is young and foolish, you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Yes; or when the father, in the dotage of age or the heat of
youth, having no sense of right and justice, prays with fervour, under the
influence of feelings akin to those of Theseus when he cursed the
unfortunate Hippolytus, do you imagine that the son, having a sense of
right and justice, will join in his father's prayers?

MEGILLUS:  I understand you to mean that a man should not desire or be in a
hurry to have all things according to his wish, for his wish may be at
variance with his reason.  But every state and every individual ought to
pray and strive for wisdom.

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and I remember, and you will remember, what I said at
first, that a statesman and legislator ought to ordain laws with a view to
wisdom; while you were arguing that the good lawgiver ought to order all
with a view to war.  And to this I replied that there were four virtues,
but that upon your view one of them only was the aim of legislation;
whereas you ought to regard all virtue, and especially that which comes
first, and is the leader of all the rest--I mean wisdom and mind and
opinion, having affection and desire in their train.  And now the argument
returns to the same point, and I say once more, in jest if you like, or in
earnest if you like, that the prayer of a fool is full of danger, being
likely to end in the opposite of what he desires.  And if you would rather
receive my words in earnest, I am willing that you should; and you will
find, I suspect, as I have said already, that not cowardice was the cause
of the ruin of the Dorian kings and of their whole design, nor ignorance of
military matters, either on the part of the rulers or of their subjects;
but their misfortunes were due to their general degeneracy, and especially
to their ignorance of the most important human affairs.  That was then, and
is still, and always will be the case, as I will endeavour, if you will
allow me, to make out and demonstrate as well as I am able to you who are
my friends, in the course of the argument.

CLEINIAS:  Pray go on, Stranger;--compliments are troublesome, but we will
show, not in word but in deed, how greatly we prize your words, for we will
give them our best attention; and that is the way in which a freeman best
shows his approval or disapproval.

MEGILLUS:  Excellent, Cleinias; let us do as you say.

CLEINIAS:  By all means, if Heaven wills.  Go on.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, proceeding in the same train of thought, I say that
the greatest ignorance was the ruin of the Dorian power, and that now, as
then, ignorance is ruin.  And if this be true, the legislator must
endeavour to implant wisdom in states, and banish ignorance to the utmost
of his power.

CLEINIAS:  That is evident.

ATHENIAN:  Then now consider what is really the greatest ignorance.  I
should like to know whether you and Megillus would agree with me in what I
am about to say; for my opinion is--

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  That the greatest ignorance is when a man hates that which he
nevertheless thinks to be good and noble, and loves and embraces that which
he knows to be unrighteous and evil.  This disagreement between the sense
of pleasure and the judgment of reason in the soul is, in my opinion, the
worst ignorance; and also the greatest, because affecting the great mass of
the human soul; for the principle which feels pleasure and pain in the
individual is like the mass or populace in a state.  And when the soul is
opposed to knowledge, or opinion, or reason, which are her natural lords,
that I call folly, just as in the state, when the multitude refuses to obey
their rulers and the laws; or, again, in the individual, when fair
reasonings have their habitation in the soul and yet do no good, but rather
the reverse of good.  All these cases I term the worst ignorance, whether
in individuals or in states.  You will understand, Stranger, that I am
speaking of something which is very different from the ignorance of
handicraftsmen.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, my friend, we understand and agree.

ATHENIAN:  Let us, then, in the first place declare and affirm that the
citizen who does not know these things ought never to have any kind of
authority entrusted to him:  he must be stigmatized as ignorant, even
though he be versed in calculation and skilled in all sorts of
accomplishments, and feats of mental dexterity; and the opposite are to be
called wise, even although, in the words of the proverb, they know neither
how to read nor how to swim; and to them, as to men of sense, authority is
to be committed.  For, O my friends, how can there be the least shadow of
wisdom when there is no harmony?  There is none; but the noblest and
greatest of harmonies may be truly said to be the greatest wisdom; and of
this he is a partaker who lives according to reason; whereas he who is
devoid of reason is the destroyer of his house and the very opposite of a
saviour of the state:  he is utterly ignorant of political wisdom.  Let
this, then, as I was saying, be laid down by us.

CLEINIAS:  Let it be so laid down.

ATHENIAN:  I suppose that there must be rulers and subjects in states?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And what are the principles on which men rule and obey in
cities, whether great or small; and similarly in families?  What are they,
and how many in number?  Is there not one claim of authority which is
always just,--that of fathers and mothers and in general of progenitors to
rule over their offspring?

CLEINIAS:  There is.

ATHENIAN:  Next follows the principle that the noble should rule over the
ignoble; and, thirdly, that the elder should rule and the younger obey?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And, fourthly, that slaves should be ruled, and their masters
rule?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  Fifthly, if I am not mistaken, comes the principle that the
stronger shall rule, and the weaker be ruled?

CLEINIAS:  That is a rule not to be disobeyed.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, and a rule which prevails very widely among all creatures,
and is according to nature, as the Theban poet Pindar once said; and the
sixth principle, and the greatest of all, is, that the wise should lead and
command, and the ignorant follow and obey; and yet, O thou most wise
Pindar, as I should reply him, this surely is not contrary to nature, but
according to nature, being the rule of law over willing subjects, and not a
rule of compulsion.

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  There is a seventh kind of rule which is awarded by lot, and is
dear to the Gods and a token of good fortune:  he on whom the lot falls is
a ruler, and he who fails in obtaining the lot goes away and is the
subject; and this we affirm to be quite just.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  'Then now,' as we say playfully to any of those who lightly
undertake the making of laws, 'you see, legislator, the principles of
government, how many they are, and that they are naturally opposed to each
other.  There we have discovered a fountain-head of seditions, to which you
must attend.  And, first, we will ask you to consider with us, how and in
what respect the kings of Argos and Messene violated these our maxims, and
ruined themselves and the great and famous Hellenic power of the olden
time.  Was it because they did not know how wisely Hesiod spoke when he
said that the half is often more than the whole?  His meaning was, that
when to take the whole would be dangerous, and to take the half would be
the safe and moderate course, then the moderate or better was more than the
immoderate or worse.'

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And may we suppose this immoderate spirit to be more fatal when
found among kings than when among peoples?

CLEINIAS:  The probability is that ignorance will be a disorder especially
prevalent among kings, because they lead a proud and luxurious life.

ATHENIAN:  Is it not palpable that the chief aim of the kings of that time
was to get the better of the established laws, and that they were not in
harmony with the principles which they had agreed to observe by word and
oath?  This want of harmony may have had the appearance of wisdom, but was
really, as we assert, the greatest ignorance, and utterly overthrew the
whole empire by dissonance and harsh discord.

CLEINIAS:  Very likely.

ATHENIAN:  Good; and what measures ought the legislator to have then taken
in order to avert this calamity?  Truly there is no great wisdom in
knowing, and no great difficulty in telling, after the evil has happened;
but to have foreseen the remedy at the time would have taken a much wiser
head than ours.

MEGILLUS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Any one who looks at what has occurred with you Lacedaemonians,
Megillus, may easily know and may easily say what ought to have been done
at that time.

MEGILLUS:  Speak a little more clearly.

ATHENIAN:  Nothing can be clearer than the observation which I am about to
make.

MEGILLUS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  That if any one gives too great a power to anything, too large a
sail to a vessel, too much food to the body, too much authority to the
mind, and does not observe the mean, everything is overthrown, and, in the
wantonness of excess, runs in the one case to disorders, and in the other
to injustice, which is the child of excess.  I mean to say, my dear
friends, that there is no soul of man, young and irresponsible, who will be
able to sustain the temptation of arbitrary power--no one who will not,
under such circumstances, become filled with folly, that worst of diseases,
and be hated by his nearest and dearest friends:  when this happens his
kingdom is undermined, and all his power vanishes from him.  And great
legislators who know the mean should take heed of the danger.  As far as we
can guess at this distance of time, what happened was as follows:--

MEGILLUS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  A God, who watched over Sparta, seeing into the future, gave you
two families of kings instead of one; and thus brought you more within the
limits of moderation.  In the next place, some human wisdom mingled with
divine power, observing that the constitution of your government was still
feverish and excited, tempered your inborn strength and pride of birth with
the moderation which comes of age, making the power of your twenty-eight
elders equal with that of the kings in the most important matters.  But
your third saviour, perceiving that your government was still swelling and
foaming, and desirous to impose a curb upon it, instituted the Ephors,
whose power he made to resemble that of magistrates elected by lot; and by
this arrangement the kingly office, being compounded of the right elements
and duly moderated, was preserved, and was the means of preserving all the
rest.  Since, if there had been only the original legislators, Temenus,
Cresphontes, and their contemporaries, as far as they were concerned not
even the portion of Aristodemus would have been preserved; for they had no
proper experience in legislation, or they would surely not have imagined
that oaths would moderate a youthful spirit invested with a power which
might be converted into a tyranny.  Now that God has instructed us what
sort of government would have been or will be lasting, there is no wisdom,
as I have already said, in judging after the event; there is no difficulty
in learning from an example which has already occurred.  But if any one
could have foreseen all this at the time, and had been able to moderate the
government of the three kingdoms and unite them into one, he might have
saved all the excellent institutions which were then conceived; and no
Persian or any other armament would have dared to attack us, or would have
regarded Hellas as a power to be despised.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  There was small credit to us, Cleinias, in defeating them; and
the discredit was, not that the conquerors did not win glorious victories
both by land and sea, but what, in my opinion, brought discredit was, first
of all, the circumstance that of the three cities one only fought on behalf
of Hellas, and the two others were so utterly good for nothing that the one
was waging a mighty war against Lacedaemon, and was thus preventing her
from rendering assistance, while the city of Argos, which had the
precedence at the time of the distribution, when asked to aid in repelling
the barbarian, would not answer to the call, or give aid.  Many things
might be told about Hellas in connexion with that war which are far from
honourable; nor, indeed, can we rightly say that Hellas repelled the
invader; for the truth is, that unless the Athenians and Lacedaemonians,
acting in concert, had warded off the impending yoke, all the tribes of
Hellas would have been fused in a chaos of Hellenes mingling with one
another, of barbarians mingling with Hellenes, and Hellenes with
barbarians; just as nations who are now subject to the Persian power, owing
to unnatural separations and combinations of them, are dispersed and
scattered, and live miserably.  These, Cleinias and Megillus, are the
reproaches which we have to make against statesmen and legislators, as they
are called, past and present, if we would analyse the causes of their
failure, and find out what else might have been done.  We said, for
instance, just now, that there ought to be no great and unmixed powers; and
this was under the idea that a state ought to be free and wise and
harmonious, and that a legislator ought to legislate with a view to this
end.  Nor is there any reason to be surprised at our continually proposing
aims for the legislator which appear not to be always the same; but we
should consider when we say that temperance is to be the aim, or wisdom is
to be the aim, or friendship is to be the aim, that all these aims are
really the same; and if so, a variety in the modes of expression ought not
to disturb us.

CLEINIAS:  Let us resume the argument in that spirit.  And now, speaking of
friendship and wisdom and freedom, I wish that you would tell me at what,
in your opinion, the legislator should aim.

ATHENIAN:  Hear me, then:  there are two mother forms of states from which
the rest may be truly said to be derived; and one of them may be called
monarchy and the other democracy:  the Persians have the highest form of
the one, and we of the other; almost all the rest, as I was saying, are
variations of these.  Now, if you are to have liberty and the combination
of friendship with wisdom, you must have both these forms of government in
a measure; the argument emphatically declares that no city can be well
governed which is not made up of both.

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  Neither the one, if it be exclusively and excessively attached
to monarchy, nor the other, if it be similarly attached to freedom,
observes moderation; but your states, the Laconian and Cretan, have more of
it; and the same was the case with the Athenians and Persians of old time,
but now they have less.  Shall I tell you why?

CLEINIAS:  By all means, if it will tend to elucidate our subject.

ATHENIAN:  Hear, then:--There was a time when the Persians had more of the
state which is a mean between slavery and freedom.  In the reign of Cyrus
they were freemen and also lords of many others:  the rulers gave a share
of freedom to the subjects, and being treated as equals, the soldiers were
on better terms with their generals, and showed themselves more ready in
the hour of danger.  And if there was any wise man among them, who was able
to give good counsel, he imparted his wisdom to the public; for the king
was not jealous, but allowed him full liberty of speech, and gave honour to
those who could advise him in any matter.  And the nation waxed in all
respects, because there was freedom and friendship and communion of mind
among them.

CLEINIAS:  That certainly appears to have been the case.

ATHENIAN:  How, then, was this advantage lost under Cambyses, and again
recovered under Darius?  Shall I try to divine?

CLEINIAS:  The enquiry, no doubt, has a bearing upon our subject.

ATHENIAN:  I imagine that Cyrus, though a great and patriotic general, had
never given his mind to education, and never attended to the order of his
household.

CLEINIAS:  What makes you say so?

ATHENIAN:  I think that from his youth upwards he was a soldier, and
entrusted the education of his children to the women; and they brought them
up from their childhood as the favourites of fortune, who were blessed
already, and needed no more blessings.  They thought that they were happy
enough, and that no one should be allowed to oppose them in any way, and
they compelled every one to praise all that they said or did.  This was how
they brought them up.

CLEINIAS:  A splendid education truly!

ATHENIAN:  Such an one as women were likely to give them, and especially
princesses who had recently grown rich, and in the absence of the men, too,
who were occupied in wars and dangers, and had no time to look after them.

CLEINIAS:  What would you expect?

ATHENIAN:  Their father had possessions of cattle and sheep, and many herds
of men and other animals, but he did not consider that those to whom he was
about to make them over were not trained in his own calling, which was
Persian; for the Persians are shepherds--sons of a rugged land, which is a
stern mother, and well fitted to produce a sturdy race able to live in the
open air and go without sleep, and also to fight, if fighting is required
(compare Arist. Pol.).  He did not observe that his sons were trained
differently; through the so-called blessing of being royal they were
educated in the Median fashion by women and eunuchs, which led to their
becoming such as people do become when they are brought up unreproved.  And
so, after the death of Cyrus, his sons, in the fulness of luxury and
licence, took the kingdom, and first one slew the other because he could
not endure a rival; and, afterwards, the slayer himself, mad with wine and
brutality, lost his kingdom through the Medes and the Eunuch, as they
called him, who despised the folly of Cambyses.

CLEINIAS:  So runs the tale, and such probably were the facts.

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and the tradition says, that the empire came back to the
Persians, through Darius and the seven chiefs.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Let us note the rest of the story.  Observe, that Darius was not
the son of a king, and had not received a luxurious education.  When he
came to the throne, being one of the seven, he divided the country into
seven portions, and of this arrangement there are some shadowy traces still
remaining; he made laws upon the principle of introducing universal
equality in the order of the state, and he embodied in his laws the
settlement of the tribute which Cyrus promised,--thus creating a feeling of
friendship and community among all the Persians, and attaching the people
to him with money and gifts.  Hence his armies cheerfully acquired for him
countries as large as those which Cyrus had left behind him.  Darius was
succeeded by his son Xerxes; and he again was brought up in the royal and
luxurious fashion.  Might we not most justly say:  'O Darius, how came you
to bring up Xerxes in the same way in which Cyrus brought up Cambyses, and
not to see his fatal mistake?'  For Xerxes, being the creation of the same
education, met with much the same fortune as Cambyses; and from that time
until now there has never been a really great king among the Persians,
although they are all called Great.  And their degeneracy is not to be
attributed to chance, as I maintain; the reason is rather the evil life
which is generally led by the sons of very rich and royal persons; for
never will boy or man, young or old, excel in virtue, who has been thus
educated.  And this, I say, is what the legislator has to consider, and
what at the present moment has to be considered by us.  Justly may you, O
Lacedaemonians, be praised, in that you do not give special honour or a
special education to wealth rather than to poverty, or to a royal rather
than to a private station, where the divine and inspired lawgiver has not
originally commanded them to be given.  For no man ought to have pre-
eminent honour in a state because he surpasses others in wealth, any more
than because he is swift of foot or fair or strong, unless he have some
virtue in him; nor even if he have virtue, unless he have this particular
virtue of temperance.

MEGILLUS:  What do you mean, Stranger?

ATHENIAN:  I suppose that courage is a part of virtue?

MEGILLUS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  Then, now hear and judge for yourself:--Would you like to have
for a fellow-lodger or neighbour a very courageous man, who had no control
over himself?

MEGILLUS:  Heaven forbid!

ATHENIAN:  Or an artist, who was clever in his profession, but a rogue?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  And surely justice does not grow apart from temperance?

MEGILLUS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  Any more than our pattern wise man, whom we exhibited as having
his pleasures and pains in accordance with and corresponding to true
reason, can be intemperate?

MEGILLUS:  No.

ATHENIAN:  There is a further consideration relating to the due and undue
award of honours in states.

MEGILLUS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  I should like to know whether temperance without the other
virtues, existing alone in the soul of man, is rightly to be praised or
blamed?

MEGILLUS:  I cannot tell.

ATHENIAN:  And that is the best answer; for whichever alternative you had
chosen, I think that you would have gone wrong.

MEGILLUS:  I am fortunate.

ATHENIAN:  Very good; a quality, which is a mere appendage of things which
can be praised or blamed, does not deserve an expression of opinion, but is
best passed over in silence.

MEGILLUS:  You are speaking of temperance?

ATHENIAN:  Yes; but of the other virtues, that which having this appendage
is also most beneficial, will be most deserving of honour, and next that
which is beneficial in the next degree; and so each of them will be rightly
honoured according to a regular order.

MEGILLUS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And ought not the legislator to determine these classes?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly he should.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose that we leave to him the arrangement of details.  But
the general division of laws according to their importance into a first and
second and third class, we who are lovers of law may make ourselves.

MEGILLUS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  We maintain, then, that a State which would be safe and happy,
as far as the nature of man allows, must and ought to distribute honour and
dishonour in the right way.  And the right way is to place the goods of the
soul first and highest in the scale, always assuming temperance to be the
condition of them; and to assign the second place to the goods of the body;
and the third place to money and property.  And if any legislator or state
departs from this rule by giving money the place of honour, or in any way
preferring that which is really last, may we not say, that he or the state
is doing an unholy and unpatriotic thing?

MEGILLUS:  Yes; let that be plainly declared.

ATHENIAN:  The consideration of the Persian governments led us thus far to
enlarge.  We remarked that the Persians grew worse and worse.  And we
affirm the reason of this to have been, that they too much diminished the
freedom of the people, and introduced too much of despotism, and so
destroyed friendship and community of feeling.  And when there is an end of
these, no longer do the governors govern on behalf of their subjects or of
the people, but on behalf of themselves; and if they think that they can
gain ever so small an advantage for themselves, they devastate cities, and
send fire and desolation among friendly races.  And as they hate ruthlessly
and horribly, so are they hated; and when they want the people to fight for
them, they find no community of feeling or willingness to risk their lives
on their behalf; their untold myriads are useless to them on the field of
battle, and they think that their salvation depends on the employment of
mercenaries and strangers whom they hire, as if they were in want of more
men.  And they cannot help being stupid, since they proclaim by their
actions that the ordinary distinctions of right and wrong which are made in
a state are a trifle, when compared with gold and silver.

MEGILLUS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  And now enough of the Persians, and their present mal-
administration of their government, which is owing to the excess of slavery
and despotism among them.

MEGILLUS:  Good.

ATHENIAN:  Next, we must pass in review the government of Attica in like
manner, and from this show that entire freedom and the absence of all
superior authority is not by any means so good as government by others when
properly limited, which was our ancient Athenian constitution at the time
when the Persians made their attack on Hellas, or, speaking more correctly,
on the whole continent of Europe.  There were four classes, arranged
according to a property census, and reverence was our queen and mistress,
and made us willing to live in obedience to the laws which then prevailed. 
Also the vastness of the Persian armament, both by sea and on land, caused
a helpless terror, which made us more and more the servants of our rulers
and of the laws; and for all these reasons an exceeding harmony prevailed
among us.  About ten years before the naval engagement at Salamis, Datis
came, leading a Persian host by command of Darius, which was expressly
directed against the Athenians and Eretrians, having orders to carry them
away captive; and these orders he was to execute under pain of death.  Now
Datis and his myriads soon became complete masters of Eretria, and he sent
a fearful report to Athens that no Eretrian had escaped him; for the
soldiers of Datis had joined hands and netted the whole of Eretria.  And
this report, whether well or ill founded, was terrible to all the Hellenes,
and above all to the Athenians, and they dispatched embassies in all
directions, but no one was willing to come to their relief, with the
exception of the Lacedaemonians; and they, either because they were
detained by the Messenian war, which was then going on, or for some other
reason of which we are not told, came a day too late for the battle of
Marathon.  After a while, the news arrived of mighty preparations being
made, and innumerable threats came from the king.  Then, as time went on, a
rumour reached us that Darius had died, and that his son, who was young and
hot-headed, had come to the throne and was persisting in his design.  The
Athenians were under the impression that the whole expedition was directed
against them, in consequence of the battle of Marathon; and hearing of the
bridge over the Hellespont, and the canal of Athos, and the host of ships,
considering that there was no salvation for them either by land or by sea,
for there was no one to help them, and remembering that in the first
expedition, when the Persians destroyed Eretria, no one came to their help,
or would risk the danger of an alliance with them, they thought that this
would happen again, at least on land; nor, when they looked to the sea,
could they descry any hope of salvation; for they were attacked by a
thousand vessels and more.  One chance of safety remained, slight indeed
and desperate, but their only one.  They saw that on the former occasion
they had gained a seemingly impossible victory, and borne up by this hope,
they found that their only refuge was in themselves and in the Gods.  All
these things created in them the spirit of friendship; there was the fear
of the moment, and there was that higher fear, which they had acquired by
obedience to their ancient laws, and which I have several times in the
preceding discourse called reverence, of which the good man ought to be a
willing servant, and of which the coward is independent and fearless.  If
this fear had not possessed them, they would never have met the enemy, or
defended their temples and sepulchres and their country, and everything
that was near and dear to them, as they did; but little by little they
would have been all scattered and dispersed.

MEGILLUS:  Your words, Athenian, are quite true, and worthy of yourself and
of your country.

ATHENIAN:  They are true, Megillus; and to you, who have inherited the
virtues of your ancestors, I may properly speak of the actions of that day. 
And I would wish you and Cleinias to consider whether my words have not
also a bearing on legislation; for I am not discoursing only for the
pleasure of talking, but for the argument's sake.  Please to remark that
the experience both of ourselves and the Persians was, in a certain sense,
the same; for as they led their people into utter servitude, so we too led
ours into all freedom.  And now, how shall we proceed? for I would like you
to observe that our previous arguments have good deal to say for
themselves.

MEGILLUS:  True; but I wish that you would give us a fuller explanation.

ATHENIAN:  I will.  Under the ancient laws, my friends, the people was not
as now the master, but rather the willing servant of the laws.

MEGILLUS:  What laws do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  In the first place, let us speak of the laws about music,--that
is to say, such music as then existed--in order that we may trace the
growth of the excess of freedom from the beginning.  Now music was early
divided among us into certain kinds and manners.  One sort consisted of
prayers to the Gods, which were called hymns; and there was another and
opposite sort called lamentations, and another termed paeans, and another,
celebrating the birth of Dionysus, called, I believe, 'dithyrambs.'  And
they used the actual word 'laws,' or nomoi, for another kind of song; and
to this they added the term 'citharoedic.'  All these and others were duly
distinguished, nor were the performers allowed to confuse one style of
music with another.  And the authority which determined and gave judgment,
and punished the disobedient, was not expressed in a hiss, nor in the most
unmusical shouts of the multitude, as in our days, nor in applause and
clapping of hands.  But the directors of public instruction insisted that
the spectators should listen in silence to the end; and boys and their
tutors, and the multitude in general, were kept quiet by a hint from a
stick.  Such was the good order which the multitude were willing to
observe; they would never have dared to give judgment by noisy cries.  And
then, as time went on, the poets themselves introduced the reign of vulgar
and lawless innovation.  They were men of genius, but they had no
perception of what is just and lawful in music; raging like Bacchanals and
possessed with inordinate delights--mingling lamentations with hymns, and
paeans with dithyrambs; imitating the sounds of the flute on the lyre, and
making one general confusion; ignorantly affirming that music has no truth,
and, whether good or bad, can only be judged of rightly by the pleasure of
the hearer (compare Republic).  And by composing such licentious works, and
adding to them words as licentious, they have inspired the multitude with
lawlessness and boldness, and made them fancy that they can judge for
themselves about melody and song.  And in this way the theatres from being
mute have become vocal, as though they had understanding of good and bad in
music and poetry; and instead of an aristocracy, an evil sort of
theatrocracy has grown up (compare Arist. Pol.).  For if the democracy
which judged had only consisted of educated persons, no fatal harm would
have been done; but in music there first arose the universal conceit of
omniscience and general lawlessness;--freedom came following afterwards,
and men, fancying that they knew what they did not know, had no longer any
fear, and the absence of fear begets shamelessness.  For what is this
shamelessness, which is so evil a thing, but the insolent refusal to regard
the opinion of the better by reason of an over-daring sort of liberty?

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Consequent upon this freedom comes the other freedom, of
disobedience to rulers (compare Republic); and then the attempt to escape
the control and exhortation of father, mother, elders, and when near the
end, the control of the laws also; and at the very end there is the
contempt of oaths and pledges, and no regard at all for the Gods,--herein
they exhibit and imitate the old so-called Titanic nature, and come to the
same point as the Titans when they rebelled against God, leading a life of
endless evils.  But why have I said all this? I ask, because the argument
ought to be pulled up from time to time, and not be allowed to run away,
but held with bit and bridle, and then we shall not, as the proverb says,
fall off our ass.  Let us then once more ask the question, To what end has
all this been said?

MEGILLUS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  This, then, has been said for the sake--

MEGILLUS:  Of what?

ATHENIAN:  We were maintaining that the lawgiver ought to have three things
in view:  first, that the city for which he legislates should be free; and
secondly, be at unity with herself; and thirdly, should have understanding;
--these were our principles, were they not?

MEGILLUS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  With a view to this we selected two kinds of government, the one
the most despotic, and the other the most free; and now we are considering
which of them is the right form:  we took a mean in both cases, of
despotism in the one, and of liberty in the other, and we saw that in a
mean they attained their perfection; but that when they were carried to the
extreme of either, slavery or licence, neither party were the gainers.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And that was our reason for considering the settlement of the
Dorian army, and of the city built by Dardanus at the foot of the
mountains, and the removal of cities to the seashore, and of our mention of
the first men, who were the survivors of the deluge.  And all that was
previously said about music and drinking, and what preceded, was said with
the view of seeing how a state might be best administered, and how an
individual might best order his own life.  And now, Megillus and Cleinias,
how can we put to the proof the value of our words?

CLEINIAS:  Stranger, I think that I see how a proof of their value may be
obtained.  This discussion of ours appears to me to have been singularly
fortunate, and just what I at this moment want; most auspiciously have you
and my friend Megillus come in my way.  For I will tell you what has
happened to me; and I regard the coincidence as a sort of omen.  The
greater part of Crete is going to send out a colony, and they have
entrusted the management of the affair to the Cnosians; and the Cnosian
government to me and nine others.  And they desire us to give them any laws
which we please, whether taken from the Cretan model or from any other; and
they do not mind about their being foreign if they are better.  Grant me
then this favour, which will also be a gain to yourselves:--Let us make a
selection from what has been said, and then let us imagine a State of which
we will suppose ourselves to be the original founders.  Thus we shall
proceed with our enquiry, and, at the same time, I may have the use of the
framework which you are constructing, for the city which is in
contemplation.

ATHENIAN:  Good news, Cleinias; if Megillus has no objection, you may be
sure that I will do all in my power to please you.

CLEINIAS:  Thank you.

MEGILLUS:  And so will I.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent; and now let us begin to frame the State.


BOOK IV.

ATHENIAN:  And now, what will this city be?  I do not mean to ask what is
or will hereafter be the name of the place; that may be determined by the
accident of locality or of the original settlement--a river or fountain, or
some local deity may give the sanction of a name to the newly-founded city;
but I do want to know what the situation is, whether maritime or inland.

CLEINIAS:  I should imagine, Stranger, that the city of which we are
speaking is about eighty stadia distant from the sea.

ATHENIAN:  And are there harbours on the seaboard?

CLEINIAS:  Excellent harbours, Stranger; there could not be better.

ATHENIAN:  Alas! what a prospect!  And is the surrounding country
productive, or in need of importations?

CLEINIAS:  Hardly in need of anything.

ATHENIAN:  And is there any neighbouring State?

CLEINIAS:  None whatever, and that is the reason for selecting the place;
in days of old, there was a migration of the inhabitants, and the region
has been deserted from time immemorial.

ATHENIAN:  And has the place a fair proportion of hill, and plain, and
wood?

CLEINIAS:  Like the rest of Crete in that.

ATHENIAN:  You mean to say that there is more rock than plain?

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  Then there is some hope that your citizens may be virtuous:  had
you been on the sea, and well provided with harbours, and an importing
rather than a producing country, some mighty saviour would have been
needed, and lawgivers more than mortal, if you were ever to have a chance
of preserving your state from degeneracy and discordance of manners
(compare Ar. Pol.).  But there is comfort in the eighty stadia; although
the sea is too near, especially if, as you say, the harbours are so good. 
Still we may be content.  The sea is pleasant enough as a daily companion,
but has indeed also a bitter and brackish quality; filling the streets with
merchants and shopkeepers, and begetting in the souls of men uncertain and
unfaithful ways--making the state unfriendly and unfaithful both to her own
citizens, and also to other nations.  There is a consolation, therefore, in
the country producing all things at home; and yet, owing to the ruggedness
of the soil, not providing anything in great abundance.  Had there been
abundance, there might have been a great export trade, and a great return
of gold and silver; which, as we may safely affirm, has the most fatal
results on a State whose aim is the attainment of just and noble
sentiments:  this was said by us, if you remember, in the previous
discussion.

CLEINIAS:  I remember, and am of opinion that we both were and are in the
right.

ATHENIAN:  Well, but let me ask, how is the country supplied with timber
for ship-building?

CLEINIAS:  There is no fir of any consequence, nor pine, and not much
cypress; and you will find very little stone-pine or plane-wood, which
shipwrights always require for the interior of ships.

ATHENIAN:  These are also natural advantages.

CLEINIAS:  Why so?

ATHENIAN:  Because no city ought to be easily able to imitate its enemies
in what is mischievous.

CLEINIAS:  How does that bear upon any of the matters of which we have been
speaking?

ATHENIAN:  Remember, my good friend, what I said at first about the Cretan
laws, that they looked to one thing only, and this, as you both agreed, was
war; and I replied that such laws, in so far as they tended to promote
virtue, were good; but in that they regarded a part only, and not the whole
of virtue, I disapproved of them.  And now I hope that you in your turn
will follow and watch me if I legislate with a view to anything but virtue,
or with a view to a part of virtue only.  For I consider that the true
lawgiver, like an archer, aims only at that on which some eternal beauty is
always attending, and dismisses everything else, whether wealth or any
other benefit, when separated from virtue.  I was saying that the imitation
of enemies was a bad thing; and I was thinking of a case in which a
maritime people are harassed by enemies, as the Athenians were by Minos (I
do not speak from any desire to recall past grievances); but he, as we
know, was a great naval potentate, who compelled the inhabitants of Attica
to pay him a cruel tribute; and in those days they had no ships of war as
they now have, nor was the country filled with ship-timber, and therefore
they could not readily build them.  Hence they could not learn how to
imitate their enemy at sea, and in this way, becoming sailors themselves,
directly repel their enemies.  Better for them to have lost many times over
the seven youths, than that heavy-armed and stationary troops should have
been turned into sailors, and accustomed to be often leaping on shore, and
again to come running back to their ships; or should have fancied that
there was no disgrace in not awaiting the attack of an enemy and dying
boldly; and that there were good reasons, and plenty of them, for a man
throwing away his arms, and betaking himself to flight,--which is not
dishonourable, as people say, at certain times.  This is the language of
naval warfare, and is anything but worthy of extraordinary praise.  For we
should not teach bad habits, least of all to the best part of the citizens. 
You may learn the evil of such a practice from Homer, by whom Odysseus is
introduced, rebuking Agamemnon, because he desires to draw down the ships
to the sea at a time when the Achaeans are hard pressed by the Trojans,--he
gets angry with him, and says:

'Who, at a time when the battle is in full cry, biddest to drag the well-
benched ships into the sea, that the prayers of the Trojans may be
accomplished yet more, and high ruin fall upon us.  For the Achaeans will
not maintain the battle, when the ships are drawn into the sea, but they
will look behind and will cease from strife; in that the counsel which you
give will prove injurious.'

You see that he quite knew triremes on the sea, in the neighbourhood of
fighting men, to be an evil;--lions might be trained in that way to fly
from a herd of deer.  Moreover, naval powers which owe their safety to
ships, do not give honour to that sort of warlike excellence which is most
deserving of it.  For he who owes his safety to the pilot and the captain,
and the oarsman, and all sorts of rather inferior persons, cannot rightly
give honour to whom honour is due.  But how can a state be in a right
condition which cannot justly award honour?

CLEINIAS:  It is hardly possible, I admit; and yet, Stranger, we Cretans
are in the habit of saying that the battle of Salamis was the salvation of
Hellas.

ATHENIAN:  Why, yes; and that is an opinion which is widely spread both
among Hellenes and barbarians.  But Megillus and I say rather, that the
battle of Marathon was the beginning, and the battle of Plataea the
completion, of the great deliverance, and that these battles by land made
the Hellenes better; whereas the sea-fights of Salamis and Artemisium--for
I may as well put them both together--made them no better, if I may say so
without offence about the battles which helped to save us.  And in
estimating the goodness of a state, we regard both the situation of the
country and the order of the laws, considering that the mere preservation
and continuance of life is not the most honourable thing for men, as the
vulgar think, but the continuance of the best life, while we live; and that
again, if I am not mistaken, is a remark which has been made already.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Then we have only to ask, whether we are taking the course which
we acknowledge to be the best for the settlement and legislation of states.

CLEINIAS:  The best by far.

ATHENIAN:  And now let me proceed to another question:  Who are to be the
colonists?  May any one come out of all Crete; and is the idea that the
population in the several states is too numerous for the means of
subsistence?  For I suppose that you are not going to send out a general
invitation to any Hellene who likes to come.  And yet I observe that to
your country settlers have come from Argos and Aegina and other parts of
Hellas.  Tell me, then, whence do you draw your recruits in the present
enterprise?

CLEINIAS:  They will come from all Crete; and of other Hellenes,
Peloponnesians will be most acceptable.  For, as you truly observe, there
are Cretans of Argive descent; and the race of Cretans which has the
highest character at the present day is the Gortynian, and this has come
from Gortys in the Peloponnesus.

ATHENIAN:  Cities find colonization in some respects easier if the
colonists are one race, which like a swarm of bees is sent out from a
single country, either when friends leave friends, owing to some pressure
of population or other similar necessity, or when a portion of a state is
driven by factions to emigrate.  And there have been whole cities which
have taken flight when utterly conquered by a superior power in war.  This,
however, which is in one way an advantage to the colonist or legislator, in
another point of view creates a difficulty.  There is an element of
friendship in the community of race, and language, and laws, and in common
temples and rites of worship; but colonies which are of this homogeneous
sort are apt to kick against any laws or any form of constitution differing
from that which they had at home; and although the badness of their own
laws may have been the cause of the factions which prevailed among them,
yet from the force of habit they would fain preserve the very customs which
were their ruin, and the leader of the colony, who is their legislator,
finds them troublesome and rebellious.  On the other hand, the conflux of
several populations might be more disposed to listen to new laws; but then,
to make them combine and pull together, as they say of horses, is a most
difficult task, and the work of years.  And yet there is nothing which
tends more to the improvement of mankind than legislation and colonization.

CLEINIAS:  No doubt; but I should like to know why you say so.

ATHENIAN:  My good friend, I am afraid that the course of my speculations
is leading me to say something depreciatory of legislators; but if the word
be to the purpose, there can be no harm.  And yet, why am I disquieted, for
I believe that the same principle applies equally to all human things?

CLEINIAS:  To what are you referring?

ATHENIAN:  I was going to say that man never legislates, but accidents of
all sorts, which legislate for us in all sorts of ways.  The violence of
war and the hard necessity of poverty are constantly overturning
governments and changing laws.  And the power of disease has often caused
innovations in the state, when there have been pestilences, or when there
has been a succession of bad seasons continuing during many years.  Any one
who sees all this, naturally rushes to the conclusion of which I was
speaking, that no mortal legislates in anything, but that in human affairs
chance is almost everything.  And this may be said of the arts of the
sailor, and the pilot, and the physician, and the general, and may seem to
be well said; and yet there is another thing which may be said with equal
truth of all of them.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  That God governs all things, and that chance and opportunity co-
operate with Him in the government of human affairs.  There is, however, a
third and less extreme view, that art should be there also; for I should
say that in a storm there must surely be a great advantage in having the
aid of the pilot's art.  You would agree?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And does not a like principle apply to legislation as well as to
other things:  even supposing all the conditions to be favourable which are
needed for the happiness of the state, yet the true legislator must from
time to time appear on the scene?

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  In each case the artist would be able to pray rightly for
certain conditions, and if these were granted by fortune, he would then
only require to exercise his art?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And all the other artists just now mentioned, if they were
bidden to offer up each their special prayer, would do so?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And the legislator would do likewise?

CLEINIAS:  I believe that he would.

ATHENIAN:  'Come, legislator,' we will say to him; 'what are the conditions
which you require in a state before you can organize it?'  How ought he to
answer this question?  Shall I give his answer?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  He will say--'Give me a state which is governed by a tyrant, and
let the tyrant be young and have a good memory; let him be quick at
learning, and of a courageous and noble nature; let him have that quality
which, as I said before, is the inseparable companion of all the other
parts of virtue, if there is to be any good in them.'

CLEINIAS:  I suppose, Megillus, that this companion virtue of which the
Stranger speaks, must be temperance?

ATHENIAN:  Yes, Cleinias, temperance in the vulgar sense; not that which in
the forced and exaggerated language of some philosophers is called
prudence, but that which is the natural gift of children and animals, of
whom some live continently and others incontinently, but when isolated,
was, as we said, hardly worth reckoning in the catalogue of goods.  I think
that you must understand my meaning.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then our tyrant must have this as well as the other qualities,
if the state is to acquire in the best manner and in the shortest time the
form of government which is most conducive to happiness; for there neither
is nor ever will be a better or speedier way of establishing a polity than
by a tyranny.

CLEINIAS:  By what possible arguments, Stranger, can any man persuade
himself of such a monstrous doctrine?

ATHENIAN:  There is surely no difficulty in seeing, Cleinias, what is in
accordance with the order of nature?

CLEINIAS:  You would assume, as you say, a tyrant who was young, temperate,
quick at learning, having a good memory, courageous, of a noble nature?

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and you must add fortunate; and his good fortune must be
that he is the contemporary of a great legislator, and that some happy
chance brings them together.  When this has been accomplished, God has done
all that he ever does for a state which he desires to be eminently
prosperous; He has done second best for a state in which there are two such
rulers, and third best for a state in which there are three.  The
difficulty increases with the increase, and diminishes with the diminution
of the number.

CLEINIAS:  You mean to say, I suppose, that the best government is produced
from a tyranny, and originates in a good lawgiver and an orderly tyrant,
and that the change from such a tyranny into a perfect form of government
takes place most easily; less easily when from an oligarchy; and, in the
third degree, from a democracy:  is not that your meaning?

ATHENIAN:  Not so; I mean rather to say that the change is best made out of
a tyranny; and secondly, out of a monarchy; and thirdly, out of some sort
of democracy:  fourth, in the capacity for improvement, comes oligarchy,
which has the greatest difficulty in admitting of such a change, because
the government is in the hands of a number of potentates.  I am supposing
that the legislator is by nature of the true sort, and that his strength is
united with that of the chief men of the state; and when the ruling element
is numerically small, and at the same time very strong, as in a tyranny,
there the change is likely to be easiest and most rapid.

CLEINIAS:  How?  I do not understand.

ATHENIAN:  And yet I have repeated what I am saying a good many times; but
I suppose that you have never seen a city which is under a tyranny?

CLEINIAS:  No, and I cannot say that I have any great desire to see one.

ATHENIAN:  And yet, where there is a tyranny, you might certainly see that
of which I am now speaking.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that you might see how, without trouble and in no very
long period of time, the tyrant, if he wishes, can change the manners of a
state:  he has only to go in the direction of virtue or of vice, whichever
he prefers, he himself indicating by his example the lines of conduct,
praising and rewarding some actions and reproving others, and degrading
those who disobey.

CLEINIAS:  But how can we imagine that the citizens in general will at once
follow the example set to them; and how can he have this power both of
persuading and of compelling them?

ATHENIAN:  Let no one, my friends, persuade us that there is any quicker
and easier way in which states change their laws than when the rulers lead: 
such changes never have, nor ever will, come to pass in any other way.  The
real impossibility or difficulty is of another sort, and is rarely
surmounted in the course of ages; but when once it is surmounted, ten
thousand or rather all blessings follow.

CLEINIAS:  Of what are you speaking?

ATHENIAN:  The difficulty is to find the divine love of temperate and just
institutions existing in any powerful forms of government, whether in a
monarchy or oligarchy of wealth or of birth.  You might as well hope to
reproduce the character of Nestor, who is said to have excelled all men in
the power of speech, and yet more in his temperance.  This, however,
according to the tradition, was in the times of Troy; in our own days there
is nothing of the sort; but if such an one either has or ever shall come
into being, or is now among us, blessed is he and blessed are they who hear
the wise words that flow from his lips.  And this may be said of power in
general:  When the supreme power in man coincides with the greatest wisdom
and temperance, then the best laws and the best constitution come into
being; but in no other way.  And let what I have been saying be regarded as
a kind of sacred legend or oracle, and let this be our proof that, in one
point of view, there may be a difficulty for a city to have good laws, but
that there is another point of view in which nothing can be easier or
sooner effected, granting our supposition.

CLEINIAS:  How do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Let us try to amuse ourselves, old boys as we are, by moulding
in words the laws which are suitable to your state.

CLEINIAS:  Let us proceed without delay.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us invoke God at the settlement of our state; may He
hear and be propitious to us, and come and set in order the State and the
laws!

CLEINIAS:  May He come!

ATHENIAN:  But what form of polity are we going to give the city?

CLEINIAS:  Tell us what you mean a little more clearly.  Do you mean some
form of democracy, or oligarchy, or aristocracy, or monarchy?  For we
cannot suppose that you would include tyranny.

ATHENIAN:  Which of you will first tell me to which of these classes his
own government is to be referred?

MEGILLUS:  Ought I to answer first, since I am the elder?

CLEINIAS:  Perhaps you should.

MEGILLUS:  And yet, Stranger, I perceive that I cannot say, without more
thought, what I should call the government of Lacedaemon, for it seems to
me to be like a tyranny,--the power of our Ephors is marvellously
tyrannical; and sometimes it appears to me to be of all cities the most
democratical; and who can reasonably deny that it is an aristocracy
(compare Ar. Pol.)?  We have also a monarchy which is held for life, and is
said by all mankind, and not by ourselves only, to be the most ancient of
all monarchies; and, therefore, when asked on a sudden, I cannot precisely
say which form of government the Spartan is.

CLEINIAS:  I am in the same difficulty, Megillus; for I do not feel
confident that the polity of Cnosus is any of these.

ATHENIAN:  The reason is, my excellent friends, that you really have
polities, but the states of which we were just now speaking are merely
aggregations of men dwelling in cities who are the subjects and servants of
a part of their own state, and each of them is named after the dominant
power; they are not polities at all.  But if states are to be named after
their rulers, the true state ought to be called by the name of the God who
rules over wise men.

CLEINIAS:  And who is this God?

ATHENIAN:  May I still make use of fable to some extent, in the hope that I
may be better able to answer your question:  shall I?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  In the primeval world, and a long while before the cities came
into being whose settlements we have described, there is said to have been
in the time of Cronos a blessed rule and life, of which the best-ordered of
existing states is a copy (compare Statesman).

CLEINIAS:  It will be very necessary to hear about that.

ATHENIAN:  I quite agree with you; and therefore I have introduced the
subject.

CLEINIAS:  Most appropriately; and since the tale is to the point, you will
do well in giving us the whole story.

ATHENIAN:  I will do as you suggest.  There is a tradition of the happy
life of mankind in days when all things were spontaneous and abundant.  And
of this the reason is said to have been as follows:--Cronos knew what we
ourselves were declaring, that no human nature invested with supreme power
is able to order human affairs and not overflow with insolence and wrong. 
Which reflection led him to appoint not men but demigods, who are of a
higher and more divine race, to be the kings and rulers of our cities; he
did as we do with flocks of sheep and other tame animals.  For we do not
appoint oxen to be the lords of oxen, or goats of goats; but we ourselves
are a superior race, and rule over them.  In like manner God, in His love
of mankind, placed over us the demons, who are a superior race, and they
with great ease and pleasure to themselves, and no less to us, taking care
of us and giving us peace and reverence and order and justice never
failing, made the tribes of men happy and united.  And this tradition,
which is true, declares that cities of which some mortal man and not God is
the ruler, have no escape from evils and toils.  Still we must do all that
we can to imitate the life which is said to have existed in the days of
Cronos, and, as far as the principle of immortality dwells in us, to that
we must hearken, both in private and public life, and regulate our cities
and houses according to law, meaning by the very term 'law,' the
distribution of mind.  But if either a single person or an oligarchy or a
democracy has a soul eager after pleasures and desires--wanting to be
filled with them, yet retaining none of them, and perpetually afflicted
with an endless and insatiable disorder; and this evil spirit, having first
trampled the laws under foot, becomes the master either of a state or of an
individual,--then, as I was saying, salvation is hopeless.  And now,
Cleinias, we have to consider whether you will or will not accept this tale
of mine.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly we will.

ATHENIAN:  You are aware,--are you not?--that there are often said to be as
many forms of laws as there are of governments, and of the latter we have
already mentioned all those which are commonly recognized.  Now you must
regard this as a matter of first-rate importance.  For what is to be the
standard of just and unjust, is once more the point at issue.  Men say that
the law ought not to regard either military virtue, or virtue in general,
but only the interests and power and preservation of the established form
of government; this is thought by them to be the best way of expressing the
natural definition of justice.

CLEINIAS:  How?

ATHENIAN:  Justice is said by them to be the interest of the stronger
(Republic).

CLEINIAS:  Speak plainer.

ATHENIAN:  I will:--'Surely,' they say, 'the governing power makes whatever
laws have authority in any state'?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  'Well,' they would add, 'and do you suppose that tyranny or
democracy, or any other conquering power, does not make the continuance of
the power which is possessed by them the first or principal object of their
laws'?

CLEINIAS:  How can they have any other?

ATHENIAN:  'And whoever transgresses these laws is punished as an evil-doer
by the legislator, who calls the laws just'?

CLEINIAS:  Naturally.

ATHENIAN:  'This, then, is always the mode and fashion in which justice
exists.'

CLEINIAS:  Certainly, if they are correct in their view.

ATHENIAN:  Why, yes, this is one of those false principles of government to
which we were referring.

CLEINIAS:  Which do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Those which we were examining when we spoke of who ought to
govern whom.  Did we not arrive at the conclusion that parents ought to
govern their children, and the elder the younger, and the noble the
ignoble?  And there were many other principles, if you remember, and they
were not always consistent.  One principle was this very principle of
might, and we said that Pindar considered violence natural and justified
it.

CLEINIAS:  Yes; I remember.

ATHENIAN:  Consider, then, to whom our state is to be entrusted.  For there
is a thing which has occurred times without number in states--

CLEINIAS:  What thing?

ATHENIAN:  That when there has been a contest for power, those who gain the
upper hand so entirely monopolize the government, as to refuse all share to
the defeated party and their descendants--they live watching one another,
the ruling class being in perpetual fear that some one who has a
recollection of former wrongs will come into power and rise up against
them.  Now, according to our view, such governments are not polities at
all, nor are laws right which are passed for the good of particular classes
and not for the good of the whole state.  States which have such laws are
not polities but parties, and their notions of justice are simply
unmeaning.  I say this, because I am going to assert that we must not
entrust the government in your state to any one because he is rich, or
because he possesses any other advantage, such as strength, or stature, or
again birth:  but he who is most obedient to the laws of the state, he
shall win the palm; and to him who is victorious in the first degree shall
be given the highest office and chief ministry of the gods; and the second
to him who bears the second palm; and on a similar principle shall all the
other offices be assigned to those who come next in order.  And when I call
the rulers servants or ministers of the law, I give them this name not for
the sake of novelty, but because I certainly believe that upon such service
or ministry depends the well- or ill-being of the state.  For that state in
which the law is subject and has no authority, I perceive to be on the
highway to ruin; but I see that the state in which the law is above the
rulers, and the rulers are the inferiors of the law, has salvation, and
every blessing which the Gods can confer.

CLEINIAS:  Truly, Stranger, you see with the keen vision of age.

ATHENIAN:  Why, yes; every man when he is young has that sort of vision
dullest, and when he is old keenest.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And now, what is to be the next step?  May we not suppose the
colonists to have arrived, and proceed to make our speech to them?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  'Friends,' we say to them,--'God, as the old tradition declares,
holding in his hand the beginning, middle, and end of all that is, travels
according to His nature in a straight line towards the accomplishment of
His end.  Justice always accompanies Him, and is the punisher of those who
fall short of the divine law.  To justice, he who would be happy holds
fast, and follows in her company with all humility and order; but he who is
lifted up with pride, or elated by wealth or rank, or beauty, who is young
and foolish, and has a soul hot with insolence, and thinks that he has no
need of any guide or ruler, but is able himself to be the guide of others,
he, I say, is left deserted of God; and being thus deserted, he takes to
him others who are like himself, and dances about, throwing all things into
confusion, and many think that he is a great man, but in a short time he
pays a penalty which justice cannot but approve, and is utterly destroyed,
and his family and city with him.  Wherefore, seeing that human things are
thus ordered, what should a wise man do or think, or not do or think'?

CLEINIAS:  Every man ought to make up his mind that he will be one of the
followers of God; there can be no doubt of that.

ATHENIAN:  Then what life is agreeable to God, and becoming in His
followers?  One only, expressed once for all in the old saying that 'like
agrees with like, with measure measure,' but things which have no measure
agree neither with themselves nor with the things which have.  Now God
ought to be to us the measure of all things, and not man (compare Crat.;
Theaet.), as men commonly say (Protagoras):  the words are far more true of
Him.  And he who would be dear to God must, as far as is possible, be like
Him and such as He is.  Wherefore the temperate man is the friend of God,
for he is like Him; and the intemperate man is unlike Him, and different
from Him, and unjust.  And the same applies to other things; and this is
the conclusion, which is also the noblest and truest of all sayings,--that
for the good man to offer sacrifice to the Gods, and hold converse with
them by means of prayers and offerings and every kind of service, is the
noblest and best of all things, and also the most conducive to a happy
life, and very fit and meet.  But with the bad man, the opposite of this is
true:  for the bad man has an impure soul, whereas the good is pure; and
from one who is polluted, neither a good man nor God can without
impropriety receive gifts.  Wherefore the unholy do only waste their much
service upon the Gods, but when offered by any holy man, such service is
most acceptable to them.  This is the mark at which we ought to aim.  But
what weapons shall we use, and how shall we direct them?  In the first
place, we affirm that next after the Olympian Gods and the Gods of the
State, honour should be given to the Gods below; they should receive
everything in even numbers, and of the second choice, and ill omen, while
the odd numbers, and the first choice, and the things of lucky omen, are
given to the Gods above, by him who would rightly hit the mark of piety. 
Next to these Gods, a wise man will do service to the demons or spirits,
and then to the heroes, and after them will follow the private and
ancestral Gods, who are worshipped as the law prescribes in the places
which are sacred to them.  Next comes the honour of living parents, to
whom, as is meet, we have to pay the first and greatest and oldest of all
debts, considering that all which a man has belongs to those who gave him
birth and brought him up, and that he must do all that he can to minister
to them, first, in his property, secondly, in his person, and thirdly, in
his soul, in return for the endless care and travail which they bestowed
upon him of old, in the days of his infancy, and which he is now to pay
back to them when they are old and in the extremity of their need.  And all
his life long he ought never to utter, or to have uttered, an unbecoming
word to them; for of light and fleeting words the penalty is most severe;
Nemesis, the messenger of justice, is appointed to watch over all such
matters.  When they are angry and want to satisfy their feelings in word or
deed, he should give way to them; for a father who thinks that he has been
wronged by his son may be reasonably expected to be very angry.  At their
death, the most moderate funeral is best, neither exceeding the customary
expense, nor yet falling short of the honour which has been usually shown
by the former generation to their parents.  And let a man not forget to pay
the yearly tribute of respect to the dead, honouring them chiefly by
omitting nothing that conduces to a perpetual remembrance of them, and
giving a reasonable portion of his fortune to the dead.  Doing this, and
living after this manner, we shall receive our reward from the Gods and
those who are above us (i.e. the demons); and we shall spend our days for
the most part in good hope.  And how a man ought to order what relates to
his descendants and his kindred and friends and fellow-citizens, and the
rites of hospitality taught by Heaven, and the intercourse which arises out
of all these duties, with a view to the embellishment and orderly
regulation of his own life--these things, I say, the laws, as we proceed
with them, will accomplish, partly persuading, and partly when natures do
not yield to the persuasion of custom, chastising them by might and right,
and will thus render our state, if the Gods co-operate with us, prosperous
and happy.  But of what has to be said, and must be said by the legislator
who is of my way of thinking, and yet, if said in the form of law, would be
out of place--of this I think that he may give a sample for the instruction
of himself and of those for whom he is legislating; and then when, as far
as he is able, he has gone through all the preliminaries, he may proceed to
the work of legislation.  Now, what will be the form of such prefaces? 
There may be a difficulty in including or describing them all under a
single form, but I think that we may get some notion of them if we can
guarantee one thing.

CLEINIAS:  What is that?

ATHENIAN:  I should wish the citizens to be as readily persuaded to virtue
as possible; this will surely be the aim of the legislator in all his laws.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  The proposal appears to me to be of some value; and I think that
a person will listen with more gentleness and good-will to the precepts
addressed to him by the legislator, when his soul is not altogether
unprepared to receive them.  Even a little done in the way of conciliation
gains his ear, and is always worth having.  For there is no great
inclination or readiness on the part of mankind to be made as good, or as
quickly good, as possible.  The case of the many proves the wisdom of
Hesiod, who says that the road to wickedness is smooth and can be travelled
without perspiring, because it is so very short:

'But before virtue the immortal Gods have placed the sweat of labour, and
long and steep is the way thither, and rugged at first; but when you have
reached the top, although difficult before, it is then easy.'  (Works and
Days.)

CLEINIAS:  Yes; and he certainly speaks well.

ATHENIAN:  Very true:  and now let me tell you the effect which the
preceding discourse has had upon me.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose that we have a little conversation with the legislator,
and say to him--'O, legislator, speak; if you know what we ought to say and
do, you can surely tell.'

CLEINIAS:  Of course he can.

ATHENIAN:  'Did we not hear you just now saying, that the legislator ought
not to allow the poets to do what they liked?  For that they would not know
in which of their words they went against the laws, to the hurt of the
state.'

CLEINIAS:  That is true.

ATHENIAN:  May we not fairly make answer to him on behalf of the poets?

CLEINIAS:  What answer shall we make to him?

ATHENIAN:  That the poet, according to the tradition which has ever
prevailed among us, and is accepted of all men, when he sits down on the
tripod of the muse, is not in his right mind; like a fountain, he allows to
flow out freely whatever comes in, and his art being imitative, he is often
compelled to represent men of opposite dispositions, and thus to contradict
himself; neither can he tell whether there is more truth in one thing that
he has said than in another.  This is not the case in a law; the legislator
must give not two rules about the same thing, but one only.  Take an
example from what you have just been saying.  Of three kinds of funerals,
there is one which is too extravagant, another is too niggardly, the third
in a mean; and you choose and approve and order the last without
qualification.  But if I had an extremely rich wife, and she bade me bury
her and describe her burial in a poem, I should praise the extravagant
sort; and a poor miserly man, who had not much money to spend, would
approve of the niggardly; and the man of moderate means, who was himself
moderate, would praise a moderate funeral.  Now you in the capacity of
legislator must not barely say 'a moderate funeral,' but you must define
what moderation is, and how much; unless you are definite, you must not
suppose that you are speaking a language that can become law.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  And is our legislator to have no preface to his laws, but to say
at once Do this, avoid that--and then holding the penalty in terrorem, to
go on to another law; offering never a word of advice or exhortation to
those for whom he is legislating, after the manner of some doctors?  For of
doctors, as I may remind you, some have a gentler, others a ruder method of
cure; and as children ask the doctor to be gentle with them, so we will ask
the legislator to cure our disorders with the gentlest remedies.  What I
mean to say is, that besides doctors there are doctors' servants, who are
also styled doctors.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And whether they are slaves or freemen makes no difference; they
acquire their knowledge of medicine by obeying and observing their masters;
empirically and not according to the natural way of learning, as the manner
of freemen is, who have learned scientifically themselves the art which
they impart scientifically to their pupils.  You are aware that there are
these two classes of doctors?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And did you ever observe that there are two classes of patients
in states, slaves and freemen; and the slave doctors run about and cure the
slaves, or wait for them in the dispensaries--practitioners of this sort
never talk to their patients individually, or let them talk about their own
individual complaints?  The slave doctor prescribes what mere experience
suggests, as if he had exact knowledge; and when he has given his orders,
like a tyrant, he rushes off with equal assurance to some other servant who
is ill; and so he relieves the master of the house of the care of his
invalid slaves.  But the other doctor, who is a freeman, attends and
practices upon freemen; and he carries his enquiries far back, and goes
into the nature of the disorder; he enters into discourse with the patient
and with his friends, and is at once getting information from the sick man,
and also instructing him as far as he is able, and he will not prescribe
for him until he has first convinced him; at last, when he has brought the
patient more and more under his persuasive influences and set him on the
road to health, he attempts to effect a cure.  Now which is the better way
of proceeding in a physician and in a trainer?  Is he the better who
accomplishes his ends in a double way, or he who works in one way, and that
the ruder and inferior?

CLEINIAS:  I should say, Stranger, that the double way is far better.

ATHENIAN:  Should you like to see an example of the double and single
method in legislation?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly I should.

ATHENIAN:  What will be our first law?  Will not the legislator, observing
the order of nature, begin by making regulations for states about births?

CLEINIAS:  He will.

ATHENIAN:  In all states the birth of children goes back to the connexion
of marriage?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And, according to the true order, the laws relating to marriage
should be those which are first determined in every state?

CLEINIAS:  Quite so.

ATHENIAN:  Then let me first give the law of marriage in a simple form; it
may run as follows:--A man shall marry between the ages of thirty and
thirty-five, or, if he does not, he shall pay such and such a fine, or
shall suffer the loss of such and such privileges.  This would be the
simple law about marriage.  The double law would run thus:--A man shall
marry between the ages of thirty and thirty-five, considering that in a
manner the human race naturally partakes of immortality, which every man is
by nature inclined to desire to the utmost; for the desire of every man
that he may become famous, and not lie in the grave without a name, is only
the love of continuance.  Now mankind are coeval with all time, and are
ever following, and will ever follow, the course of time; and so they are
immortal, because they leave children's children behind them, and partake
of immortality in the unity of generation.  And for a man voluntarily to
deprive himself of this gift, as he deliberately does who will not have a
wife or children, is impiety.  He who obeys the law shall be free, and
shall pay no fine; but he who is disobedient, and does not marry, when he
has arrived at the age of thirty-five, shall pay a yearly fine of a certain
amount, in order that he may not imagine his celibacy to bring ease and
profit to him; and he shall not share in the honours which the young men in
the state give to the aged.  Comparing now the two forms of the law, you
will be able to arrive at a judgment about any other laws--whether they
should be double in length even when shortest, because they have to
persuade as well as threaten, or whether they shall only threaten and be of
half the length.

MEGILLUS:  The shorter form, Stranger, would be more in accordance with
Lacedaemonian custom; although, for my own part, if any one were to ask me
which I myself prefer in the state, I should certainly determine in favour
of the longer; and I would have every law made after the same pattern, if I
had to choose.  But I think that Cleinias is the person to be consulted,
for his is the state which is going to use these laws.

CLEINIAS:  Thank you, Megillus.

ATHENIAN:  Whether, in the abstract, words are to be many or few, is a very
foolish question; the best form, and not the shortest, is to be approved;
nor is length at all to be regarded.  Of the two forms of law which have
been recited, the one is not only twice as good in practical usefulness as
the other, but the case is like that of the two kinds of doctors, which I
was just now mentioning.  And yet legislators never appear to have
considered that they have two instruments which they might use in
legislation--persuasion and force; for in dealing with the rude and
uneducated multitude, they use the one only as far as they can; they do not
mingle persuasion with coercion, but employ force pure and simple. 
Moreover, there is a third point, sweet friends, which ought to be, and
never is, regarded in our existing laws.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  A point arising out of our previous discussion, which comes into
my mind in some mysterious way.  All this time, from early dawn until noon,
have we been talking about laws in this charming retreat:  now we are going
to promulgate our laws, and what has preceded was only the prelude of them. 
Why do I mention this?  For this reason:--Because all discourses and vocal
exercises have preludes and overtures, which are a sort of artistic
beginnings intended to help the strain which is to be performed; lyric
measures and music of every other kind have preludes framed with wonderful
care.  But of the truer and higher strain of law and politics, no one has
ever yet uttered any prelude, or composed or published any, as though there
was no such thing in nature.  Whereas our present discussion seems to me to
imply that there is;--these double laws, of which we were speaking, are not
exactly double, but they are in two parts, the law and the prelude of the
law.  The arbitrary command, which was compared to the commands of doctors,
whom we described as of the meaner sort, was the law pure and simple; and
that which preceded, and was described by our friend here as being
hortatory only, was, although in fact, an exhortation, likewise analogous
to the preamble of a discourse.  For I imagine that all this language of
conciliation, which the legislator has been uttering in the preface of the
law, was intended to create good-will in the person whom he addressed, in
order that, by reason of this good-will, he might more intelligently
receive his command, that is to say, the law.  And therefore, in my way of
speaking, this is more rightly described as the preamble than as the matter
of the law.  And I must further proceed to observe, that to all his laws,
and to each separately, the legislator should prefix a preamble; he should
remember how great will be the difference between them, according as they
have, or have not, such preambles, as in the case already given.

CLEINIAS:  The lawgiver, if he asks my opinion, will certainly legislate in
the form which you advise.

ATHENIAN:  I think that you are right, Cleinias, in affirming that all laws
have preambles, and that throughout the whole of this work of legislation
every single law should have a suitable preamble at the beginning; for that
which is to follow is most important, and it makes all the difference
whether we clearly remember the preambles or not.  Yet we should be wrong
in requiring that all laws, small and great alike, should have preambles of
the same kind, any more than all songs or speeches; although they may be
natural to all, they are not always necessary, and whether they are to be
employed or not has in each case to be left to the judgment of the speaker
or the musician, or, in the present instance, of the lawgiver.

CLEINIAS:  That I think is most true.  And now, Stranger, without delay let
us return to the argument, and, as people say in play, make a second and
better beginning, if you please, with the principles which we have been
laying down, which we never thought of regarding as a preamble before, but
of which we may now make a preamble, and not merely consider them to be
chance topics of discourse.  Let us acknowledge, then, that we have a
preamble.  About the honour of the Gods and the respect of parents, enough
has been already said; and we may proceed to the topics which follow next
in order, until the preamble is deemed by you to be complete; and after
that you shall go through the laws themselves.

ATHENIAN:  I understand you to mean that we have made a sufficient preamble
about Gods and demigods, and about parents living or dead; and now you
would have us bring the rest of the subject into the light of day?

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  After this, as is meet and for the interest of us all, I the
speaker, and you the listeners, will try to estimate all that relates to
the souls and bodies and properties of the citizens, as regards both their
occupations and amusements, and thus arrive, as far as in us lies, at the
nature of education.  These then are the topics which follow next in order.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.


BOOK V.

ATHENIAN:  Listen, all ye who have just now heard the laws about Gods, and
about our dear forefathers:--Of all the things which a man has, next to the
Gods, his soul is the most divine and most truly his own.  Now in every man
there are two parts:  the better and superior, which rules, and the worse
and inferior, which serves; and the ruling part of him is always to be
preferred to the subject.  Wherefore I am right in bidding every one next
to the Gods, who are our masters, and those who in order follow them (i.e.
the demons), to honour his own soul, which every one seems to honour, but
no one honours as he ought; for honour is a divine good, and no evil thing
is honourable; and he who thinks that he can honour the soul by word or
gift, or any sort of compliance, without making her in any way better,
seems to honour her, but honours her not at all.  For example, every man,
from his very boyhood, fancies that he is able to know everything, and
thinks that he honours his soul by praising her, and he is very ready to
let her do whatever she may like.  But I mean to say that in acting thus he
injures his soul, and is far from honouring her; whereas, in our opinion,
he ought to honour her as second only to the Gods.  Again, when a man
thinks that others are to be blamed, and not himself, for the errors which
he has committed from time to time, and the many and great evils which
befell him in consequence, and is always fancying himself to be exempt and
innocent, he is under the idea that he is honouring his soul; whereas the
very reverse is the fact, for he is really injuring her.  And when,
disregarding the word and approval of the legislator, he indulges in
pleasure, then again he is far from honouring her; he only dishonours her,
and fills her full of evil and remorse; or when he does not endure to the
end the labours and fears and sorrows and pains which the legislator
approves, but gives way before them, then, by yielding, he does not honour
the soul, but by all such conduct he makes her to be dishonourable; nor
when he thinks that life at any price is a good, does he honour her, but
yet once more he dishonours her; for the soul having a notion that the
world below is all evil, he yields to her, and does not resist and teach or
convince her that, for aught she knows, the world of the Gods below,
instead of being evil, may be the greatest of all goods.  Again, when any
one prefers beauty to virtue, what is this but the real and utter dishonour
of the soul?  For such a preference implies that the body is more
honourable than the soul; and this is false, for there is nothing of
earthly birth which is more honourable than the heavenly, and he who thinks
otherwise of the soul has no idea how greatly he undervalues this wonderful
possession; nor, again, when a person is willing, or not unwilling, to
acquire dishonest gains, does he then honour his soul with gifts--far
otherwise; he sells her glory and honour for a small piece of gold; but all
the gold which is under or upon the earth is not enough to give in exchange
for virtue.  In a word, I may say that he who does not estimate the base
and evil, the good and noble, according to the standard of the legislator,
and abstain in every possible way from the one and practise the other to
the utmost of his power, does not know that in all these respects he is
most foully and disgracefully abusing his soul, which is the divinest part
of man; for no one, as I may say, ever considers that which is declared to
be the greatest penalty of evil-doing--namely, to grow into the likeness of
bad men, and growing like them to fly from the conversation of the good,
and be cut off from them, and cleave to and follow after the company of the
bad.  And he who is joined to them must do and suffer what such men by
nature do and say to one another,--a suffering which is not justice but
retribution; for justice and the just are noble, whereas retribution is the
suffering which waits upon injustice; and whether a man escape or endure
this, he is miserable,--in the former case, because he is not cured; while
in the latter, he perishes in order that the rest of mankind may be saved.

Speaking generally, our glory is to follow the better and improve the
inferior, which is susceptible of improvement, as far as this is possible. 
And of all human possessions, the soul is by nature most inclined to avoid
the evil, and track out and find the chief good; which when a man has
found, he should take up his abode with it during the remainder of his
life.  Wherefore the soul also is second (or next to God) in honour; and
third, as every one will perceive, comes the honour of the body in natural
order.  Having determined this, we have next to consider that there is a
natural honour of the body, and that of honours some are true and some are
counterfeit.  To decide which are which is the business of the legislator;
and he, I suspect, would intimate that they are as follows:--Honour is not
to be given to the fair body, or to the strong or the swift or the tall, or
to the healthy body (although many may think otherwise), any more than to
their opposites; but the mean states of all these habits are by far the
safest and most moderate; for the one extreme makes the soul braggart and
insolent, and the other, illiberal and base; and money, and property, and
distinction all go to the same tune.  The excess of any of these things is
apt to be a source of hatreds and divisions among states and individuals;
and the defect of them is commonly a cause of slavery.  And, therefore, I
would not have any one fond of heaping up riches for the sake of his
children, in order that he may leave them as rich as possible.  For the
possession of great wealth is of no use, either to them or to the state. 
The condition of youth which is free from flattery, and at the same time
not in need of the necessaries of life, is the best and most harmonious of
all, being in accord and agreement with our nature, and making life to be
most entirely free from sorrow.  Let parents, then, bequeath to their
children not a heap of riches, but the spirit of reverence.  We, indeed,
fancy that they will inherit reverence from us, if we rebuke them when they
show a want of reverence.  But this quality is not really imparted to them
by the present style of admonition, which only tells them that the young
ought always to be reverential.  A sensible legislator will rather exhort
the elders to reverence the younger, and above all to take heed that no
young man sees or hears one of themselves doing or saying anything
disgraceful; for where old men have no shame, there young men will most
certainly be devoid of reverence.  The best way of training the young is to
train yourself at the same time; not to admonish them, but to be always
carrying out your own admonitions in practice.  He who honours his kindred,
and reveres those who share in the same Gods and are of the same blood and
family, may fairly expect that the Gods who preside over generation will be
propitious to him, and will quicken his seed.  And he who deems the
services which his friends and acquaintances do for him, greater and more
important than they themselves deem them, and his own favours to them less
than theirs to him, will have their good-will in the intercourse of life. 
And surely in his relations to the state and his fellow citizens, he is by
far the best, who rather than the Olympic or any other victory of peace or
war, desires to win the palm of obedience to the laws of his country, and
who, of all mankind, is the person reputed to have obeyed them best through
life.  In his relations to strangers, a man should consider that a contract
is a most holy thing, and that all concerns and wrongs of strangers are
more directly dependent on the protection of God, than wrongs done to
citizens; for the stranger, having no kindred and friends, is more to be
pitied by Gods and men. Wherefore, also, he who is most able to avenge him
is most zealous in his cause; and he who is most able is the genius and the
god of the stranger, who follow in the train of Zeus, the god of strangers. 
And for this reason, he who has a spark of caution in him, will do his best
to pass through life without sinning against the stranger.  And of offences
committed, whether against strangers or fellow-countrymen, that against
suppliants is the greatest.  For the God who witnessed to the agreement
made with the suppliant, becomes in a special manner the guardian of the
sufferer; and he will certainly not suffer unavenged.

Thus we have fairly described the manner in which a man is to act about his
parents, and himself, and his own affairs; and in relation to the state,
and his friends, and kindred, both in what concerns his own countrymen, and
in what concerns the stranger.  We will now consider what manner of man he
must be who would best pass through life in respect of those other things
which are not matters of law, but of praise and blame only; in which praise
and blame educate a man, and make him more tractable and amenable to the
laws which are about to be imposed.

Truth is the beginning of every good thing, both to Gods and men; and he
who would be blessed and happy, should be from the first a partaker of the
truth, that he may live a true man as long as possible, for then he can be
trusted; but he is not to be trusted who loves voluntary falsehood, and he
who loves involuntary falsehood is a fool.  Neither condition is enviable,
for the untrustworthy and ignorant has no friend, and as time advances he
becomes known, and lays up in store for himself isolation in crabbed age
when life is on the wane:  so that, whether his children or friends are
alive or not, he is equally solitary.--Worthy of honour is he who does no
injustice, and of more than twofold honour, if he not only does no
injustice himself, but hinders others from doing any; the first may count
as one man, the second is worth many men, because he informs the rulers of
the injustice of others.  And yet more highly to be esteemed is he who co-
operates with the rulers in correcting the citizens as far as he can--he
shall be proclaimed the great and perfect citizen, and bear away the palm
of virtue.  The same praise may be given about temperance and wisdom, and
all other goods which may be imparted to others, as well as acquired by a
man for himself; he who imparts them shall be honoured as the man of men,
and he who is willing, yet is not able, may be allowed the second place;
but he who is jealous and will not, if he can help, allow others to partake
in a friendly way of any good, is deserving of blame:  the good, however,
which he has, is not to be undervalued by us because it is possessed by
him, but must be acquired by us also to the utmost of our power.  Let every
man, then, freely strive for the prize of virtue, and let there be no envy. 
For the unenvious nature increases the greatness of states--he himself
contends in the race, blasting the fair fame of no man; but the envious,
who thinks that he ought to get the better by defaming others, is less
energetic himself in the pursuit of true virtue, and reduces his rivals to
despair by his unjust slanders of them.  And so he makes the whole city to
enter the arena untrained in the practice of virtue, and diminishes her
glory as far as in him lies.  Now every man should be valiant, but he
should also be gentle.  From the cruel, or hardly curable, or altogether
incurable acts of injustice done to him by others, a man can only escape by
fighting and defending himself and conquering, and by never ceasing to
punish them; and no man who is not of a noble spirit is able to accomplish
this.  As to the actions of those who do evil, but whose evil is curable,
in the first place, let us remember that the unjust man is not unjust of
his own free will.  For no man of his own free will would choose to possess
the greatest of evils, and least of all in the most honourable part of
himself.  And the soul, as we said, is of a truth deemed by all men the
most honourable.  In the soul, then, which is the most honourable part of
him, no one, if he could help, would admit, or allow to continue the
greatest of evils (compare Republic).  The unrighteous and vicious are
always to be pitied in any case; and one can afford to forgive as well as
pity him who is curable, and refrain and calm one's anger, not getting into
a passion, like a woman, and nursing ill-feeling.  But upon him who is
incapable of reformation and wholly evil, the vials of our wrath should be
poured out; wherefore I say that good men ought, when occasion demands, to
be both gentle and passionate.

Of all evils the greatest is one which in the souls of most men is innate,
and which a man is always excusing in himself and never correcting; I mean,
what is expressed in the saying that 'Every man by nature is and ought to
be his own friend.'  Whereas the excessive love of self is in reality the
source to each man of all offences; for the lover is blinded about the
beloved, so that he judges wrongly of the just, the good, and the
honourable, and thinks that he ought always to prefer himself to the truth. 
But he who would be a great man ought to regard, not himself or his
interests, but what is just, whether the just act be his own or that of
another.  Through a similar error men are induced to fancy that their own
ignorance is wisdom, and thus we who may be truly said to know nothing,
think that we know all things; and because we will not let others act for
us in what we do not know, we are compelled to act amiss ourselves. 
Wherefore let every man avoid excess of self-love, and condescend to follow
a better man than himself, not allowing any false shame to stand in the
way.  There are also minor precepts which are often repeated, and are quite
as useful; a man should recollect them and remind himself of them.  For
when a stream is flowing out, there should be water flowing in too; and
recollection flows in while wisdom is departing.  Therefore I say that a
man should refrain from excess either of laughter or tears, and should
exhort his neighbour to do the same; he should veil his immoderate sorrow
or joy, and seek to behave with propriety, whether the genius of his good
fortune remains with him, or whether at the crisis of his fate, when he
seems to be mounting high and steep places, the Gods oppose him in some of
his enterprises.  Still he may ever hope, in the case of good men, that
whatever afflictions are to befall them in the future God will lessen, and
that present evils He will change for the better; and as to the goods which
are the opposite of these evils, he will not doubt that they will be added
to them, and that they will be fortunate.  Such should be men's hopes, and
such should be the exhortations with which they admonish one another, never
losing an opportunity, but on every occasion distinctly reminding
themselves and others of all these things, both in jest and earnest.

Enough has now been said of divine matters, both as touching the practices
which men ought to follow, and as to the sort of persons who they ought
severally to be.  But of human things we have not as yet spoken, and we
must; for to men we are discoursing and not to Gods.  Pleasures and pains
and desires are a part of human nature, and on them every mortal being must
of necessity hang and depend with the most eager interest.  And therefore
we must praise the noblest life, not only as the fairest in appearance, but
as being one which, if a man will only taste, and not, while still in his
youth, desert for another, he will find to surpass also in the very thing
which we all of us desire,--I mean in having a greater amount of pleasure
and less of pain during the whole of life.  And this will be plain, if a
man has a true taste of them, as will be quickly and clearly seen.  But
what is a true taste?  That we have to learn from the argument--the point
being what is according to nature, and what is not according to nature. 
One life must be compared with another, the more pleasurable with the more
painful, after this manner:--We desire to have pleasure, but we neither
desire nor choose pain; and the neutral state we are ready to take in
exchange, not for pleasure but for pain; and we also wish for less pain and
greater pleasure, but less pleasure and greater pain we do not wish for;
and an equal balance of either we cannot venture to assert that we should
desire.  And all these differ or do not differ severally in number and
magnitude and intensity and equality, and in the opposites of these when
regarded as objects of choice, in relation to desire.  And such being the
necessary order of things, we wish for that life in which there are many
great and intense elements of pleasure and pain, and in which the pleasures
are in excess, and do not wish for that in which the opposites exceed; nor,
again, do we wish for that in which the elements of either are small and
few and feeble, and the pains exceed.  And when, as I said before, there is
a balance of pleasure and pain in life, this is to be regarded by us as the
balanced life; while other lives are preferred by us because they exceed in
what we like, or are rejected by us because they exceed in what we dislike. 
All the lives of men may be regarded by us as bound up in these, and we
must also consider what sort of lives we by nature desire.  And if we wish
for any others, I say that we desire them only through some ignorance and
inexperience of the lives which actually exist.

Now, what lives are they, and how many in which, having searched out and
beheld the objects of will and desire and their opposites, and making of
them a law, choosing, I say, the dear and the pleasant and the best and
noblest, a man may live in the happiest way possible?  Let us say that the
temperate life is one kind of life, and the rational another, and the
courageous another, and the healthful another; and to these four let us
oppose four other lives--the foolish, the cowardly, the intemperate, the
diseased.  He who knows the temperate life will describe it as in all
things gentle, having gentle pains and gentle pleasures, and placid desires
and loves not insane; whereas the intemperate life is impetuous in all
things, and has violent pains and pleasures, and vehement and stinging
desires, and loves utterly insane; and in the temperate life the pleasures
exceed the pains, but in the intemperate life the pains exceed the
pleasures in greatness and number and frequency.  Hence one of the two
lives is naturally and necessarily more pleasant and the other more
painful, and he who would live pleasantly cannot possibly choose to live
intemperately.  And if this is true, the inference clearly is that no man
is voluntarily intemperate; but that the whole multitude of men lack
temperance in their lives, either from ignorance, or from want of self-
control, or both.  And the same holds of the diseased and healthy life;
they both have pleasures and pains, but in health the pleasure exceeds the
pain, and in sickness the pain exceeds the pleasure.  Now our intention in
choosing the lives is not that the painful should exceed, but the life in
which pain is exceeded by pleasure we have determined to be the more
pleasant life.  And we should say that the temperate life has the elements
both of pleasure and pain fewer and smaller and less frequent than the
intemperate, and the wise life than the foolish life, and the life of
courage than the life of cowardice; one of each pair exceeding in pleasure
and the other in pain, the courageous surpassing the cowardly, and the wise
exceeding the foolish.  And so the one class of lives exceeds the other
class in pleasure; the temperate and courageous and wise and healthy exceed
the cowardly and foolish and intemperate and diseased lives; and generally
speaking, that which has any virtue, whether of body or soul, is pleasanter
than the vicious life, and far superior in beauty and rectitude and
excellence and reputation, and causes him who lives accordingly to be
infinitely happier than the opposite.

Enough of the preamble; and now the laws should follow; or, to speak more
correctly, an outline of them.  As, then, in the case of a web or any other
tissue, the warp and the woof cannot be made of the same materials (compare
Statesman), but the warp is necessarily superior as being stronger, and
having a certain character of firmness, whereas the woof is softer and has
a proper degree of elasticity;--in a similar manner those who are to hold
great offices in states, should be distinguished truly in each case from
those who have been but slenderly proven by education.  Let us suppose that
there are two parts in the constitution of a state--one the creation of
offices, the other the laws which are assigned to them to administer.

But, before all this, comes the following consideration:--The shepherd or
herdsman, or breeder of horses or the like, when he has received his
animals will not begin to train them until he has first purified them in a
manner which befits a community of animals; he will divide the healthy and
unhealthy, and the good breed and the bad breed, and will send away the
unhealthy and badly bred to other herds, and tend the rest, reflecting that
his labours will be vain and have no effect, either on the souls or bodies
of those whom nature and ill nurture have corrupted, and that they will
involve in destruction the pure and healthy nature and being of every other
animal, if he should neglect to purify them.  Now the case of other animals
is not so important--they are only worth introducing for the sake of
illustration; but what relates to man is of the highest importance; and the
legislator should make enquiries, and indicate what is proper for each one
in the way of purification and of any other procedure.  Take, for example,
the purification of a city--there are many kinds of purification, some
easier and others more difficult; and some of them, and the best and most
difficult of them, the legislator, if he be also a despot, may be able to
effect; but the legislator, who, not being a despot, sets up a new
government and laws, even if he attempt the mildest of purgations, may
think himself happy if he can complete his work.  The best kind of
purification is painful, like similar cures in medicine, involving
righteous punishment and inflicting death or exile in the last resort.  For
in this way we commonly dispose of great sinners who are incurable, and are
the greatest injury of the whole state.  But the milder form of
purification is as follows:--when men who have nothing, and are in want of
food, show a disposition to follow their leaders in an attack on the
property of the rich--these, who are the natural plague of the state, are
sent away by the legislator in a friendly spirit as far as he is able; and
this dismissal of them is euphemistically termed a colony.  And every
legislator should contrive to do this at once.  Our present case, however,
is peculiar.  For there is no need to devise any colony or purifying
separation under the circumstances in which we are placed.  But as, when
many streams flow together from many sources, whether springs or mountain
torrents, into a single lake, we ought to attend and take care that the
confluent waters should be perfectly clear, and in order to effect this,
should pump and draw off and divert impurities, so in every political
arrangement there may be trouble and danger.  But, seeing that we are now
only discoursing and not acting, let our selection be supposed to be
completed, and the desired purity attained.  Touching evil men, who want to
join and be citizens of our state, after we have tested them by every sort
of persuasion and for a sufficient time, we will prevent them from coming;
but the good we will to the utmost of our ability receive as friends with
open arms.

Another piece of good fortune must not be forgotten, which, as we were
saying, the Heraclid colony had, and which is also ours,--that we have
escaped division of land and the abolition of debts; for these are always a
source of dangerous contention, and a city which is driven by necessity to
legislate upon such matters can neither allow the old ways to continue, nor
yet venture to alter them.  We must have recourse to prayers, so to speak,
and hope that a slight change may be cautiously effected in a length of
time.  And such a change can be accomplished by those who have abundance of
land, and having also many debtors, are willing, in a kindly spirit, to
share with those who are in want, sometimes remitting and sometimes giving,
holding fast in a path of moderation, and deeming poverty to be the
increase of a man's desires and not the diminution of his property.  For
this is the great beginning of salvation to a state, and upon this lasting
basis may be erected afterwards whatever political order is suitable under
the circumstances; but if the change be based upon an unsound principle,
the future administration of the country will be full of difficulties. 
That is a danger which, as I am saying, is escaped by us, and yet we had
better say how, if we had not escaped, we might have escaped; and we may
venture now to assert that no other way of escape, whether narrow or broad,
can be devised but freedom from avarice and a sense of justice--upon this
rock our city shall be built; for there ought to be no disputes among
citizens about property.  If there are quarrels of long standing among
them, no legislator of any degree of sense will proceed a step in the
arrangement of the state until they are settled.  But that they to whom God
has given, as He has to us, to be the founders of a new state as yet free
from enmity--that they should create themselves enmities by their mode of
distributing lands and houses, would be superhuman folly and wickedness.

How then can we rightly order the distribution of the land?  In the first
place, the number of the citizens has to be determined, and also the number
and size of the divisions into which they will have to be formed; and the
land and the houses will then have to be apportioned by us as fairly as we
can.  The number of citizens can only be estimated satisfactorily in
relation to the territory and the neighbouring states.  The territory must
be sufficient to maintain a certain number of inhabitants in a moderate way
of life--more than this is not required; and the number of citizens should
be sufficient to defend themselves against the injustice of their
neighbours, and also to give them the power of rendering efficient aid to
their neighbours when they are wronged.  After having taken a survey of
their's and their neighbours' territory, we will determine the limits of
them in fact as well as in theory.  And now, let us proceed to legislate
with a view to perfecting the form and outline of our state.  The number of
our citizens shall be 5040--this will be a convenient number; and these
shall be owners of the land and protectors of the allotment.  The houses
and the land will be divided in the same way, so that every man may
correspond to a lot.  Let the whole number be first divided into two parts,
and then into three; and the number is further capable of being divided
into four or five parts, or any number of parts up to ten.  Every
legislator ought to know so much arithmetic as to be able to tell what
number is most likely to be useful to all cities; and we are going to take
that number which contains the greatest and most regular and unbroken
series of divisions.  The whole of number has every possible division, and
the number 5040 can be divided by exactly fifty-nine divisors, and ten of
these proceed without interval from one to ten:  this will furnish numbers
for war and peace, and for all contracts and dealings, including taxes and
divisions of the land.  These properties of number should be ascertained at
leisure by those who are bound by law to know them; for they are true, and
should be proclaimed at the foundation of the city, with a view to use. 
Whether the legislator is establishing a new state or restoring an old and
decayed one, in respect of Gods and temples,--the temples which are to be
built in each city, and the Gods or demi-gods after whom they are to be
called,--if he be a man of sense, he will make no change in anything which
the oracle of Delphi, or Dodona, or the God Ammon, or any ancient tradition
has sanctioned in whatever manner, whether by apparitions or reputed
inspiration of Heaven, in obedience to which mankind have established
sacrifices in connexion with mystic rites, either originating on the spot,
or derived from Tyrrhenia or Cyprus or some other place, and on the
strength of which traditions they have consecrated oracles and images, and
altars and temples, and portioned out a sacred domain for each of them. 
The least part of all these ought not to be disturbed by the legislator;
but he should assign to the several districts some God, or demi-god, or
hero, and, in the distribution of the soil, should give to these first
their chosen domain and all things fitting, that the inhabitants of the
several districts may meet at fixed times, and that they may readily supply
their various wants, and entertain one another with sacrifices, and become
friends and acquaintances; for there is no greater good in a state than
that the citizens should be known to one another.  When not light but
darkness and ignorance of each other's characters prevails among them, no
one will receive the honour of which he is deserving, or the power or the
justice to which he is fairly entitled:  wherefore, in every state, above
all things, every man should take heed that he have no deceit in him, but
that he be always true and simple; and that no deceitful person take any
advantage of him.

The next move in our pastime of legislation, like the withdrawal of the
stone from the holy line in the game of draughts, being an unusual one,
will probably excite wonder when mentioned for the first time.  And yet, if
a man will only reflect and weigh the matter with care, he will see that
our city is ordered in a manner which, if not the best, is the second best. 
Perhaps also some one may not approve this form, because he thinks that
such a constitution is ill adapted to a legislator who has not despotic
power.  The truth is, that there are three forms of government, the best,
the second and the third best, which we may just mention, and then leave
the selection to the ruler of the settlement.  Following this method in the
present instance, let us speak of the states which are respectively first,
second, and third in excellence, and then we will leave the choice to
Cleinias now, or to any one else who may hereafter have to make a similar
choice among constitutions, and may desire to give to his state some
feature which is congenial to him and which he approves in his own country.

The first and highest form of the state and of the government and of the
law is that in which there prevails most widely the ancient saying, that
'Friends have all things in common.'  Whether there is anywhere now, or
will ever be, this communion of women and children and of property, in
which the private and individual is altogether banished from life, and
things which are by nature private, such as eyes and ears and hands, have
become common, and in some way see and hear and act in common, and all men
express praise and blame and feel joy and sorrow on the same occasions, and
whatever laws there are unite the city to the utmost (compare Republic),--
whether all this is possible or not, I say that no man, acting upon any
other principle, will ever constitute a state which will be truer or better
or more exalted in virtue.  Whether such a state is governed by Gods or
sons of Gods, one, or more than one, happy are the men who, living after
this manner, dwell there; and therefore to this we are to look for the
pattern of the state, and to cling to this, and to seek with all our might
for one which is like this.  The state which we have now in hand, when
created, will be nearest to immortality and the only one which takes the
second place; and after that, by the grace of God, we will complete the
third one.  And we will begin by speaking of the nature and origin of the
second.

Let the citizens at once distribute their land and houses, and not till the
land in common, since a community of goods goes beyond their proposed
origin, and nurture, and education.  But in making the distribution, let
the several possessors feel that their particular lots also belong to the
whole city; and seeing that the earth is their parent, let them tend her
more carefully than children do their mother.  For she is a goddess and
their queen, and they are her mortal subjects.  Such also are the feelings
which they ought to entertain to the Gods and demi-gods of the country. 
And in order that the distribution may always remain, they ought to
consider further that the present number of families should be always
retained, and neither increased nor diminished.  This may be secured for
the whole city in the following manner:--Let the possessor of a lot leave
the one of his children who is his best beloved, and one only, to be the
heir of his dwelling, and his successor in the duty of ministering to the
Gods, the state and the family, as well the living members of it as those
who are departed when he comes into the inheritance; but of his other
children, if he have more than one, he shall give the females in marriage
according to the law to be hereafter enacted, and the males he shall
distribute as sons to those citizens who have no children, and are disposed
to receive them; or if there should be none such, and particular
individuals have too many children, male or female, or too few, as in the
case of barrenness--in all these cases let the highest and most honourable
magistracy created by us judge and determine what is to be done with the
redundant or deficient, and devise a means that the number of 5040 houses
shall always remain the same.  There are many ways of regulating numbers;
for they in whom generation is affluent may be made to refrain (compare
Arist. Pol.), and, on the other hand, special care may be taken to increase
the number of births by rewards and stigmas, or we may meet the evil by the
elder men giving advice and administering rebuke to the younger--in this
way the object may be attained.  And if after all there be very great
difficulty about the equal preservation of the 5040 houses, and there be an
excess of citizens, owing to the too great love of those who live together,
and we are at our wits' end, there is still the old device often mentioned
by us of sending out a colony, which will part friends with us, and be
composed of suitable persons.  If, on the other hand, there come a wave
bearing a deluge of disease, or a plague of war, and the inhabitants become
much fewer than the appointed number by reason of bereavement, we ought not
to introduce citizens of spurious birth and education, if this can be
avoided; but even God is said not to be able to fight against necessity.

Wherefore let us suppose this 'high argument' of ours to address us in the
following terms:--Best of men, cease not to honour according to nature
similarity and equality and sameness and agreement, as regards number and
every good and noble quality.  And, above all, observe the aforesaid number
5040 throughout life; in the second place, do not disparage the small and
modest proportions of the inheritances which you received in the
distribution, by buying and selling them to one another.  For then neither
will the God who gave you the lot be your friend, nor will the legislator;
and indeed the law declares to the disobedient that these are the terms
upon which he may or may not take the lot.  In the first place, the earth
as he is informed is sacred to the Gods; and in the next place, priests and
priestesses will offer up prayers over a first, and second, and even a
third sacrifice, that he who buys or sells the houses or lands which he has
received, may suffer the punishment which he deserves; and these their
prayers they shall write down in the temples, on tablets of cypress-wood,
for the instruction of posterity.  Moreover they will set a watch over all
these things, that they may be observed;--the magistracy which has the
sharpest eyes shall keep watch that any infringement of these commands may
be discovered and punished as offences both against the law and the God. 
How great is the benefit of such an ordinance to all those cities, which
obey and are administered accordingly, no bad man can ever know, as the old
proverb says; but only a man of experience and good habits.  For in such an
order of things there will not be much opportunity for making money; no man
either ought, or indeed will be allowed, to exercise any ignoble
occupation, of which the vulgarity is a matter of reproach to a freeman,
and should never want to acquire riches by any such means.

Further, the law enjoins that no private man shall be allowed to possess
gold and silver, but only coin for daily use, which is almost necessary in
dealing with artisans, and for payment of hirelings, whether slaves or
immigrants, by all those persons who require the use of them.  Wherefore
our citizens, as we say, should have a coin passing current among
themselves, but not accepted among the rest of mankind; with a view,
however, to expeditions and journeys to other lands,--for embassies, or for
any other occasion which may arise of sending out a herald, the state must
also possess a common Hellenic currency.  If a private person is ever
obliged to go abroad, let him have the consent of the magistrates and go;
and if when he returns he has any foreign money remaining, let him give the
surplus back to the treasury, and receive a corresponding sum in the local
currency.  And if he is discovered to appropriate it, let it be
confiscated, and let him who knows and does not inform be subject to curse
and dishonour equally him who brought the money, and also to a fine not
less in amount than the foreign money which has been brought back.  In
marrying and giving in marriage, no one shall give or receive any dowry at
all; and no one shall deposit money with another whom he does not trust as
a friend, nor shall he lend money upon interest; and the borrower should be
under no obligation to repay either capital or interest.  That these
principles are best, any one may see who compares them with the first
principle and intention of a state.  The intention, as we affirm, of a
reasonable statesman, is not what the many declare to be the object of a
good legislator, namely, that the state for the true interests of which he
is advising should be as great and as rich as possible, and should possess
gold and silver, and have the greatest empire by sea and land;--this they
imagine to be the real object of legislation, at the same time adding,
inconsistently, that the true legislator desires to have the city the best
and happiest possible.  But they do not see that some of these things are
possible, and some of them are impossible; and he who orders the state will
desire what is possible, and will not indulge in vain wishes or attempts to
accomplish that which is impossible.  The citizen must indeed be happy and
good, and the legislator will seek to make him so; but very rich and very
good at the same time he cannot be, not, at least, in the sense in which
the many speak of riches.  For they mean by 'the rich' the few who have the
most valuable possessions, although the owner of them may quite well be a
rogue.  And if this is true, I can never assent to the doctrine that the
rich man will be happy--he must be good as well as rich.  And good in a
high degree, and rich in a high degree at the same time, he cannot be. 
Some one will ask, why not?  And we shall answer--Because acquisitions
which come from sources which are just and unjust indifferently, are more
than double those which come from just sources only; and the sums which are
expended neither honourably nor disgracefully, are only half as great as
those which are expended honourably and on honourable purposes.  Thus, if
the one acquires double and spends half, the other who is in the opposite
case and is a good man cannot possibly be wealthier than he.  The first--I
am speaking of the saver and not of the spender--is not always bad; he may
indeed in some cases be utterly bad, but, as I was saying, a good man he
never is.  For he who receives money unjustly as well as justly, and spends
neither nor unjustly, will be a rich man if he be also thrifty.  On the
other hand, the utterly bad is in general profligate, and therefore very
poor; while he who spends on noble objects, and acquires wealth by just
means only, can hardly be remarkable for riches, any more than he can be
very poor.  Our statement, then, is true, that the very rich are not good,
and, if they are not good, they are not happy.  But the intention of our
laws was, that the citizens should be as happy as may be, and as friendly
as possible to one another.  And men who are always at law with one
another, and amongst whom there are many wrongs done, can never be friends
to one another, but only those among whom crimes and lawsuits are few and
slight.  Therefore we say that gold and silver ought not to be allowed in
the city, nor much of the vulgar sort of trade which is carried on by
lending money, or rearing the meaner kinds of live stock; but only the
produce of agriculture, and only so much of this as will not compel us in
pursuing it to neglect that for the sake of which riches exist--I mean,
soul and body, which without gymnastics, and without education, will never
be worth anything; and therefore, as we have said not once but many times,
the care of riches should have the last place in our thoughts.  For there
are in all three things about which every man has an interest; and the
interest about money, when rightly regarded, is the third and lowest of
them:  midway comes the interest of the body; and, first of all, that of
the soul; and the state which we are describing will have been rightly
constituted if it ordains honours according to this scale.  But if, in any
of the laws which have been ordained, health has been preferred to
temperance, or wealth to health and temperate habits, that law must clearly
be wrong.  Wherefore, also, the legislator ought often to impress upon
himself the question--'What do I want?' and 'Do I attain my aim, or do I
miss the mark?'  In this way, and in this way only, he may acquit himself
and free others from the work of legislation.

Let the allottee then hold his lot upon the conditions which we have
mentioned.

It would be well that every man should come to the colony having all things
equal; but seeing that this is not possible, and one man will have greater
possessions than another, for many reasons and in particular in order to
preserve equality in special crises of the state, qualifications of
property must be unequal, in order that offices and contributions and
distributions may be proportioned to the value of each person's wealth, and
not solely to the virtue of his ancestors or himself, nor yet to the
strength and beauty of his person, but also to the measure of his wealth or
poverty; and so by a law of inequality, which will be in proportion to his
wealth, he will receive honours and offices as equally as possible, and
there will be no quarrels and disputes.  To which end there should be four
different standards appointed according to the amount of property:  there
should be a first and a second and a third and a fourth class, in which the
citizens will be placed, and they will be called by these or similar names: 
they may continue in the same rank, or pass into another in any individual
case, on becoming richer from being poorer, or poorer from being richer. 
The form of law which I should propose as the natural sequel would be as
follows:--In a state which is desirous of being saved from the greatest of
all plagues--not faction, but rather distraction;--there should exist among
the citizens neither extreme poverty, nor, again, excess of wealth, for
both are productive of both these evils.  Now the legislator should
determine what is to be the limit of poverty or wealth.  Let the limit of
poverty be the value of the lot; this ought to be preserved, and no ruler,
nor any one else who aspires after a reputation for virtue, will allow the
lot to be impaired in any case.  This the legislator gives as a measure,
and he will permit a man to acquire double or triple, or as much as four
times the amount of this (compare Arist. Pol.).  But if a person have yet
greater riches, whether he has found them, or they have been given to him,
or he has made them in business, or has acquired by any stroke of fortune
that which is in excess of the measure, if he give back the surplus to the
state, and to the Gods who are the patrons of the state, he shall suffer no
penalty or loss of reputation; but if he disobeys this our law, any one who
likes may inform against him and receive half the value of the excess, and
the delinquent shall pay a sum equal to the excess out of his own property,
and the other half of the excess shall belong to the Gods.  And let every
possession of every man, with the exception of the lot, be publicly
registered before the magistrates whom the law appoints, so that all suits
about money may be easy and quite simple.

The next thing to be noted is, that the city should be placed as nearly as
possible in the centre of the country; we should choose a place which
possesses what is suitable for a city, and this may easily be imagined and
described.  Then we will divide the city into twelve portions, first
founding temples to Hestia, to Zeus and to Athene, in a spot which we will
call the Acropolis, and surround with a circular wall, making the division
of the entire city and country radiate from this point.  The twelve
portions shall be equalized by the provision that those which are of good
land shall be smaller, while those of inferior quality shall be larger. 
The number of the lots shall be 5040, and each of them shall be divided
into two, and every allotment shall be composed of two such sections; one
of land near the city, the other of land which is at a distance (compare
Arist. Pol.).  This arrangement shall be carried out in the following
manner:  The section which is near the city shall be added to that which is
on the borders, and form one lot, and the portion which is next nearest
shall be added to the portion which is next farthest; and so of the rest. 
Moreover, in the two sections of the lots the same principle of
equalization of the soil ought to be maintained; the badness and goodness
shall be compensated by more and less.  And the legislator shall divide the
citizens into twelve parts, and arrange the rest of their property, as far
as possible, so as to form twelve equal parts; and there shall be a
registration of all.  After this they shall assign twelve lots to twelve
Gods, and call them by their names, and dedicate to each God their several
portions, and call the tribes after them.  And they shall distribute the
twelve divisions of the city in the same way in which they divided the
country; and every man shall have two habitations, one in the centre of the
country, and the other at the extremity.  Enough of the manner of
settlement.

Now we ought by all means to consider that there can never be such a happy
concurrence of circumstances as we have described; neither can all things
coincide as they are wanted.  Men who will not take offence at such a mode
of living together, and will endure all their life long to have their
property fixed at a moderate limit, and to beget children in accordance
with our ordinances, and will allow themselves to be deprived of gold and
other things which the legislator, as is evident from these enactments,
will certainly forbid them; and will endure, further, the situation of the
land with the city in the middle and dwellings round about;--all this is as
if the legislator were telling his dreams, or making a city and citizens of
wax.  There is truth in these objections, and therefore every one should
take to heart what I am going to say.  Once more, then, the legislator
shall appear and address us:--'O my friends,' he will say to us, 'do not
suppose me ignorant that there is a certain degree of truth in your words;
but I am of opinion that, in matters which are not present but future, he
who exhibits a pattern of that at which he aims, should in nothing fall
short of the fairest and truest; and that if he finds any part of this work
impossible of execution he should avoid and not execute it, but he should
contrive to carry out that which is nearest and most akin to it; you must
allow the legislator to perfect his design, and when it is perfected, you
should join with him in considering what part of his legislation is
expedient and what will arouse opposition; for surely the artist who is to
be deemed worthy of any regard at all, ought always to make his work self-
consistent.'

Having determined that there is to be a distribution into twelve parts, let
us now see in what way this may be accomplished.  There is no difficulty in
perceiving that the twelve parts admit of the greatest number of divisions
of that which they include, or in seeing the other numbers which are
consequent upon them, and are produced out of them up to 5040; wherefore
the law ought to order phratries and demes and villages, and also military
ranks and movements, as well as coins and measures, dry and liquid, and
weights, so as to be commensurable and agreeable to one another.  Nor
should we fear the appearance of minuteness, if the law commands that all
the vessels which a man possesses should have a common measure, when we
consider generally that the divisions and variations of numbers have a use
in respect of all the variations of which they are susceptible, both in
themselves and as measures of height and depth, and in all sounds, and in
motions, as well those which proceed in a straight direction, upwards or
downwards, as in those which go round and round.  The legislator is to
consider all these things and to bid the citizens, as far as possible, not
to lose sight of numerical order; for no single instrument of youthful
education has such mighty power, both as regards domestic economy and
politics, and in the arts, as the study of arithmetic.  Above all,
arithmetic stirs up him who is by nature sleepy and dull, and makes him
quick to learn, retentive, shrewd, and aided by art divine he makes
progress quite beyond his natural powers (compare Republic).  All such
things, if only the legislator, by other laws and institutions, can banish
meanness and covetousness from the souls of men, so that they can use them
properly and to their own good, will be excellent and suitable instruments
of education.  But if he cannot, he will unintentionally create in them,
instead of wisdom, the habit of craft, which evil tendency may be observed
in the Egyptians and Phoenicians, and many other races, through the general
vulgarity of their pursuits and acquisitions, whether some unworthy
legislator of theirs has been the cause, or some impediment of chance or
nature.  For we must not fail to observe, O Megillus and Cleinias, that
there is a difference in places, and that some beget better men and others
worse; and we must legislate accordingly.  Some places are subject to
strange and fatal influences by reason of diverse winds and violent heats,
some by reason of waters; or, again, from the character of the food given
by the earth, which not only affects the bodies of men for good or evil,
but produces similar results in their souls.  And in all such qualities
those spots excel in which there is a divine inspiration, and in which the
demigods have their appointed lots, and are propitious, not adverse, to the
settlers in them.  To all these matters the legislator, if he have any
sense in him, will attend as far as man can, and frame his laws
accordingly.  And this is what you, Cleinias, must do, and to matters of
this kind you must turn your mind since you are going to colonize a new
country.

CLEINIAS:  Your words, Athenian Stranger, are excellent, and I will do as
you say.


BOOK VI.

ATHENIAN:  And now having made an end of the preliminaries we will proceed
to the appointment of magistracies.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  In the ordering of a state there are two parts:  first, the
number of the magistracies, and the mode of establishing them; and,
secondly, when they have been established, laws again will have to be
provided for each of them, suitable in nature and number.  But before
electing the magistrates let us stop a little and say a word in season
about the election of them.

CLEINIAS:  What have you got to say?

ATHENIAN:  This is what I have to say;--every one can see, that although
the work of legislation is a most important matter, yet if a well-ordered
city superadd to good laws unsuitable offices, not only will there be no
use in having the good laws,--not only will they be ridiculous and useless,
but the greatest political injury and evil will accrue from them.

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  Then now, my friend, let us observe what will happen in the
constitution of out intended state.  In the first place, you will
acknowledge that those who are duly appointed to magisterial power, and
their families, should severally have given satisfactory proof of what they
are, from youth upward until the time of election; in the next place, those
who are to elect should have been trained in habits of law, and be well
educated, that they may have a right judgment, and may be able to select or
reject men whom they approve or disapprove, as they are worthy of either. 
But how can we imagine that those who are brought together for the first
time, and are strangers to one another, and also uneducated, will avoid
making mistakes in the choice of magistrates?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  The matter is serious, and excuses will not serve the turn.  I
will tell you, then, what you and I will have to do, since you, as you tell
me, with nine others, have offered to settle the new state on behalf of the
people of Crete, and I am to help you by the invention of the present
romance.  I certainly should not like to leave the tale wandering all over
the world without a head;--a headless monster is such a hideous thing.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and I will be as good as my word.

CLEINIAS:  Let us by all means do as you propose.

ATHENIAN:  That we will, by the grace of God, if old age will only permit
us.

CLEINIAS:  But God will be gracious.

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and under his guidance let us consider a further point.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  Let us remember what a courageously mad and daring creation this
our city is.

CLEINIAS:  What had you in your mind when you said that?

ATHENIAN:  I had in my mind the free and easy manner in which we are
ordaining that the inexperienced colonists shall receive our laws.  Now a
man need not be very wise, Cleinias, in order to see that no one can easily
receive laws at their first imposition.  But if we could anyhow wait until
those who have been imbued with them from childhood, and have been nurtured
in them, and become habituated to them, take their part in the public
elections of the state; I say, if this could be accomplished, and rightly
accomplished by any way or contrivance--then, I think that there would be
very little danger, at the end of the time, of a state thus trained not
being permanent.

CLEINIAS:  A reasonable supposition.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us consider if we can find any way out of the
difficulty; for I maintain, Cleinias, that the Cnosians, above all the
other Cretans, should not be satisfied with barely discharging their duty
to the colony, but they ought to take the utmost pains to establish the
offices which are first created by them in the best and surest manner. 
Above all, this applies to the selection of the guardians of the law, who
must be chosen first of all, and with the greatest care; the others are of
less importance.

CLEINIAS:  What method can we devise of electing them?

ATHENIAN:  This will be the method:--Sons of the Cretans, I shall say to
them, inasmuch as the Cnosians have precedence over the other states, they
should, in common with those who join this settlement, choose a body of
thirty-seven in all, nineteen of them being taken from the settlers, and
the remainder from the citizens of Cnosus.  Of these latter the Cnosians
shall make a present to your colony, and you yourself shall be one of the
eighteen, and shall become a citizen of the new state; and if you and they
cannot be persuaded to go, the Cnosians may fairly use a little violence in
order to make you.

CLEINIAS:  But why, Stranger, do not you and Megillus take a part in our
new city?

ATHENIAN:  O, Cleinias, Athens is proud, and Sparta too; and they are both
a long way off.  But you and likewise the other colonists are conveniently
situated as you describe.  I have been speaking of the way in which the new
citizens may be best managed under present circumstances; but in after-
ages, if the city continues to exist, let the election be on this wise. 
All who are horse or foot soldiers, or have seen military service at the
proper ages when they were severally fitted for it (compare Arist. Pol.),
shall share in the election of magistrates; and the election shall be held
in whatever temple the state deems most venerable, and every one shall
carry his vote to the altar of the God, writing down on a tablet the name
of the person for whom he votes, and his father's name, and his tribe, and
ward; and at the side he shall write his own name in like manner.  Any one
who pleases may take away any tablet which he does not think properly
filled up, and exhibit it in the Agora for a period of not less than thirty
days.  The tablets which are judged to be first, to the number of 300,
shall be shown by the magistrates to the whole city, and the citizens shall
in like manner select from these the candidates whom they prefer; and this
second selection, to the number of 100, shall be again exhibited to the
citizens; in the third, let any one who pleases select whom he pleases out
of the 100, walking through the parts of victims, and let them choose for
magistrates and proclaim the seven-and-thirty who have the greatest number
of votes.  But who, Cleinias and Megillus, will order for us in the colony
all this matter of the magistrates, and the scrutinies of them?  If we
reflect, we shall see that cities which are in process of construction like
ours must have some such persons, who cannot possibly be elected before
there are any magistrates; and yet they must be elected in some way, and
they are not to be inferior men, but the best possible.  For as the proverb
says, 'a good beginning is half the business'; and 'to have begun well' is
praised by all, and in my opinion is a great deal more than half the
business, and has never been praised by any one enough.

CLEINIAS:  That is very true.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us recognize the difficulty, and make clear to our own
minds how the beginning is to be accomplished.  There is only one proposal
which I have to offer, and that is one which, under our circumstances, is
both necessary and expedient.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  I maintain that this colony of ours has a father and mother, who
are no other than the colonizing state.  Well I know that many colonies
have been, and will be, at enmity with their parents.  But in early days
the child, as in a family, loves and is beloved; even if there come a time
later when the tie is broken, still, while he is in want of education, he
naturally loves his parents and is beloved by them, and flies to his
relatives for protection, and finds in them his only natural allies in time
of need; and this parental feeling already exists in the Cnosians, as is
shown by their care of the new city; and there is a similar feeling on the
part of the young city towards Cnosus.  And I repeat what I was saying--for
there is no harm in repeating a good thing--that the Cnosians should take a
common interest in all these matters, and choose, as far as they can, the
eldest and best of the colonists, to the number of not less than a hundred;
and let there be another hundred of the Cnosians themselves.  These, I say,
on their arrival, should have a joint care that the magistrates should be
appointed according to law, and that when they are appointed they should
undergo a scrutiny.  When this has been effected, the Cnosians shall return
home, and the new city do the best she can for her own preservation and
happiness.  I would have the seven-and-thirty now, and in all future time,
chosen to fulfil the following duties:--Let them, in the first place, be
the guardians of the law; and, secondly, of the registers in which each one
registers before the magistrate the amount of his property, excepting four
minae which are allowed to citizens of the first class, three allowed to
the second, two to the third, and a single mina to the fourth.  And if any
one, despising the laws for the sake of gain, be found to possess anything
more which has not been registered, let all that he has in excess be
confiscated, and let him be liable to a suit which shall be the reverse of
honourable or fortunate.  And let any one who will, indict him on the
charge of loving base gains, and proceed against him before the guardians
of the law.  And if he be cast, let him lose his share of the public
possessions, and when there is any public distribution, let him have
nothing but his original lot; and let him be written down a condemned man
as long as he lives, in some place in which any one who pleases can read
about his offences.  The guardian of the law shall not hold office longer
than twenty years, and shall not be less than fifty years of age when he is
elected; or if he is elected when he is sixty years of age, he shall hold
office for ten years only; and upon the same principle, he must not imagine
that he will be permitted to hold such an important office as that of
guardian of the laws after he is seventy years of age, if he live so long.

These are the three first ordinances about the guardians of the law; as the
work of legislation progresses, each law in turn will assign to them their
further duties.  And now we may proceed in order to speak of the election
of other officers; for generals have to be elected, and these again must
have their ministers, commanders, and colonels of horse, and commanders of
brigades of foot, who would be more rightly called by their popular name of
brigadiers.  The guardians of the law shall propose as generals men who are
natives of the city, and a selection from the candidates proposed shall be
made by those who are or have been of the age for military service.  And if
one who is not proposed is thought by somebody to be better than one who
is, let him name whom he prefers in the place of whom, and make oath that
he is better, and propose him; and whichever of them is approved by vote
shall be admitted to the final selection; and the three who have the
greatest number of votes shall be appointed generals, and superintendents
of military affairs, after previously undergoing a scrutiny, like the
guardians of the law.  And let the generals thus elected propose twelve
brigadiers, one for each tribe; and there shall be a right of counter-
proposal as in the case of the generals, and the voting and decision shall
take place in the same way.  Until the prytanes and council are elected,
the guardians of the law shall convene the assembly in some holy spot which
is suitable to the purpose, placing the hoplites by themselves, and the
cavalry by themselves, and in a third division all the rest of the army. 
All are to vote for the generals (and for the colonels of horse), but the
brigadiers are to be voted for only by those who carry shields (i.e. the
hoplites).  Let the body of cavalry choose phylarchs for the generals; but
captains of light troops, or archers, or any other division of the army,
shall be appointed by the generals for themselves.  There only remains the
appointment of officers of cavalry:  these shall be proposed by the same
persons who proposed the generals, and the election and the counter-
proposal of other candidates shall be arranged in the same way as in the
case of the generals, and let the cavalry vote and the infantry look on at
the election; the two who have the greatest number of votes shall be the
leaders of all the horse.  Disputes about the voting may be raised once or
twice; but if the dispute be raised a third time, the officers who preside
at the several elections shall decide.

The council shall consist of 30 x 12 members--360 will be a convenient
number for sub-division.  If we divide the whole number into four parts of
ninety each, we get ninety counsellors for each class.  First, all the
citizens shall select candidates from the first class; they shall be
compelled to vote, and, if they do not, shall be duly fined.  When the
candidates have been selected, some one shall mark them down; this shall be
the business of the first day.  And on the following day, candidates shall
be selected from the second class in the same manner and under the same
conditions as on the previous day; and on the third day a selection shall
be made from the third class, at which every one may, if he likes vote, and
the three first classes shall be compelled to vote; but the fourth and
lowest class shall be under no compulsion, and any member of this class who
does not vote shall not be punished.  On the fourth day candidates shall be
selected from the fourth and smallest class; they shall be selected by all,
but he who is of the fourth class shall suffer no penalty, nor he who is of
the third, if he be not willing to vote; but he who is of the first or
second class, if he does not vote shall be punished;--he who is of the
second class shall pay a fine of triple the amount which was exacted at
first, and he who is of the first class quadruple.  On the fifth day the
rulers shall bring out the names noted down, for all the citizens to see,
and every man shall choose out of them, under pain, if he do not, of
suffering the first penalty; and when they have chosen 180 out of each of
the classes, they shall choose one-half of them by lot, who shall undergo a
scrutiny:--These are to form the council for the year.

The mode of election which has been described is in a mean between monarchy
and democracy, and such a mean the state ought always to observe; for
servants and masters never can be friends, nor good and bad, merely because
they are declared to have equal privileges.  For to unequals equals become
unequal, if they are not harmonised by measure; and both by reason of
equality, and by reason of inequality, cities are filled with seditions. 
The old saying, that 'equality makes friendship,' is happy and also true;
but there is obscurity and confusion as to what sort of equality is meant. 
For there are two equalities which are called by the same name, but are in
reality in many ways almost the opposite of one another; one of them may be
introduced without difficulty, by any state or any legislator in the
distribution of honours:  this is the rule of measure, weight, and number,
which regulates and apportions them.  But there is another equality, of a
better and higher kind, which is not so easily recognized.  This is the
judgment of Zeus; among men it avails but little; that little, however, is
the source of the greatest good to individuals and states.  For it gives to
the greater more, and to the inferior less and in proportion to the nature
of each; and, above all, greater honour always to the greater virtue, and
to the less less; and to either in proportion to their respective measure
of virtue and education.  And this is justice, and is ever the true
principle of states, at which we ought to aim, and according to this rule
order the new city which is now being founded, and any other city which may
be hereafter founded.  To this the legislator should look,--not to the
interests of tyrants one or more, or to the power of the people, but to
justice always; which, as I was saying, is the distribution of natural
equality among unequals in each case.  But there are times at which every
state is compelled to use the words, 'just,' 'equal,' in a secondary sense,
in the hope of escaping in some degree from factions.  For equity and
indulgence are infractions of the perfect and strict rule of justice.  And
this is the reason why we are obliged to use the equality of the lot, in
order to avoid the discontent of the people; and so we invoke God and
fortune in our prayers, and beg that they themselves will direct the lot
with a view to supreme justice.  And therefore, although we are compelled
to use both equalities, we should use that into which the element of chance
enters as seldom as possible.

Thus, O my friends, and for the reasons given, should a state act which
would endure and be saved.  But as a ship sailing on the sea has to be
watched night and day, in like manner a city also is sailing on a sea of
politics, and is liable to all sorts of insidious assaults; and therefore
from morning to night, and from night to morning, rulers must join hands
with rulers, and watchers with watchers, receiving and giving up their
trust in a perpetual succession.  Now a multitude can never fulfil a duty
of this sort with anything like energy.  Moreover, the greater number of
the senators will have to be left during the greater part of the year to
order their concerns at their own homes.  They will therefore have to be
arranged in twelve portions, answering to the twelve months, and furnish
guardians of the state, each portion for a single month.  Their business is
to be at hand and receive any foreigner or citizen who comes to them,
whether to give information, or to put one of those questions, to which,
when asked by other cities, a city should give an answer, and to which, if
she ask them herself, she should receive an answer; or again, when there is
a likelihood of internal commotions, which are always liable to happen in
some form or other, they will, if they can, prevent their occurring; or if
they have already occurred, will lose no time in making them known to the
city, and healing the evil.  Wherefore, also, this which is the presiding
body of the state ought always to have the control of their assemblies, and
of the dissolutions of them, ordinary as well as extraordinary.  All this
is to be ordered by the twelfth part of the council, which is always to
keep watch together with the other officers of the state during one portion
of the year, and to rest during the remaining eleven portions.

Thus will the city be fairly ordered.  And now, who is to have the
superintendence of the country, and what shall be the arrangement?  Seeing
that the whole city and the entire country have been both of them divided
into twelve portions, ought there not to be appointed superintendents of
the streets of the city, and of the houses, and buildings, and harbours,
and the agora, and fountains, and sacred domains, and temples, and the
like?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure there ought.

ATHENIAN:  Let us assume, then, that there ought to be servants of the
temples, and priests and priestesses.  There must also be superintendents
of roads and buildings, who will have a care of men, that they may do no
harm, and also of beasts, both within the enclosure and in the suburbs. 
Three kinds of officers will thus have to be appointed, in order that the
city may be suitably provided according to her needs.  Those who have the
care of the city shall be called wardens of the city; and those who have
the care of the agora shall be called wardens of the agora; and those who
have the care of the temples shall be called priests.  Those who hold
hereditary offices as priests or priestesses, shall not be disturbed; but
if there be few or none such, as is probable at the foundation of a new
city, priests and priestesses shall be appointed to be servants of the Gods
who have no servants.  Some of our officers shall be elected, and others
appointed by lot, those who are of the people and those who are not of the
people mingling in a friendly manner in every place and city, that the
state may be as far as possible of one mind.  The officers of the temples
shall be appointed by lot; in this way their election will be committed to
God, that He may do what is agreeable to Him.  And he who obtains a lot
shall undergo a scrutiny, first, as to whether he is sound of body and of
legitimate birth; and in the second place, in order to show that he is of a
perfectly pure family, not stained with homicide or any similar impiety in
his own person, and also that his father and mother have led a similar
unstained life.  Now the laws about all divine things should be brought
from Delphi, and interpreters appointed, under whose direction they should
be used.  The tenure of the priesthood should always be for a year and no
longer; and he who will duly execute the sacred office, according to the
laws of religion, must be not less than sixty years of age--the laws shall
be the same about priestesses.  As for the interpreters, they shall be
appointed thus:--Let the twelve tribes be distributed into groups of four,
and let each group select four, one out of each tribe within the group,
three times; and let the three who have the greatest number of votes (out
of the twelve appointed by each group), after undergoing a scrutiny, nine
in all, be sent to Delphi, in order that the God may return one out of each
triad; their age shall be the same as that of the priests, and the scrutiny
of them shall be conducted in the same manner; let them be interpreters for
life, and when any one dies let the four tribes select another from the
tribe of the deceased.  Moreover, besides priests and interpreters, there
must be treasurers, who will take charge of the property of the several
temples, and of the sacred domains, and shall have authority over the
produce and the letting of them; and three of them shall be chosen from the
highest classes for the greater temples, and two for the lesser, and one
for the least of all; the manner of their election and the scrutiny of them
shall be the same as that of the generals.  This shall be the order of the
temples.

Let everything have a guard as far as possible.  Let the defence of the
city be commited to the generals, and taxiarchs, and hipparchs, and
phylarchs, and prytanes, and the wardens of the city, and of the agora,
when the election of them has been completed.  The defence of the country
shall be provided for as follows:--The entire land has been already
distributed into twelve as nearly as possible equal parts, and let the
tribe allotted to a division provide annually for it five wardens of the
country and commanders of the watch; and let each body of five have the
power of selecting twelve others out of the youth of their own tribe,--
these shall be not less than twenty-five years of age, and not more than
thirty.  And let there be allotted to them severally every month the
various districts, in order that they may all acquire knowledge and
experience of the whole country.  The term of service for commanders and
for watchers shall continue during two years.  After having had their
stations allotted to them, they will go from place to place in regular
order, making their round from left to right as their commanders direct
them; (when I speak of going to the right, I mean that they are to go to
the east).  And at the commencement of the second year, in order that as
many as possible of the guards may not only get a knowledge of the country
at any one season of the year, but may also have experience of the manner
in which different places are affected at different seasons of the year,
their then commanders shall lead them again towards the left, from place to
place in succession, until they have completed the second year.  In the
third year other wardens of the country shall be chosen and commanders of
the watch, five for each division, who are to be the superintendents of the
bands of twelve.  While on service at each station, their attention shall
be directed to the following points:--In the first place, they shall see
that the country is well protected against enemies; they shall trench and
dig wherever this is required, and, as far as they can, they shall by
fortifications keep off the evil-disposed, in order to prevent them from
doing any harm to the country or the property; they shall use the beasts of
burden and the labourers whom they find on the spot:  these will be their
instruments whom they will superintend, taking them, as far as possible, at
the times when they are not engaged in their regular business.  They shall
make every part of the country inaccessible to enemies, and as accessible
as possible to friends (compare Arist. Pol.); there shall be ways for man
and beasts of burden and for cattle, and they shall take care to have them
always as smooth as they can; and shall provide against the rains doing
harm instead of good to the land, when they come down from the mountains
into the hollow dells; and shall keep in the overflow by the help of works
and ditches, in order that the valleys, receiving and drinking up the rain
from heaven, and providing fountains and streams in the fields and regions
which lie underneath, may furnish even to the dry places plenty of good
water.  The fountains of water, whether of rivers or of springs, shall be
ornamented with plantations and buildings for beauty; and let them bring
together the streams in subterraneous channels, and make all things
plenteous; and if there be a sacred grove or dedicated precinct in the
neighbourhood, they shall conduct the water to the actual temples of the
Gods, and so beautify them at all seasons of the year.  Everywhere in such
places the youth shall make gymnasia for themselves, and warm baths for the
aged, placing by them abundance of dry wood, for the benefit of those
labouring under disease--there the weary frame of the rustic, worn with
toil, will receive a kindly welcome, far better than he would at the hands
of a not over-wise doctor.

The building of these and the like works will be useful and ornamental;
they will provide a pleasing amusement, but they will be a serious
employment too; for the sixty wardens will have to guard their several
divisions, not only with a view to enemies, but also with an eye to
professing friends.  When a quarrel arises among neighbours or citizens,
and any one whether slave or freeman wrongs another, let the five wardens
decide small matters on their own authority; but where the charge against
another relates to greater matters, the seventeen composed of the fives and
twelves, shall determine any charges which one man brings against another,
not involving more than three minae.  Every judge and magistrate shall be
liable to give an account of his conduct in office, except those who, like
kings, have the final decision.  Moreover, as regards the aforesaid wardens
of the country, if they do any wrong to those of whom they have the care,
whether by imposing upon them unequal tasks, or by taking the produce of
the soil or implements of husbandry without their consent; also if they
receive anything in the way of a bribe, or decide suits unjustly, or if
they yield to the influences of flattery, let them be publicly dishonoured;
and in regard to any other wrong which they do to the inhabitants of the
country, if the question be of a mina, let them submit to the decision of
the villagers in the neighbourhood; but in suits of greater amount, or in
case of lesser, if they refuse to submit, trusting that their monthly
removal into another part of the country will enable them to escape--in
such cases the injured party may bring his suit in the common court, and if
he obtain a verdict he may exact from the defendant, who refused to submit,
a double penalty.

The wardens and the overseers of the country, while on their two years'
service, shall have common meals at their several stations, and shall all
live together; and he who is absent from the common meal, or sleeps out, if
only for one day or night, unless by order of his commanders, or by reason
of absolute necessity, if the five denounce him and inscribe his name in
the agora as not having kept his guard, let him be deemed to have betrayed
the city, as far as lay in his power, and let him be disgraced and beaten
with impunity by any one who meets him and is willing to punish him.  If
any of the commanders is guilty of such an irregularity, the whole company
of sixty shall see to it, and he who is cognisant of the offence, and does
not bring the offender to trial, shall be amenable to the same laws as the
younger offender himself, and shall pay a heavier fine, and be incapable of
ever commanding the young.  The guardians of the law are to be careful
inspectors of these matters, and shall either prevent or punish offenders. 
Every man should remember the universal rule, that he who is not a good
servant will not be a good master; a man should pride himself more upon
serving well than upon commanding well:  first upon serving the laws, which
is also the service of the Gods; in the second place, upon having served
ancient and honourable men in the days of his youth.  Furthermore, during
the two years in which any one is a warden of the country, his daily food
ought to be of a simple and humble kind.  When the twelve have been chosen,
let them and the five meet together, and determine that they will be their
own servants, and, like servants, will not have other slaves and servants
for their own use, neither will they use those of the villagers and
husbandmen for their private advantage, but for the public service only;
and in general they should make up their minds to live independently by
themselves, servants of each other and of themselves.  Further, at all
seasons of the year, summer and winter alike, let them be under arms and
survey minutely the whole country; thus they will at once keep guard, and
at the same time acquire a perfect knowledge of every locality.  There can
be no more important kind of information than the exact knowledge of a
man's own country; and for this as well as for more general reasons of
pleasure and advantage, hunting with dogs and other kinds of sports should
be pursued by the young.  The service to whom this is committed may be
called the secret police or wardens of the country; the name does not much
signify, but every one who has the safety of the state at heart will use
his utmost diligence in this service.

After the wardens of the country, we have to speak of the election of
wardens of the agora and of the city.  The wardens of the country were
sixty in number, and the wardens of the city will be three, and will divide
the twelve parts of the city into three; like the former, they shall have
care of the ways, and of the different high roads which lead out of the
country into the city, and of the buildings, that they may be all made
according to law;--also of the waters, which the guardians of the supply
preserve and convey to them, care being taken that they may reach the
fountains pure and abundant, and be both an ornament and a benefit to the
city.  These also should be men of influence, and at leisure to take care
of the public interest.  Let every man propose as warden of the city any
one whom he likes out of the highest class, and when the vote has been
given on them, and the number is reduced to the six who have the greatest
number of votes, let the electing officers choose by lot three out of the
six, and when they have undergone a scrutiny let them hold office according
to the laws laid down for them.  Next, let the wardens of the agora be
elected in like manner, out of the first and second class, five in number: 
ten are to be first elected, and out of the ten five are to be chosen by
lot, as in the election of the wardens of the city:--these when they have
undergone a scrutiny are to be declared magistrates.  Every one shall vote
for every one, and he who will not vote, if he be informed against before
the magistrates, shall be fined fifty drachmae, and shall also be deemed a
bad citizen.  Let any one who likes go to the assembly and to the general
council; it shall be compulsory to go on citizens of the first and second
class, and they shall pay a fine of ten drachmae if they be found not
answering to their names at the assembly.  But the third and fourth class
shall be under no compulsion, and shall be let off without a fine, unless
the magistrates have commanded all to be present, in consequence of some
urgent necessity.  The wardens of the agora shall observe the order
appointed by law for the agora, and shall have the charge of the temples
and fountains which are in the agora; and they shall see that no one
injures anything, and punish him who does, with stripes and bonds, if he be
a slave or stranger; but if he be a citizen who misbehaves in this way,
they shall have the power themselves of inflicting a fine upon him to the
amount of a hundred drachmae, or with the consent of the wardens of the
city up to double that amount.  And let the wardens of the city have a
similar power of imposing punishments and fines in their own department;
and let them impose fines by their own department; and let them impose
fines by their own authority, up to a mina, or up to two minae with the
consent of the wardens of the agora.

In the next place, it will be proper to appoint directors of music and
gymnastic, two kinds of each--of the one kind the business will be
education, of the other, the superintendence of contests.  In speaking of
education, the law means to speak of those who have the care of order and
instruction in gymnasia and schools, and of the going to school, and of
school buildings for boys and girls; and in speaking of contests, the law
refers to the judges of gymnastics and of music; these again are divided
into two classes, the one having to do with music, the other with
gymnastics; and the same who judge of the gymnastic contests of men, shall
judge of horses; but in music there shall be one set of judges of solo
singing, and of imitation--I mean of rhapsodists, players on the harp, the
flute and the like, and another who shall judge of choral song.  First of
all, we must choose directors for the choruses of boys, and men, and
maidens, whom they shall follow in the amusement of the dance, and for our
other musical arrangements;--one director will be enough for the choruses,
and he should be not less than forty years of age.  One director will also
be enough to introduce the solo singers, and to give judgment on the
competitors, and he ought not to be less than thirty years of age.  The
director and manager of the choruses shall be elected after the following
manner:--Let any persons who commonly take an interest in such matters go
to the meeting, and be fined if they do not go (the guardians of the law
shall judge of their fault), but those who have no interest shall not be
compelled.  The elector shall propose as director some one who understands
music, and he in the scrutiny may be challenged on the one part by those
who say he has no skill, and defended on the other hand by those who say
that he has.  Ten are to be elected by vote, and he of the ten who is
chosen by lot shall undergo a scrutiny, and lead the choruses for a year
according to law.  And in like manner the competitor who wins the lot shall
be leader of the solo and concert music for that year; and he who is thus
elected shall deliver the award to the judges.  In the next place, we have
to choose judges in the contests of horses and of men; these shall be
selected from the third and also from the second class of citizens, and
three first classes shall be compelled to go to the election, but the
lowest may stay away with impunity; and let there be three elected by lot
out of the twenty who have been chosen previously, and they must also have
the vote and approval of the examiners.  But if any one is rejected in the
scrutiny at any ballot or decision, others shall be chosen in the same
manner, and undergo a similar scrutiny.

There remains the minister of the education of youth, male and female; he
too will rule according to law; one such minister will be sufficient, and
he must be fifty years old, and have children lawfully begotten, both boys
and girls by preference, at any rate, one or the other.  He who is elected,
and he who is the elector, should consider that of all the great offices of
state this is the greatest; for the first shoot of any plant, if it makes a
good start towards the attainment of its natural excellence, has the
greatest effect on its maturity; and this is not only true of plants, but
of animals wild and tame, and also of men.  Man, as we say, is a tame or
civilized animal; nevertheless, he requires proper instruction and a
fortunate nature, and then of all animals he becomes the most divine and
most civilized (Arist. Pol.); but if he be insufficiently or ill educated
he is the most savage of earthly creatures.  Wherefore the legislator ought
not to allow the education of children to become a secondary or accidental
matter.  In the first place, he who would be rightly provident about them,
should begin by taking care that he is elected, who of all the citizens is
in every way best; him the legislator shall do his utmost to appoint
guardian and superintendent.  To this end all the magistrates, with the
exception of the council and prytanes, shall go to the temple of Apollo,
and elect by ballot him of the guardians of the law whom they severally
think will be the best superintendent of education.  And he who has the
greatest number of votes, after he has undergone a scrutiny at the hands of
all the magistrates who have been his electors, with the exception of the
guardians of the law,--shall hold office for five years; and in the sixth
year let another be chosen in like manner to fill his office.

If any one dies while he is holding a public office, and more than thirty
days before his term of office expires, let those whose business it is
elect another to the office in the same manner as before.  And if any one
who is entrusted with orphans dies, let the relations both on the father's
and mother's side, who are residing at home, including cousins, appoint
another guardian within ten days, or be fined a drachma a day for neglect
to do so.

A city which has no regular courts of law ceases to be a city; and again,
if a judge is silent and says no more in preliminary proceedings than the
litigants, as is the case in arbitrations, he will never be able to decide
justly; wherefore a multitude of judges will not easily judge well, nor a
few if they are bad.  The point in dispute between the parties should be
made clear; and time, and deliberation, and repeated examination, greatly
tend to clear up doubts.  For this reason, he who goes to law with another,
should go first of all to his neighbours and friends who know best the
questions at issue.  And if he be unable to obtain from them a satisfactory
decision, let him have recourse to another court; and if the two courts
cannot settle the matter, let a third put an end to the suit.

Now the establishment of courts of justice may be regarded as a choice of
magistrates, for every magistrate must also be a judge of some things; and
the judge, though he be not a magistrate, yet in certain respects is a very
important magistrate on the day on which he is determining a suit. 
Regarding then the judges also as magistrates, let us say who are fit to be
judges, and of what they are to be judges, and how many of them are to
judge in each suit.  Let that be the supreme tribunal which the litigants
appoint in common for themselves, choosing certain persons by agreement. 
And let there be two other tribunals:  one for private causes, when a
citizen accuses another of wronging him and wishes to get a decision; the
other for public causes, in which some citizen is of opinion that the
public has been wronged by an individual, and is willing to vindicate the
common interests.  And we must not forget to mention how the judges are to
be qualified, and who they are to be.  In the first place, let there be a
tribunal open to all private persons who are trying causes one against
another for the third time, and let this be composed as follows:--All the
officers of state, as well annual as those holding office for a longer
period, when the new year is about to commence, in the month following
after the summer solstice, on the last day but one of the year, shall meet
in some temple, and calling God to witness, shall dedicate one judge from
every magistracy to be their first-fruits, choosing in each office him who
seems to them to be the best, and whom they deem likely to decide the
causes of his fellow-citizens during the ensuing year in the best and
holiest manner.  And when the election is completed, a scrutiny shall be
held in the presence of the electors themselves, and if any one be rejected
another shall be chosen in the same manner.  Those who have undergone the
scrutiny shall judge the causes of those who have declined the inferior
courts, and shall give their vote openly.  The councillors and other
magistrates who have elected them shall be required to be hearers and
spectators of the causes; and any one else may be present who pleases.  If
one man charges another with having intentionally decided wrong, let him go
to the guardians of the law and lay his accusation before them, and he who
is found guilty in such a case shall pay damages to the injured party equal
to half the injury; but if he shall appear to deserve a greater penalty,
the judges shall determine what additional punishment he shall suffer, and
how much more he ought to pay to the public treasury, and to the party who
brought the suit.

In the judgment of offences against the state, the people ought to
participate, for when any one wrongs the state all are wronged, and may
reasonably complain if they are not allowed to share in the decision.  Such
causes ought to originate with the people, and the ought also to have the
final decision of them, but the trial of them shall take place before three
of the highest magistrates, upon whom the plaintiff and the defendant shall
agree; and if they are not able to come to an agreement themselves, the
council shall choose one of the two proposed.  And in private suits, too,
as far as is possible, all should have a share; for he who has no share in
the administration of justice, is apt to imagine that he has no share in
the state at all.  And for this reason there shall be a court of law in
every tribe, and the judges shall be chosen by lot;--they shall give their
decisions at once, and shall be inaccessible to entreaties.  The final
judgment shall rest with that court which, as we maintain, has been
established in the most incorruptible form of which human things admit: 
this shall be the court established for those who are unable to get rid of
their suits either in the courts of neighbours or of the tribes.

Thus much of the courts of law, which, as I was saying, cannot be precisely
defined either as being or not being offices; a superficial sketch has been
given of them, in which some things have been told and others omitted.  For
the right place of an exact statement of the laws respecting suits, under
their several heads, will be at the end of the body of legislation;--let us
then expect them at the end.  Hitherto our legislation has been chiefly
occupied with the appointment of offices.  Perfect unity and exactness,
extending to the whole and every particular of political administration,
cannot be attained to the full, until the discussion shall have a
beginning, middle, and end, and is complete in every part.  At present we
have reached the election of magistrates, and this may be regarded as a
sufficient termination of what preceded.  And now there need no longer be
any delay or hesitation in beginning the work of legislation.

CLEINIAS:  I like what you have said, Stranger; and I particularly like
your manner of tacking on the beginning of your new discourse to the end of
the former one.

ATHENIAN:  Thus far, then, the old men's rational pastime has gone off
well.

CLEINIAS:  You mean, I suppose, their serious and noble pursuit?

ATHENIAN:  Perhaps; but I should like to know whether you and I are agreed
about a certain thing.

CLEINIAS:  About what thing?

ATHENIAN:  You know the endless labour which painters expend upon their
pictures--they are always putting in or taking out colours, or whatever be
the term which artists employ; they seem as if they would never cease
touching up their works, which are always being made brighter and more
beautiful.

CLEINIAS:  I know something of these matters from report, although I have
never had any great acquaintance with the art.

ATHENIAN:  No matter; we may make use of the illustration notwithstanding:
--Suppose that some one had a mind to paint a figure in the most beautiful
manner, in the hope that his work instead of losing would always improve as
time went on--do you not see that being a mortal, unless he leaves some one
to succeed him who will correct the flaws which time may introduce, and be
able to add what is left imperfect through the defect of the artist, and
who will further brighten up and improve the picture, all his great labour
will last but a short time?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And is not the aim of the legislator similar?  First, he desires
that his laws should be written down with all possible exactness; in the
second place, as time goes on and he has made an actual trial of his
decrees, will he not find omissions?  Do you imagine that there ever was a
legislator so foolish as not to know that many things are necessarily
omitted, which some one coming after him must correct, if the constitution
and the order of government is not to deteriorate, but to improve in the
state which he has established?

CLEINIAS:  Assuredly, that is the sort of thing which every one would
desire.

ATHENIAN:  And if any one possesses any means of accomplishing this by word
or deed, or has any way great or small by which he can teach a person to
understand how he can maintain and amend the laws, he should finish what he
has to say, and not leave the work incomplete.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  And is not this what you and I have to do at the present moment?

CLEINIAS:  What have we to do?

ATHENIAN:  As we are about to legislate and have chosen our guardians of
the law, and are ourselves in the evening of life, and they as compared
with us are young men, we ought not only to legislate for them, but to
endeavour to make them not only guardians of the law but legislators
themselves, as far as this is possible.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly; if we can.

ATHENIAN:  At any rate, we must do our best.

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  We will say to them--O friends and saviours of our laws, in
laying down any law, there are many particulars which we shall omit, and
this cannot be helped; at the same time, we will do our utmost to describe
what is important, and will give an outline which you shall fill up.  And I
will explain on what principle you are to act.  Megillus and Cleinias and I
have often spoken to one another touching these matters, and we are of
opinion that we have spoken well.  And we hope that you will be of the same
mind with us, and become our disciples, and keep in view the things which
in our united opinion the legislator and guardian of the law ought to keep
in view.  There was one main point about which we were agreed--that a man's
whole energies throughout life should be devoted to the acquisition of the
virtue proper to a man, whether this was to be gained by study, or habit,
or some mode of acquisition, or desire, or opinion, or knowledge--and this
applies equally to men and women, old and young--the aim of all should
always be such as I have described; anything which may be an impediment,
the good man ought to show that he utterly disregards.  And if at last
necessity plainly compels him to be an outlaw from his native land, rather
than bow his neck to the yoke of slavery and be ruled by inferiors, and he
has to fly, an exile he must be and endure all such trials, rather than
accept another form of government, which is likely to make men worse. 
These are our original principles; and do you now, fixing your eyes upon
the standard of what a man and a citizen ought or ought not to be, praise
and blame the laws--blame those which have not this power of making the
citizen better, but embrace those which have; and with gladness receive and
live in them; bidding a long farewell to other institutions which aim at
goods, as they are termed, of a different kind.

Let us proceed to another class of laws, beginning with their foundation in
religion.  And we must first return to the number 5040--the entire number
had, and has, a great many convenient divisions, and the number of the
tribes which was a twelfth part of the whole, being correctly formed by 
21 x 20 (5040/(21 x 20), i.e., 5040/420 = 12), also has them.  And not only
is the whole number divisible by twelve, but also the number of each tribe
is divisible by twelve.  Now every portion should be regarded by us as a
sacred gift of Heaven, corresponding to the months and to the revolution of
the universe (compare Tim.).  Every city has a guiding and sacred principle
given by nature, but in some the division or distribution has been more
right than in others, and has been more sacred and fortunate.  In our
opinion, nothing can be more right than the selection of the number 5040,
which may be divided by all numbers from one to twelve with the single
exception of eleven, and that admits of a very easy correction; for if,
turning to the dividend (5040), we deduct two families, the defect in the
division is cured.  And the truth of this may be easily proved when we have
leisure.  But for the present, trusting to the mere assertion of this
principle, let us divide the state; and assigning to each portion some God
or son of a God, let us give them altars and sacred rites, and at the
altars let us hold assemblies for sacrifice twice in the month--twelve
assemblies for the tribes, and twelve for the city, according to their
divisions; the first in honour of the Gods and divine things, and the
second to promote friendship and 'better acquaintance,' as the phrase is,
and every sort of good fellowship with one another.  For people must be
acquainted with those into whose families and whom they marry and with
those to whom they give in marriage; in such matters, as far as possible, a
man should deem it all important to avoid a mistake, and with this serious
purpose let games be instituted (compare Republic) in which youths and
maidens shall dance together, seeing one another and being seen naked, at a
proper age, and on a suitable occasion, not transgressing the rules of
modesty.

The directors of choruses will be the superintendents and regulators of
these games, and they, together with the guardians of the law, will
legislate in any matters which we have omitted; for, as we said, where
there are numerous and minute details, the legislator must leave out
something.  And the annual officers who have experience, and know what is
wanted, must make arrangements and improvements year by year, until such
enactments and provisions are sufficiently determined.  A ten years'
experience of sacrifices and dances, if extending to all particulars, will
be quite sufficient; and if the legislator be alive they shall communicate
with him, but if he be dead then the several officers shall refer the
omissions which come under their notice to the guardians of the law, and
correct them, until all is perfect; and from that time there shall be no
more change, and they shall establish and use the new laws with the others
which the legislator originally gave them, and of which they are never, if
they can help, to change aught; or, if some necessity overtakes them, the
magistrates must be called into counsel, and the whole people, and they
must go to all the oracles of the Gods; and if they are all agreed, in that
case they may make the change, but if they are not agreed, by no manner of
means, and any one who dissents shall prevail, as the law ordains.

Whenever any one over twenty-five years of age, having seen and been seen
by others, believes himself to have found a marriage connexion which is to
his mind, and suitable for the procreation of children, let him marry if he
be still under the age of five-and-thirty years; but let him first hear how
he ought to seek after what is suitable and appropriate (compare Arist.
Pol.).  For, as Cleinias says, every law should have a suitable prelude.

CLEINIAS:  You recollect at the right moment, Stranger, and do not miss the
opportunity which the argument affords of saying a word in season.

ATHENIAN:  I thank you.  We will say to him who is born of good parents--O
my son, you ought to make such a marriage as wise men would approve.  Now
they would advise you neither to avoid a poor marriage, nor specially to
desire a rich one; but if other things are equal, always to honour
inferiors, and with them to form connexions;--this will be for the benefit
of the city and of the families which are united; for the equable and
symmetrical tends infinitely more to virtue than the unmixed.  And he who
is conscious of being too headstrong, and carried away more than is fitting
in all his actions, ought to desire to become the relation of orderly
parents; and he who is of the opposite temper ought to seek the opposite
alliance.  Let there be one word concerning all marriages:--Every man shall
follow, not after the marriage which is most pleasing to himself, but after
that which is most beneficial to the state.  For somehow every one is by
nature prone to that which is likest to himself, and in this way the whole
city becomes unequal in property and in disposition; and hence there arise
in most states the very results which we least desire to happen.  Now, to
add to the law an express provision, not only that the rich man shall not
marry into the rich family, nor the powerful into the family of the
powerful, but that the slower natures shall be compelled to enter into
marriage with the quicker, and the quicker with the slower, may awaken
anger as well as laughter in the minds of many; for there is a difficulty
in perceiving that the city ought to be well mingled like a cup, in which
the maddening wine is hot and fiery, but when chastened by a soberer God,
receives a fair associate and becomes an excellent and temperate drink
(compare Statesman).  Yet in marriage no one is able to see that the same
result occurs.  Wherefore also the law must let alone such matters, but we
should try to charm the spirits of men into believing the equability of
their children's disposition to be of more importance than equality in
excessive fortune when they marry; and him who is too desirous of making a
rich marriage we should endeavour to turn aside by reproaches, not,
however, by any compulsion of written law.

Let this then be our exhortation concerning marriage, and let us remember
what was said before--that a man should cling to immortality, and leave
behind him children's children to be the servants of God in his place for
ever.  All this and much more may be truly said by way of prelude about the
duty of marriage.  But if a man will not listen, and remains unsocial and
alien among his fellow-citizens, and is still unmarried at thirty-five
years of age, let him pay a yearly fine;--he who of the highest class shall
pay a fine of a hundred drachmae, and he who is of the second class a fine
of seventy drachmae; the third class shall pay sixty drachmae, and the
fourth thirty drachmae, and let the money be sacred to Here; he who does
not pay the fine annually shall owe ten times the sum, which the treasurer
of the goddess shall exact; and if he fails in doing so, let him be
answerable and give an account of the money at his audit.  He who refuses
to marry shall be thus punished in money, and also be deprived of all
honour which the younger show to the elder; let no young man voluntarily
obey him, and, if he attempt to punish any one, let every one come to the
rescue and defend the injured person, and he who is present and does not
come to the rescue, shall be pronounced by the law to be a coward and a bad
citizen.  Of the marriage portion I have already spoken; and again I say
for the instruction of poor men that he who neither gives nor receives a
dowry on account of poverty, has a compensation; for the citizens of our
state are provided with the necessaries of life, and wives will be less
likely to be insolent, and husbands to be mean and subservient to them on
account of property.  And he who obeys this law will do a noble action; but
he who will not obey, and gives or receives more than fifty drachmae as the
price of the marriage garments if he be of the lowest, or more than a mina,
or a mina-and-a-half, if he be of the third or second classes, or two minae
if he be of the highest class, shall owe to the public treasury a similar
sum, and that which is given or received shall be sacred to Here and Zeus;
and let the treasurers of these Gods exact the money, as was said before
about the unmarried--that the treasurers of Here were to exact the money,
or pay the fine themselves.

The betrothal by a father shall be valid in the first degree, that by a
grandfather in the second degree, and in the third degree, betrothal by
brothers who have the same father; but if there are none of these alive,
the betrothal by a mother shall be valid in like manner; in cases of
unexampled fatality, the next of kin and the guardians shall have
authority.  What are to be the rites before marriages, or any other sacred
acts, relating either to future, present, or past marriages, shall be
referred to the interpreters; and he who follows their advice may be
satisfied.  Touching the marriage festival, they shall assemble not more
than five male and five female friends of both families; and a like number
of members of the family of either sex, and no man shall spend more than
his means will allow; he who is of the richest class may spend a mina,--he
who is of the second, half a mina, and in the same proportion as the census
of each decreases:  all men shall praise him who is obedient to the law;
but he who is disobedient shall be punished by the guardians of the law as
a man wanting in true taste, and uninstructed in the laws of bridal song. 
Drunkenness is always improper, except at the festivals of the God who gave
wine; and peculiarly dangerous, when a man is engaged in the business of
marriage; at such a crisis of their lives a bride and bridegroom ought to
have all their wits about them--they ought to take care that their
offspring may be born of reasonable beings; for on what day or night Heaven
will give them increase, who can say?  Moreover, they ought not to
begetting children when their bodies are dissipated by intoxication, but
their offspring should be compact and solid, quiet and compounded properly;
whereas the drunkard is all abroad in all his actions, and beside himself
both in body and soul.  Wherefore, also, the drunken man is bad and
unsteady in sowing the seed of increase, and is likely to beget offspring
who will be unstable and untrustworthy, and cannot be expected to walk
straight either in body or mind.  Hence during the whole year and all his
life long, and especially while he is begetting children, he ought to take
care and not intentionally do what is injurious to health, or what involves
insolence and wrong; for he cannot help leaving the impression of himself
on the souls and bodies of his offspring, and he begets children in every
way inferior.  And especially on the day and night of marriage should a man
abstain from such things.  For the beginning, which is also a God dwelling
in man, preserves all things, if it meet with proper respect from each
individual.  He who marries is further to consider, that one of the two
houses in the lot is the nest and nursery of his young, and there he is to
marry and make a home for himself and bring up his children, going away
from his father and mother.  For in friendships there must be some degree
of desire, in order to cement and bind together diversities of character;
but excessive intercourse not having the desire which is created by time,
insensibly dissolves friendships from a feeling of satiety; wherefore a man
and his wife shall leave to his and her father and mother their own
dwelling-places, and themselves go as to a colony and dwell there, and
visit and be visited by their parents; and they shall beget and bring up
children, handing on the torch of life from one generation to another, and
worshipping the Gods according to law for ever.

In the next place, we have to consider what sort of property will be most
convenient.  There is no difficulty either in understanding or acquiring
most kinds of property, but there is great difficulty in what relates to
slaves.  And the reason is, that we speak about them in a way which is
right and which is not right; for what we say about our slaves is
consistent and also inconsistent with our practice about them.

MEGILLUS:  I do not understand, Stranger, what you mean.

ATHENIAN:  I am not surprised, Megillus, for the state of the Helots among
the Lacedaemonians is of all Hellenic forms of slavery the most
controverted and disputed about, some approving and some condemning it;
there is less dispute about the slavery which exists among the Heracleots,
who have subjugated the Mariandynians, and about the Thessalian Penestae. 
Looking at these and the like examples, what ought we to do concerning
property in slaves?  I made a remark, in passing, which naturally elicited
a question about my meaning from you.  It was this:--We know that all would
agree that we should have the best and most attached slaves whom we can
get.  For many a man has found his slaves better in every way than brethren
or sons, and many times they have saved the lives and property of their
masters and their whole house--such tales are well known.

MEGILLUS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  But may we not also say that the soul of the slave is utterly
corrupt, and that no man of sense ought to trust them?  And the wisest of
our poets, speaking of Zeus, says:

'Far-seeing Zeus takes away half the understanding of men whom the day of
slavery subdues.'

Different persons have got these two different notions of slaves in their
minds--some of them utterly distrust their servants, and, as if they were
wild beasts, chastise them with goads and whips, and make their souls three
times, or rather many times, as slavish as they were before;--and others do
just the opposite.

MEGILLUS:  True.

CLEINIAS:  Then what are we to do in our own country, Stranger, seeing that
there are such differences in the treatment of slaves by their owners?

ATHENIAN:  Well, Cleinias, there can be no doubt that man is a troublesome
animal, and therefore he is not very manageable, nor likely to become so,
when you attempt to introduce the necessary division of slave, and freeman,
and master.

CLEINIAS:  That is obvious.

ATHENIAN:  He is a troublesome piece of goods, as has been often shown by
the frequent revolts of the Messenians, and the great mischiefs which
happen in states having many slaves who speak the same language, and the
numerous robberies and lawless life of the Italian banditti, as they are
called.  A man who considers all this is fairly at a loss.  Two remedies
alone remain to us,--not to have the slaves of the same country, nor if
possible, speaking the same language (compare Aris. Pol.); in this way they
will more easily be held in subjection:  secondly, we should tend them
carefully, not only out of regard to them, but yet more out of respect to
ourselves.  And the right treatment of slaves is to behave properly to
them, and to do to them, if possible, even more justice than to those who
are our equals; for he who naturally and genuinely reverences justice, and
hates injustice, is discovered in his dealings with any class of men to
whom he can easily be unjust.  And he who in regard to the natures and
actions of his slaves is undefiled by impiety and injustice, will best sow
the seeds of virtue in them; and this may be truly said of every master,
and tyrant, and of every other having authority in relation to his
inferiors.  Slaves ought to be punished as they deserve, and not admonished
as if they were freemen, which will only make them conceited.  The language
used to a servant ought always to be that of a command (compare Arist.
Pol.), and we ought not to jest with them, whether they are males or
females--this is a foolish way which many people have of setting up their
slaves, and making the life of servitude more disagreeable both for them
and for their masters.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Now that each of the citizens is provided, as far as possible,
with a sufficient number of suitable slaves who can help him in what he has
to do, we may next proceed to describe their dwellings.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  The city being new and hitherto uninhabited, care ought to be
taken of all the buildings, and the manner of building each of them, and
also of the temples and walls.  These, Cleinias, were matters which
properly came before the marriages;--but, as we are only talking, there is
no objection to changing the order.  If, however, our plan of legislation
is ever to take effect, then the house shall precede the marriage if God so
will, and afterwards we will come to the regulations about marriage; but at
present we are only describing these matters in a general outline.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  The temples are to be placed all round the agora, and the whole
city built on the heights in a circle (compare Arist. Pol.), for the sake
of defence and for the sake of purity.  Near the temples are to be placed
buildings for the magistrates and the courts of law; in these plaintiff and
defendant will receive their due, and the places will be regarded as most
holy, partly because they have to do with holy things:  and partly because
they are the dwelling-places of holy Gods:  and in them will be held the
courts in which cases of homicide and other trials of capital offences may
fitly take place.  As to the walls, Megillus, I agree with Sparta in
thinking that they should be allowed to sleep in the earth, and that we
should not attempt to disinter them (compare Arist. Pol.); there is a
poetical saying, which is finely expressed, that 'walls ought to be of
steel and iron, and not of earth;' besides, how ridiculous of us to be
sending out our young men annually into the country to dig and to trench,
and to keep off the enemy by fortifications, under the idea that they are
not to be allowed to set foot in our territory, and then, that we should
surround ourselves with a wall, which, in the first place, is by no means
conducive to the health of cities, and is also apt to produce a certain
effeminacy in the minds of the inhabitants, inviting men to run thither
instead of repelling their enemies, and leading them to imagine that their
safety is due not to their keeping guard day and night, but that when they
are protected by walls and gates, then they may sleep in safety; as if they
were not meant to labour, and did not know that true repose comes from
labour, and that disgraceful indolence and a careless temper of mind is
only the renewal of trouble.  But if men must have walls, the private
houses ought to be so arranged from the first that the whole city may be
one wall, having all the houses capable of defence by reason of their
uniformity and equality towards the streets (compare Arist. Pol.).  The
form of the city being that of a single dwelling will have an agreeable
aspect, and being easily guarded will be infinitely better for security. 
Until the original building is completed, these should be the principal
objects of the inhabitants; and the wardens of the city should superintend
the work, and should impose a fine on him who is negligent; and in all that
relates to the city they should have a care of cleanliness, and not allow a
private person to encroach upon any public property either by buildings or
excavations.  Further, they ought to take care that the rains from heaven
flow off easily, and of any other matters which may have to be administered
either within or without the city.  The guardians of the law shall pass any
further enactments which their experience may show to be necessary, and
supply any other points in which the law may be deficient.  And now that
these matters, and the buildings about the agora, and the gymnasia, and
places of instruction, and theatres, are all ready and waiting for scholars
and spectators, let us proceed to the subjects which follow marriage in the
order of legislation.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Assuming that marriages exist already, Cleinias, the mode of
life during the year after marriage, before children are born, will follow
next in order.  In what way bride and bridegroom ought to live in a city
which is to be superior to other cities, is a matter not at all easy for us
to determine.  There have been many difficulties already, but this will be
the greatest of them, and the most disagreeable to the many.  Still I
cannot but say what appears to me to be right and true, Cleinias.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  He who imagines that he can give laws for the public conduct of
states, while he leaves the private life of citizens wholly to take care of
itself; who thinks that individuals may pass the day as they please, and
that there is no necessity of order in all things; he, I say, who gives up
the control of their private lives, and supposes that they will conform to
law in their common and public life, is making a great mistake.  Why have I
made this remark?  Why, because I am going to enact that the bridegrooms
should live at the common tables, just as they did before marriage.  This
was a singularity when first enacted by the legislator in your parts of the
world, Megillus and Cleinias, as I should suppose, on the occasion of some
war or other similar danger, which caused the passing of the law, and which
would be likely to occur in thinly-peopled places, and in times of
pressure.  But when men had once tried and been accustomed to a common
table, experience showed that the institution greatly conduced to security;
and in some such manner the custom of having common tables arose among you.

CLEINIAS:  Likely enough.

ATHENIAN:  I said that there may have been singularity and danger in
imposing such a custom at first, but that now there is not the same
difficulty.  There is, however, another institution which is the natural
sequel to this, and would be excellent, if it existed anywhere, but at
present it does not.  The institution of which I am about to speak is not
easily described or executed; and would be like the legislator 'combing
wool into the fire,' as people say, or performing any other impossible and
useless feat.

CLEINIAS:  What is the cause, Stranger, of this extreme hesitation?

ATHENIAN:  You shall hear without any fruitless loss of time.  That which
has law and order in a state is the cause of every good, but that which is
disordered or ill-ordered is often the ruin of that which is well-ordered;
and at this point the argument is now waiting.  For with you, Cleinias and
Megillus, the common tables of men are, as I said, a heaven-born and
admirable institution, but you are mistaken in leaving the women
unregulated by law.  They have no similar institution of public tables in
the light of day, and just that part of the human race which is by nature
prone to secrecy and stealth on account of their weakness--I mean the
female sex--has been left without regulation by the legislator, which is a
great mistake.  And, in consequence of this neglect, many things have grown
lax among you, which might have been far better, if they had been only
regulated by law; for the neglect of regulations about women may not only
be regarded as a neglect of half the entire matter (Arist. Pol.), but in
proportion as woman's nature is inferior to that of men in capacity for
virtue, in that degree the consequence of such neglect is more than twice
as important.  The careful consideration of this matter, and the arranging
and ordering on a common principle of all our institutions relating both to
men and women, greatly conduces to the happiness of the state.  But at
present, such is the unfortunate condition of mankind, that no man of sense
will even venture to speak of common tables in places and cities in which
they have never been established at all; and how can any one avoid being
utterly ridiculous, who attempts to compel women to show in public how much
they eat and drink?  There is nothing at which the sex is more likely to
take offence.  For women are accustomed to creep into dark places, and when
dragged out into the light they will exert their utmost powers of
resistance, and be far too much for the legislator.  And therefore, as I
said before, in most places they will not endure to have the truth spoken
without raising a tremendous outcry, but in this state perhaps they may. 
And if we may assume that our whole discussion about the state has not been
mere idle talk, I should like to prove to you, if you will consent to
listen, that this institution is good and proper; but if you had rather
not, I will refrain.

CLEINIAS:  There is nothing which we should both of us like better,
Stranger, than to hear what you have to say.

ATHENIAN:  Very good; and you must not be surprised if I go back a little,
for we have plenty of leisure, and there is nothing to prevent us from
considering in every point of view the subject of law.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us return once more to what we were saying at first.
Every man should understand that the human race either had no beginning at
all, and will never have an end, but always will be and has been; or that
it began an immense while ago.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Well, and have there not been constitutions and destructions of
states, and all sorts of pursuits both orderly and disorderly, and diverse
desires of meats and drinks always, and in all the world, and all sorts of
changes of the seasons in which animals may be expected to have undergone
innumerable transformations of themselves?

CLEINIAS:  No doubt.

ATHENIAN:  And may we not suppose that vines appeared, which had previously
no existence, and also olives, and the gifts of Demeter and her daughter,
of which one Triptolemus was the minister, and that, before these existed,
animals took to devouring each other as they do still?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Again, the practice of men sacrificing one another still exists
among many nations; while, on the other hand, we hear of other human beings
who did not even venture to taste the flesh of a cow and had no animal
sacrifices, but only cakes and fruits dipped in honey, and similar pure
offerings, but no flesh of animals; from these they abstained under the
idea that they ought not to eat them, and might not stain the altars of the
Gods with blood.  For in those days men are said to have lived a sort of
Orphic life, having the use of all lifeless things, but abstaining from all
living things.

CLEINIAS:  Such has been the constant tradition, and is very likely true.

ATHENIAN:  Some one might say to us, What is the drift of all this?

CLEINIAS:  A very pertinent question, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  And therefore I will endeavour, Cleinias, if I can, to draw the
natural inference.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  I see that among men all things depend upon three wants and
desires, of which the end is virtue, if they are rightly led by them, or
the opposite if wrongly.  Now these are eating and drinking, which begin at
birth--every animal has a natural desire for them, and is violently
excited, and rebels against him who says that he must not satisfy all his
pleasures and appetites, and get rid of all the corresponding pains--and
the third and greatest and sharpest want and desire breaks out last, and is
the fire of sexual lust, which kindles in men every species of wantonness
and madness.  And these three disorders we must endeavour to master by the
three great principles of fear and law and right reason; turning them away
from that which is called pleasantest to the best, using the Muses and the
Gods who preside over contests to extinguish their increase and influx.

But to return:--After marriage let us speak of the birth of children, and
after their birth of their nurture and education.  In the course of
discussion the several laws will be perfected, and we shall at last arrive
at the common tables.  Whether such associations are to be confined to men,
or extended to women also, we shall see better when we approach and take a
nearer view of them; and we may then determine what previous institutions
are required and will have to precede them.  As I said before, we shall see
them more in detail, and shall be better able to lay down the laws which
are proper or suited to them.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Let us keep in mind the words which have now been spoken; for
hereafter there may be need of them.

CLEINIAS:  What do you bid us keep in mind?

ATHENIAN:  That which we comprehended under the three words--first, eating,
secondly, drinking, thirdly, the excitement of love.

CLEINIAS:  We shall be sure to remember, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Very good.  Then let us now proceed to marriage, and teach
persons in what way they shall beget children, threatening them, if they
disobey, with the terrors of the law.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  The bride and bridegroom should consider that they are to
produce for the state the best and fairest specimens of children which they
can.  Now all men who are associated in any action always succeed when they
attend and give their mind to what they are doing, but when they do not
give their mind or have no mind, they fail; wherefore let the bridegroom
give his mind to the bride and to the begetting of children, and the bride
in like manner give her mind to the bridegroom, and particularly at the
time when their children are not yet born.  And let the women whom we have
chosen be the overseers of such matters, and let them in whatever number,
large or small, and at whatever time the magistrates may command, assemble
every day in the temple of Eileithyia during a third part of the day, and
being there assembled, let them inform one another of any one whom they
see, whether man or woman, of those who are begetting children,
disregarding the ordinances given at the time when the nuptial sacrifices
and ceremonies were performed.  Let the begetting of children and the
supervision of those who are begetting them continue ten years and no
longer, during the time when marriage is fruitful.  But if any continue
without children up to this time, let them take counsel with their kindred
and with the women holding the office of overseer and be divorced for their
mutual benefit.  If, however, any dispute arises about what is proper and
for the interest of either party, they shall choose ten of the guardians of
the law and abide by their permission and appointment.  The women who
preside over these matters shall enter into the houses of the young, and
partly by admonitions and partly by threats make them give over their folly
and error:  if they persist, let the women go and tell the guardians of the
law, and the guardians shall prevent them.  But if they too cannot prevent
them, they shall bring the matter before the people; and let them write up
their names and make oath that they cannot reform such and such an one; and
let him who is thus written up, if he cannot in a court of law convict
those who have inscribed his name, be deprived of the privileges of a
citizen in the following respects:--let him not go to weddings nor to the
thanksgivings after the birth of children; and if he go, let any one who
pleases strike him with impunity; and let the same regulations hold about
women:  let not a woman be allowed to appear abroad, or receive honour, or
go to nuptial and birthday festivals, if she in like manner be written up
as acting disorderly and cannot obtain a verdict.  And if, when they
themselves have done begetting children according to the law, a man or
woman have connexion with another man or woman who are still begetting
children, let the same penalties be inflicted upon them as upon those who
are still having a family; and when the time for procreation has passed let
the man or woman who refrains in such matters be held in esteem, and let
those who do not refrain be held in the contrary of esteem--that is to say,
disesteem.  Now, if the greater part of mankind behave modestly, the
enactments of law may be left to slumber; but, if they are disorderly, the
enactments having been passed, let them be carried into execution.  To
every man the first year is the beginning of life, and the time of birth
ought to be written down in the temples of their fathers as the beginning
of existence to every child, whether boy or girl.  Let every phratria have
inscribed on a whited wall the names of the successive archons by whom the
years are reckoned.  And near to them let the living members of the
phratria be inscribed, and when they depart life let them be erased.  The
limit of marriageable ages for a woman shall be from sixteen to twenty
years at the longest,--for a man, from thirty to thirty-five years; and let
a woman hold office at forty, and a man at thirty years.  Let a man go out
to war from twenty to sixty years, and for a woman, if there appear any
need to make use of her in military service, let the time of service be
after she shall have brought forth children up to fifty years of age; and
let regard be had to what is possible and suitable to each.


BOOK VII.

And now, assuming children of both sexes to have been born, it will be
proper for us to consider, in the next place, their nurture and education;
this cannot be left altogether unnoticed, and yet may be thought a subject
fitted rather for precept and admonition than for law.  In private life
there are many little things, not always apparent, arising out of the
pleasures and pains and desires of individuals, which run counter to the
intention of the legislator, and make the characters of the citizens
various and dissimilar:--this is an evil in states; for by reason of their
smallness and frequent occurrence, there would be an unseemliness and want
of propriety in making them penal by law; and if made penal, they are the
destruction of the written law because mankind get the habit of frequently
transgressing the law in small matters.  The result is that you cannot
legislate about them, and still less can you be silent.  I speak somewhat
darkly, but I shall endeavour also to bring my wares into the light of day,
for I acknowledge that at present there is a want of clearness in what I am
saying.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN.  Am I not right in maintaining that a good education is that
which tends most to the improvement of mind and body?

CLEINIAS:  Undoubtedly.

ATHENIAN:  And nothing can be plainer than that the fairest bodies are
those which grow up from infancy in the best and straightest manner?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And do we not further observe that the first shoot of every
living thing is by far the greatest and fullest?  Many will even contend
that a man at twenty-five does not reach twice the height which he attained
at five.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Well, and is not rapid growth without proper and abundant
exercise the source endless evils in the body?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And the body should have the most exercise when it receives most
nourishment?

CLEINIAS:  But, Stranger, are we to impose this great amount of exercise
upon newly-born infants?

ATHENIAN:  Nay, rather on the bodies of infants still unborn.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean, my good sir?  In the process of gestation?

ATHENIAN:  Exactly.  I am not at all surprised that you have never heard of
this very peculiar sort of gymnastic applied to such little creatures,
which, although strange, I will endeavour to explain to you.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  The practice is more easy for us to understand than for you, by
reason of certain amusements which are carried to excess by us at Athens. 
Not only boys, but often older persons, are in the habit of keeping quails
and cocks (compare Republic), which they train to fight one another.  And
they are far from thinking that the contests in which they stir them up to
fight with one another are sufficient exercise; for, in addition to this,
they carry them about tucked beneath their armpits, holding the smaller
birds in their hands, the larger under their arms, and go for a walk of a
great many miles for the sake of health, that is to say, not their own
health, but the health of the birds; whereby they prove to any intelligent
person, that all bodies are benefited by shakings and movements, when they
are moved without weariness, whether the motion proceeds from themselves,
or is caused by a swing, or at sea, or on horseback, or by other bodies in
whatever way moving, and that thus gaining the mastery over food and drink,
they are able to impart beauty and health and strength.  But admitting all
this, what follows?  Shall we make a ridiculous law that the pregnant woman
shall walk about and fashion the embryo within as we fashion wax before it
hardens, and after birth swathe the infant for two years?  Suppose that we
compel nurses, under penalty of a legal fine, to be always carrying the
children somewhere or other, either to the temples, or into the country, or
to their relations' houses, until they are well able to stand, and to take
care that their limbs are not distorted by leaning on them when they are
too young (compare Arist. Pol.),--they should continue to carry them until
the infant has completed its third year; the nurses should be strong, and
there should be more than one of them.  Shall these be our rules, and shall
we impose a penalty for the neglect of them?  No, no; the penalty of which
we were speaking will fall upon our own heads more than enough.

CLEINIAS:  What penalty?

ATHENIAN:  Ridicule, and the difficulty of getting the feminine and
servant-like dispositions of the nurses to comply.

CLEINIAS:  Then why was there any need to speak of the matter at all?

ATHENIAN:  The reason is, that masters and freemen in states, when they
hear of it, are very likely to arrive at a true conviction that without due
regulation of private life in cities, stability in the laying down of laws
is hardly to be expected (compare Republic); and he who makes this
reflection may himself adopt the laws just now mentioned, and, adopting
them, may order his house and state well and be happy.

CLEINIAS:  Likely enough.

ATHENIAN:  And therefore let us proceed with our legislation until we have
determined the exercises which are suited to the souls of young children,
in the same manner in which we have begun to go through the rules relating
to their bodies.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Let us assume, then, as a first principle in relation both to
the body and soul of very young creatures, that nursing and moving about by
day and night is good for them all, and that the younger they are, the more
they will need it (compare Arist. Pol.); infants should live, if that were
possible, as if they were always rocking at sea.  This is the lesson which
we may gather from the experience of nurses, and likewise from the use of
the remedy of motion in the rites of the Corybantes; for when mothers want
their restless children to go to sleep they do not employ rest, but, on the
contrary, motion--rocking them in their arms; nor do they give them
silence, but they sing to them and lap them in sweet strains; and the
Bacchic women are cured of their frenzy in the same manner by the use of
the dance and of music.

CLEINIAS:  Well, Stranger, and what is the reason of this?

ATHENIAN:  The reason is obvious.

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  The affection both of the Bacchantes and of the children is an
emotion of fear, which springs out of an evil habit of the soul.  And when
some one applies external agitation to affections of this sort, the motion
coming from without gets the better of the terrible and violent internal
one, and produces a peace and calm in the soul, and quiets the restless
palpitation of the heart, which is a thing much to be desired, sending the
children to sleep, and making the Bacchantes, although they remain awake,
to dance to the pipe with the help of the Gods to whom they offer
acceptable sacrifices, and producing in them a sound mind, which takes the
place of their frenzy.  And, to express what I mean in a word, there is a
good deal to be said in favour of this treatment.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  But if fear has such a power we ought to infer from these facts,
that every soul which from youth upward has been familiar with fears, will
be made more liable to fear (compare Republic), and every one will allow
that this is the way to form a habit of cowardice and not of courage.

CLEINIAS:  No doubt.

ATHENIAN:  And, on the other hand, the habit of overcoming, from our youth
upwards, the fears and terrors which beset us, may be said to be an
exercise of courage.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And we may say that the use of exercise and motion in the
earliest years of life greatly contributes to create a part of virtue in
the soul.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Further, a cheerful temper, or the reverse, may be regarded as
having much to do with high spirit on the one hand, or with cowardice on
the other.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  Then now we must endeavour to show how and to what extent we
may, if we please, without difficulty implant either character in the
young.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  There is a common opinion, that luxury makes the disposition of
youth discontented and irascible and vehemently excited by trifles; that on
the other hand excessive and savage servitude makes men mean and abject,
and haters of their kind, and therefore makes them undesirable associates.

CLEINIAS:  But how must the state educate those who do not as yet
understand the language of the country, and are therefore incapable of
appreciating any sort of instruction?

ATHENIAN:  I will tell you how:--Every animal that is born is wont to utter
some cry, and this is especially the case with man, and he is also affected
with the inclination to weep more than any other animal.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Do not nurses, when they want to know what an infant desires,
judge by these signs?--when anything is brought to the infant and he is
silent, then he is supposed to be pleased, but, when he weeps and cries
out, then he is not pleased.  For tears and cries are the inauspicious
signs by which children show what they love and hate.  Now the time which
is thus spent is no less than three years, and is a very considerable
portion of life to be passed ill or well.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Does not the discontented and ungracious nature appear to you to
be full of lamentations and sorrows more than a good man ought to be?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Well, but if during these three years every possible care were
taken that our nursling should have as little of sorrow and fear, and in
general of pain as was possible, might we not expect in early childhood to
make his soul more gentle and cheerful?  (Compare Arist. Pol.)

CLEINIAS:  To be sure, Stranger--more especially if we could procure him a
variety of pleasures.

ATHENIAN:  There I can no longer agree, Cleinias:  you amaze me.  To bring
him up in such a way would be his utter ruin; for the beginning is always
the most critical part of education.  Let us see whether I am right.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  The point about which you and I differ is of great importance,
and I hope that you, Megillus, will help to decide between us.  For I
maintain that the true life should neither seek for pleasures, nor, on the
other hand, entirely avoid pains, but should embrace the middle state
(compare Republic), which I just spoke of as gentle and benign, and is a
state which we by some divine presage and inspiration rightly ascribe to
God.  Now, I say, he among men, too, who would be divine ought to pursue
after this mean habit--he should not rush headlong into pleasures, for he
will not be free from pains; nor should we allow any one, young or old,
male or female, to be thus given any more than ourselves, and least of all
the newly-born infant, for in infancy more than at any other time the
character is engrained by habit.  Nay, more, if I were not afraid of
appearing to be ridiculous, I would say that a woman during her year of
pregnancy should of all women be most carefully tended, and kept from
violent or excessive pleasures and pains, and should at that time cultivate
gentleness and benevolence and kindness.

CLEINIAS:  You need not ask Megillus, Stranger, which of us has most truly
spoken; for I myself agree that all men ought to avoid the life of
unmingled pain or pleasure, and pursue always a middle course.  And having
spoken well, may I add that you have been well answered?

ATHENIAN:  Very good, Cleinias; and now let us all three consider a further
point.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  That all the matters which we are now describing are commonly
called by the general name of unwritten customs, and what are termed the
laws of our ancestors are all of similar nature.  And the reflection which
lately arose in our minds, that we can neither call these things laws, nor
yet leave them unmentioned, is justified; for they are the bonds of the
whole state, and come in between the written laws which are or are
hereafter to be laid down; they are just ancestral customs of great
antiquity, which, if they are rightly ordered and made habitual, shield and
preserve the previously existing written law; but if they depart from right
and fall into disorder, then they are like the props of builders which slip
away out of their place and cause a universal ruin--one part drags another
down, and the fair super-structure falls because the old foundations are
undermined.  Reflecting upon this, Cleinias, you ought to bind together the
new state in every possible way, omitting nothing, whether great or small,
of what are called laws or manners or pursuits, for by these means a city
is bound together, and all these things are only lasting when they depend
upon one another; and, therefore, we must not wonder if we find that many
apparently trifling customs or usages come pouring in and lengthening out
our laws.

CLEINIAS:  Very true:  we are disposed to agree with you.

ATHENIAN:  Up to the age of three years, whether of boy or girl, if a
person strictly carries out our previous regulations and makes them a
principal aim, he will do much for the advantage of the young creatures. 
But at three, four, five, and even six years the childish nature will
require sports; now is the time to get rid of self-will in him, punishing
him, but not so as to disgrace him.  We were saying about slaves, that we
ought neither to add insult to punishment so as to anger them, nor yet to
leave them unpunished lest they become self-willed; and a like rule is to
be observed in the case of the free-born.  Children at that age have
certain natural modes of amusement which they find out for themselves when
they meet.  And all the children who are between the ages of three and six
ought to meet at the temples of the villages, the several families of a
village uniting on one spot.  The nurses are to see that the children
behave properly and orderly,--they themselves and all their companies are
to be under the control of twelve matrons, one for each company, who are
annually selected to inspect them from the women previously mentioned,
(i.e. the women who have authority over marriage), whom the guardians of
the law appoint.  These matrons shall be chosen by the women who have
authority over marriage, one out of each tribe; all are to be of the same
age; and let each of them, as soon as she is appointed, hold office and go
to the temples every day, punishing all offenders, male or female, who are
slaves or strangers, by the help of some of the public slaves; but if any
citizen disputes the punishment, let her bring him before the wardens of
the city; or, if there be no dispute, let her punish him herself.  After
the age of six years the time has arrived for the separation of the sexes,
--let boys live with boys, and girls in like manner with girls.  Now they
must begin to learn--the boys going to teachers of horsemanship and the use
of the bow, the javelin, and sling, and the girls too, if they do not
object, at any rate until they know how to manage these weapons, and
especially how to handle heavy arms; for I may note, that the practice
which now prevails is almost universally misunderstood.

CLEINIAS:  In what respect?

ATHENIAN:  In that the right and left hand are supposed to be by nature
differently suited for our various uses of them; whereas no difference is
found in the use of the feet and the lower limbs; but in the use of the
hands we are, as it were, maimed by the folly of nurses and mothers; for
although our several limbs are by nature balanced, we create a difference
in them by bad habit.  In some cases this is of no consequence, as, for
example, when we hold the lyre in the left hand, and the plectrum in the
right, but it is downright folly to make the same distinction in other
cases.  The custom of the Scythians proves our error; for they not only
hold the bow from them with the left hand and draw the arrow to them with
their right, but use either hand for both purposes.  And there are many
similar examples in charioteering and other things, from which we may learn
that those who make the left side weaker than the right act contrary to
nature.  In the case of the plectrum, which is of horn only, and similar
instruments, as I was saying, it is of no consequence, but makes a great
difference, and may be of very great importance to the warrior who has to
use iron weapons, bows and javelins, and the like; above all, when in heavy
armour, he has to fight against heavy armour.  And there is a very great
difference between one who has learnt and one who has not, and between one
who has been trained in gymnastic exercises and one who has not been.  For
as he who is perfectly skilled in the Pancratium or boxing or wrestling, is
not unable to fight from his left side, and does not limp and draggle in
confusion when his opponent makes him change his position, so in heavy-
armed fighting, and in all other things, if I am not mistaken, the like
holds--he who has these double powers of attack and defence ought not in
any case to leave them either unused or untrained, if he can help; and if a
person had the nature of Geryon or Briareus he ought to be able with his
hundred hands to throw a hundred darts.  Now, the magistrates, male and
female, should see to all these things, the women superintending the
nursing and amusements of the children, and the men superintending their
education, that all of them, boys and girls alike, may be sound hand and
foot, and may not, if they can help, spoil the gifts of nature by bad
habits.

Education has two branches,--one of gymnastic, which is concerned with the
body, and the other of music, which is designed for the improvement of the
soul (compare Republic).  And gymnastic has also two branches--dancing and
wrestling; and one sort of dancing imitates musical recitation, and aims at
preserving dignity and freedom, the other aims at producing health,
agility, and beauty in the limbs and parts of the body, giving the proper
flexion and extension to each of them, a harmonious motion being diffused
everywhere, and forming a suitable accompaniment to the dance.  As regards
wrestling, the tricks which Antaeus and Cercyon devised in their systems
out of a vain spirit of competition, or the tricks of boxing which Epeius
or Amycus invented, are useless and unsuitable for war, and do not deserve
to have much said about them; but the art of wrestling erect and keeping
free the neck and hands and sides, working with energy and constancy, with
a composed strength, and for the sake of health--these are always useful,
and are not to be neglected, but to be enjoined alike on masters and
scholars, when we reach that part of legislation; and we will desire the
one to give their instructions freely, and the others to receive them
thankfully.  Nor, again, must we omit suitable imitations of war in our
choruses; here in Crete you have the armed dances of the Curetes, and the
Lacedaemonians have those of the Dioscuri.  And our virgin lady, delighting
in the amusement of the dance, thought it not fit to amuse herself with
empty hands; she must be clothed in a complete suit of armour, and in this
attire go through the dance (compare Crit.); and youths and maidens should
in every respect imitate her, esteeming highly the favour of the Goddess,
both with a view to the necessities of war, and to festive occasions:  it
will be right also for the boys, until such time as they go out to war, to
make processions and supplications to all the Gods in goodly array, armed
and on horseback, in dances and marches, fast or slow, offering up prayers
to the Gods and to the sons of Gods; and also engaging in contests and
preludes of contests, if at all, with these objects:  For these sorts of
exercises, and no others, are useful both in peace and war, and are
beneficial alike to states and to private houses.  But other labours and
sports and exercises of the body are unworthy of freemen, O Megillus and
Cleinias.

I have now completely described the kind of gymnastic which I said at first
ought to be described; if you know of any better, will you communicate your
thoughts?

CLEINIAS:  It is not easy, Stranger, to put aside these principles of
gymnastic and wrestling and to enunciate better ones.

ATHENIAN:  Now we must say what has yet to be said about the gifts of the
Muses and of Apollo:  before, we fancied that we had said all, and that
gymnastic alone remained; but now we see clearly what points have been
omitted, and should be first proclaimed; of these, then, let us proceed to
speak.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Let me tell you once more--although you have heard me say the
same before--that caution must be always exercised, both by the speaker and
by the hearer, about anything that is very singular and unusual.  For my
tale is one which many a man would be afraid to tell, and yet I have a
confidence which makes me go on.

CLEINIAS:  What have you to say, Stranger?

ATHENIAN:  I say that in states generally no one has observed that the
plays of childhood have a great deal to do with the permanence or want of
permanence in legislation.  For when plays are ordered with a view to
children having the same plays, and amusing themselves after the same
manner, and finding delight in the same playthings, the more solemn
institutions of the state are allowed to remain undisturbed.  Whereas if
sports are disturbed, and innovations are made in them, and they constantly
change, and the young never speak of their having the same likings, or the
same established notions of good and bad taste, either in the bearing of
their bodies or in their dress, but he who devises something new and out of
the way in figures and colours and the like is held in special honour, we
may truly say that no greater evil can happen in a state (compare
Republic); for he who changes the sports is secretly changing the manners
of the young, and making the old to be dishonoured among them and the new
to be honoured.  And I affirm that there is nothing which is a greater
injury to all states than saying or thinking thus.  Will you hear me tell
how great I deem the evil to be?

CLEINIAS:  You mean the evil of blaming antiquity in states?

ATHENIAN:  Exactly.

CLEINIAS:  If you are speaking of that, you will find in us hearers who are
disposed to receive what you say not unfavourably but most favourably.

ATHENIAN:  I should expect so.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, let us give all the greater heed to one another's
words.  The argument affirms that any change whatever except from evil is
the most dangerous of all things; this is true in the case of the seasons
and of the winds, in the management of our bodies and the habits of our
minds--true of all things except, as I said before, of the bad.  He who
looks at the constitution of individuals accustomed to eat any sort of
meat, or drink any drink, or to do any work which they can get, may see
that they are at first disordered by them, but afterwards, as time goes on,
their bodies grow adapted to them, and they learn to know and like variety,
and have good health and enjoyment of life; and if ever afterwards they are
confined again to a superior diet, at first they are troubled with
disorders, and with difficulty become habituated to their new food.  A
similar principle we may imagine to hold good about the minds of men and
the natures of their souls.  For when they have been brought up in certain
laws, which by some Divine Providence have remained unchanged during long
ages, so that no one has any memory or tradition of their ever having been
otherwise than they are, then every one is afraid and ashamed to change
that which is established.  The legislator must somehow find a way of
implanting this reverence for antiquity, and I would propose the following
way:--People are apt to fancy, as I was saying before, that when the plays
of children are altered they are merely plays, not seeing that the most
serious and detrimental consequences arise out of the change; and they
readily comply with the child's wishes instead of deterring him, not
considering that these children who make innovations in their games, when
they grow up to be men, will be different from the last generation of
children, and, being different, will desire a different sort of life, and
under the influence of this desire will want other institutions and laws;
and no one of them reflects that there will follow what I just now called
the greatest of evils to states.  Changes in bodily fashions are no such
serious evils, but frequent changes in the praise and censure of manners
are the greatest of evils, and require the utmost prevision.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And now do we still hold to our former assertion, that rhythms
and music in general are imitations of good and evil characters in men? 
What say you?

CLEINIAS:  That is the only doctrine which we can admit.

ATHENIAN:  Must we not, then, try in every possible way to prevent our
youth from even desiring to imitate new modes either in dance or song? nor
must any one be allowed to offer them varieties of pleasures.

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  Can any of us imagine a better mode of effecting this object
than that of the Egyptians?

CLEINIAS:  What is their method?

ATHENIAN:  To consecrate every sort of dance or melody.  First we should
ordain festivals,--calculating for the year what they ought to be, and at
what time, and in honour of what Gods, sons of Gods, and heroes they ought
to be celebrated; and, in the next place, what hymns ought to be sung at
the several sacrifices, and with what dances the particular festival is to
be honoured.  This has to be arranged at first by certain persons, and,
when arranged, the whole assembly of the citizens are to offer sacrifices
and libations to the Fates and all the other Gods, and to consecrate the
several odes to Gods and heroes:  and if any one offers any other hymns or
dances to any one of the Gods, the priests and priestesses, acting in
concert with the guardians of the law, shall, with the sanction of religion
and the law, exclude him, and he who is excluded, if he do not submit,
shall be liable all his life long to have a suit of impiety brought against
him by any one who likes.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  In the consideration of this subject, let us remember what is
due to ourselves.

CLEINIAS:  To what are you referring?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that any young man, and much more any old one, when he
sees or hears anything strange or unaccustomed, does not at once run to
embrace the paradox, but he stands considering, like a person who is at a
place where three paths meet, and does not very well know his way--he may
be alone or he may be walking with others, and he will say to himself and
them, 'Which is the way?' and will not move forward until he is satisfied
that he is going right.  And this is what we must do in the present
instance:--A strange discussion on the subject of law has arisen, which
requires the utmost consideration, and we should not at our age be too
ready to speak about such great matters, or be confident that we can say
anything certain all in a moment.

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  Then we will allow time for reflection, and decide when we have
given the subject sufficient consideration.  But that we may not be
hindered from completing the natural arrangement of our laws, let us
proceed to the conclusion of them in due order; for very possibly, if God
will, the exposition of them, when completed, may throw light on our
present perplexity.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent, Stranger; let us do as you propose.

ATHENIAN:  Let us then affirm the paradox that strains of music are our
laws (nomoi), and this latter being the name which the ancients gave to
lyric songs, they probably would not have very much objected to our
proposed application of the word.  Some one, either asleep or awake, must
have had a dreamy suspicion of their nature.  And let our decree be as
follows:--No one in singing or dancing shall offend against public and
consecrated models, and the general fashion among the youth, any more than
he would offend against any other law.  And he who observes this law shall
be blameless; but he who is disobedient, as I was saying, shall be punished
by the guardians of the laws, and by the priests and priestesses.  Suppose
that we imagine this to be our law.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Can any one who makes such laws escape ridicule?  Let us see.  I
think that our only safety will be in first framing certain models for
composers.  One of these models shall be as follows:--If when a sacrifice
is going on, and the victims are being burnt according to law,--if, I say,
any one who may be a son or brother, standing by another at the altar and
over the victims, horribly blasphemes, will not his words inspire
despondency and evil omens and forebodings in the mind of his father and of
his other kinsmen?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And this is just what takes place in almost all our cities.  A
magistrate offers a public sacrifice, and there come in not one but many
choruses, who take up a position a little way from the altar, and from time
to time pour forth all sorts of horrible blasphemies on the sacred rites,
exciting the souls of the audience with words and rhythms and melodies most
sorrowful to hear; and he who at the moment when the city is offering
sacrifice makes the citizens weep most, carries away the palm of victory. 
Now, ought we not to forbid such strains as these?  And if ever our
citizens must hear such lamentations, then on some unblest and inauspicious
day let there be choruses of foreign and hired minstrels, like those
hirelings who accompany the departed at funerals with barbarous Carian
chants.  That is the sort of thing which will be appropriate if we have
such strains at all; and let the apparel of the singers be, not circlets
and ornaments of gold, but the reverse.  Enough of all this.  I will simply
ask once more whether we shall lay down as one of our principles of song--

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  That we should avoid every word of evil omen; let that kind of
song which is of good omen be heard everywhere and always in our state.  I
need hardly ask again, but shall assume that you agree with me.

CLEINIAS:  By all means; that law is approved by the suffrages of us all.

ATHENIAN:  But what shall be our next musical law or type?  Ought not
prayers to be offered up to the Gods when we sacrifice?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And our third law, if I am not mistaken, will be to the effect
that our poets, understanding prayers to be requests which we make to the
Gods, will take especial heed that they do not by mistake ask for evil
instead of good.  To make such a prayer would surely be too ridiculous.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Were we not a little while ago quite convinced that no silver or
golden Plutus should dwell in our state?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And what has it been the object of our argument to show?  Did we
not imply that the poets are not always quite capable of knowing what is
good or evil?  And if one of them utters a mistaken prayer in song or
words, he will make our citizens pray for the opposite of what is good in
matters of the highest import; than which, as I was saying, there can be
few greater mistakes.  Shall we then propose as one of our laws and models
relating to the Muses--

CLEINIAS:  What?--will you explain the law more precisely?

ATHENIAN:  Shall we make a law that the poet shall compose nothing contrary
to the ideas of the lawful, or just, or beautiful, or good, which are
allowed in the state? nor shall he be permitted to communicate his
compositions to any private individuals, until he shall have shown them to
the appointed judges and the guardians of the law, and they are satisfied
with them.  As to the persons whom we appoint to be our legislators about
music and as to the director of education, these have been already
indicated.  Once more then, as I have asked more than once, shall this be
our third law, and type, and model--What do you say?

CLEINIAS:  Let it be so, by all means.

ATHENIAN:  Then it will be proper to have hymns and praises of the Gods
(compare Republic), intermingled with prayers; and after the Gods prayers
and praises should be offered in like manner to demigods and heroes,
suitable to their several characters.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  In the next place there will be no objection to a law, that
citizens who are departed and have done good and energetic deeds, either
with their souls or with their bodies, and have been obedient to the laws,
should receive eulogies; this will be very fitting.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  But to honour with hymns and panegyrics those who are still
alive is not safe; a man should run his course, and make a fair ending, and
then we will praise him; and let praise be given equally to women as well
as men who have been distinguished in virtue.  The order of songs and
dances shall be as follows:--There are many ancient musical compositions
and dances which are excellent, and from these the newly-founded city may
freely select what is proper and suitable; and they shall choose judges of
not less than fifty years of age, who shall make the selection, and any of
the old poems which they deem sufficient they shall include; any that are
deficient or altogether unsuitable, they shall either utterly throw aside,
or examine and amend, taking into their counsel poets and musicians, and
making use of their poetical genius; but explaining to them the wishes of
the legislator in order that they may regulate dancing, music, and all
choral strains, according to the mind of the judges; and not allowing them
to indulge, except in some few matters, their individual pleasures and
fancies.  Now the irregular strain of music is always made ten thousand
times better by attaining to law and order, and rejecting the honeyed Muse
--not however that we mean wholly to exclude pleasure, which is the
characteristic of all music.  And if a man be brought up from childhood to
the age of discretion and maturity in the use of the orderly and severe
music, when he hears the opposite he detests it, and calls it illiberal;
but if trained in the sweet and vulgar music, he deems the severer kind
cold and displeasing (compare Arist. Pol.).  So that, as I was saying
before, while he who hears them gains no more pleasure from the one than
from the other, the one has the advantage of making those who are trained
in it better men, whereas the other makes them worse.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Again, we must distinguish and determine on some general
principle what songs are suitable to women, and what to men, and must
assign to them their proper melodies and rhythms.  It is shocking for a
whole harmony to be inharmonical, or for a rhythm to be unrhythmical, and
this will happen when the melody is inappropriate to them.  And therefore
the legislator must assign to these also their forms.  Now both sexes have
melodies and rhythms which of necessity belong to them; and those of women
are clearly enough indicated by their natural difference.  The grand, and
that which tends to courage, may be fairly called manly; but that which
inclines to moderation and temperance, may be declared both in law and in
ordinary speech to be the more womanly quality.  This, then, will be the
general order of them.

Let us now speak of the manner of teaching and imparting them, and the
persons to whom, and the time when, they are severally to be imparted.  As
the shipwright first lays down the lines of the keel, and thus, as it were,
draws the ship in outline, so do I seek to distinguish the patterns of
life, and lay down their keels according to the nature of different men's
souls; seeking truly to consider by what means, and in what ways, we may go
through the voyage of life best.  Now human affairs are hardly worth
considering in earnest, and yet we must be in earnest about them,--a sad
necessity constrains us.  And having got thus far, there will be a fitness
in our completing the matter, if we can only find some suitable method of
doing so.  But what do I mean?  Some one may ask this very question, and
quite rightly, too.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  I say that about serious matters a man should be serious, and
about a matter which is not serious he should not be serious; and that God
is the natural and worthy object of our most serious and blessed
endeavours, for man, as I said before, is made to be the plaything of God,
and this, truly considered, is the best of him; wherefore also every man
and woman should walk seriously, and pass life in the noblest of pastimes,
and be of another mind from what they are at present.

CLEINIAS:  In what respect?

ATHENIAN:  At present they think that their serious pursuits should be for
the sake of their sports, for they deem war a serious pursuit, which must
be managed well for the sake of peace; but the truth is, that there neither
is, nor has been, nor ever will be, either amusement or instruction in any
degree worth speaking of in war, which is nevertheless deemed by us to be
the most serious of our pursuits.  And therefore, as we say, every one of
us should live the life of peace as long and as well as he can.  And what
is the right way of living?  Are we to live in sports always?  If so, in
what kind of sports?  We ought to live sacrificing, and singing, and
dancing, and then a man will be able to propitiate the Gods, and to defend
himself against his enemies and conquer them in battle.  The type of song
or dance by which he will propitiate them has been described, and the paths
along which he is to proceed have been cut for him.  He will go forward in
the spirit of the poet (Homer, Odyss.):--

'Telemachus, some things thou wilt thyself find in thy heart, but other
things God will suggest; for I deem that thou wast not born or brought up
without the will of the Gods.'

And this ought to be the view of our alumni; they ought to think that what
has been said is enough for them, and that any other things their Genius
and God will suggest to them--he will tell them to whom, and when, and to
what Gods severally they are to sacrifice and perform dances, and how they
may propitiate the deities, and live according to the appointment of
nature; being for the most part puppets, but having some little share of
reality.

MEGILLUS:  You have a low opinion of mankind, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Nay, Megillus, be not amazed, but forgive me:--I was comparing
them with the Gods; and under that feeling I spoke.  Let us grant, if you
wish, that the human race is not to be despised, but is worthy of some
consideration.

Next follow the buildings for gymnasia and schools open to all; these are
to be in three places in the midst of the city; and outside the city and in
the surrounding country, also in three places, there shall be schools for
horse exercise, and large grounds arranged with a view to archery and the
throwing of missiles, at which young men may learn and practise.  Of these
mention has already been made, and if the mention be not sufficiently
explicit, let us speak further of them and embody them in laws.  In these
several schools let there be dwellings for teachers, who shall be brought
from foreign parts by pay, and let them teach those who attend the schools
the art of war and the art of music, and the children shall come not only
if their parents please, but if they do not please; there shall be
compulsory education, as the saying is, of all and sundry, as far this is
possible; and the pupils shall be regarded as belonging to the state rather
than to their parents (compare Arist. Pol.).  My law would apply to females
as well as males; they shall both go through the same exercises.  I assert
without fear of contradiction that gymnastic and horsemanship are as
suitable to women as to men (compare Republic).  Of the truth of this I am
persuaded from ancient tradition, and at the present day there are said to
be countless myriads of women in the neighbourhood of the Black Sea, called
Sauromatides, who not only ride on horseback like men, but have enjoined
upon them the use of bows and other weapons equally with the men.  And I
further affirm, that if these things are possible, nothing can be more
absurd than the practice which prevails in our own country, of men and
women not following the same pursuits with all their strength and with one
mind, for thus the state, instead of being a whole, is reduced to a half,
but has the same imposts to pay and the same toils to undergo; and what can
be a greater mistake for any legislator to make than this?

CLEINIAS:  Very true; yet much of what has been asserted by us, Stranger,
is contrary to the custom of states; still, in saying that the discourse
should be allowed to proceed, and that when the discussion is completed, we
should choose what seems best, you spoke very properly, and I now feel
compunction for what I have said.  Tell me, then, what you would next wish
to say.

ATHENIAN:  I should wish to say, Cleinias, as I said before, that if the
possibility of these things were not sufficiently proven in fact, then
there might be an objection to the argument, but the fact being as I have
said, he who rejects the law must find some other ground of objection; and,
failing this, our exhortation will still hold good, nor will any one deny
that women ought to share as far as possible in education and in other ways
with men.  For consider;--if women do not share in their whole life with
men, then they must have some other order of life.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And what arrangement of life to be found anywhere is preferable
to this community which we are now assigning to them?  Shall we prefer that
which is adopted by the Thracians and many other races who use their women
to till the ground and to be shepherds of their herds and flocks, and to
minister to them like slaves?--Or shall we do as we and people in our part
of the world do--getting together, as the phrase is, all our goods and
chattels into one dwelling, we entrust them to our women, who are the
stewards of them, and who also preside over the shuttles and the whole art
of spinning?  Or shall we take a middle course, as in Lacedaemon, Megillus
--letting the girls share in gymnastic and music, while the grown-up women,
no longer employed in spinning wool, are hard at work weaving the web of
life, which will be no cheap or mean employment, and in the duty of serving
and taking care of the household and bringing up children, in which they
will observe a sort of mean, not participating in the toils of war; and if
there were any necessity that they should fight for their city and
families, unlike the Amazons, they would be unable to take part in archery
or any other skilled use of missiles, nor could they, after the example of
the Goddess, carry shield or spear, or stand up nobly for their country
when it was being destroyed, and strike terror into their enemies, if only
because they were seen in regular order?  Living as they do, they would
never dare at all to imitate the Sauromatides, who, when compared with
ordinary women, would appear to be like men.  Let him who will, praise your
legislators, but I must say what I think.  The legislator ought to be whole
and perfect, and not half a man only; he ought not to let the female sex
live softly and waste money and have no order of life, while he takes the
utmost care of the male sex, and leaves half of life only blest with
happiness, when he might have made the whole state happy.

MEGILLUS:  What shall we do, Cleinias?  Shall we allow a stranger to run
down Sparta in this fashion?

CLEINIAS:  Yes; for as we have given him liberty of speech we must let him
go on until we have perfected the work of legislation.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Then now I may proceed?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  What will be the manner of life among men who may be supposed to
have their food and clothing provided for them in moderation, and who have
entrusted the practice of the arts to others, and whose husbandry committed
to slaves paying a part of the produce, brings them a return sufficient for
men living temperately; who, moreover, have common tables in which the men
are placed apart, and near them are the common tables of their families, of
their daughters and mothers, which day by day, the officers, male and
female, are to inspect--they shall see to the behaviour of the company, and
so dismiss them; after which the presiding magistrate and his attendants
shall honour with libations those Gods to whom that day and night are
dedicated, and then go home?  To men whose lives are thus ordered, is there
no work remaining to be done which is necessary and fitting, but shall each
one of them live fattening like a beast?  Such a life is neither just nor
honourable, nor can he who lives it fail of meeting his due; and the due
reward of the idle fatted beast is that he should be torn in pieces by some
other valiant beast whose fatness is worn down by brave deeds and toil. 
These regulations, if we duly consider them, will never be exactly carried
into execution under present circumstances, nor as long as women and
children and houses and all other things are the private property of
individuals; but if we can attain the second-best form of polity, we shall
be very well off.  And to men living under this second polity there remains
a work to be accomplished which is far from being small or insignificant,
but is the greatest of all works, and ordained by the appointment of
righteous law.  For the life which may be truly said to be concerned with
the virtue of body and soul is twice, or more than twice, as full of toil
and trouble as the pursuit after Pythian and Olympic victories (compare
Republic), which debars a man from every employment of life.  For there
ought to be no bye-work interfering with the greater work of providing the
necessary exercise and nourishment for the body, and instruction and
education for the soul.  Night and day are not long enough for the
accomplishment of their perfection and consummation; and therefore to this
end all freemen ought to arrange the way in which they will spend their
time during the whole course of the day, from morning till evening and from
evening till the morning of the next sunrise.  There may seem to be some
impropriety in the legislator determining minutely the numberless details
of the management of the house, including such particulars as the duty of
wakefulness in those who are to be perpetual watchmen of the whole city;
for that any citizen should continue during the whole of any night in
sleep, instead of being seen by all his servants, always the first to awake
and get up--this, whether the regulation is to be called a law or only a
practice, should be deemed base and unworthy of a freeman; also that the
mistress of the house should be awakened by her handmaidens instead of
herself first awakening them, is what the slaves, male and female, and the
serving-boys, and, if that were possible, everybody and everything in the
house should regard as base.  If they rise early, they may all of them do
much of their public and of their household business, as magistrates in the
city, and masters and mistresses in their private houses, before the sun is
up.  Much sleep is not required by nature, either for our souls or bodies,
or for the actions which they perform.  For no one who is asleep is good
for anything, any more than if he were dead; but he of us who has the most
regard for life and reason keeps awake as long he can, reserving only so
much time for sleep as is expedient for health; and much sleep is not
required, if the habit of moderation be once rightly formed.  Magistrates
in states who keep awake at night are terrible to the bad, whether enemies
or citizens, and are honoured and reverenced by the just and temperate, and
are useful to themselves and to the whole state.

A night which is passed in such a manner, in addition to all the above-
mentioned advantages, infuses a sort of courage into the minds of the
citizens.  When the day breaks, the time has arrived for youth to go to
their schoolmasters.  Now neither sheep nor any other animals can live
without a shepherd, nor can children be left without tutors, or slaves
without masters.  And of all animals the boy is the most unmanageable,
inasmuch as he has the fountain of reason in him not yet regulated; he is
the most insidious, sharp-witted, and insubordinate of animals.  Wherefore
he must be bound with many bridles; in the first place, when he gets away
from mothers and nurses, he must be under the management of tutors on
account of his childishness and foolishness; then, again, being a freeman,
he must be controlled by teachers, no matter what they teach, and by
studies; but he is also a slave, and in that regard any freeman who comes
in his way may punish him and his tutor and his instructor, if any of them
does anything wrong; and he who comes across him and does not inflict upon
him the punishment which he deserves, shall incur the greatest disgrace;
and let the guardian of the law, who is the director of education, see to
him who coming in the way of the offences which we have mentioned, does not
chastise them when he ought, or chastises them in a way which he ought not;
let him keep a sharp look-out, and take especial care of the training of
our children, directing their natures, and always turning them to good
according to the law.

But how can our law sufficiently train the director of education himself;
for as yet all has been imperfect, and nothing has been said either clear
or satisfactory?  Now, as far as possible, the law ought to leave nothing
to him, but to explain everything, that he may be an interpreter and tutor
to others.  About dances and music and choral strains, I have already
spoken both to the character of the selection of them, and the manner in
which they are to be amended and consecrated.  But we have not as yet
spoken, O illustrious guardian of education, of the manner in which your
pupils are to use those strains which are written in prose, although you
have been informed what martial strains they are to learn and practise;
what relates in the first place to the learning of letters, and secondly,
to the lyre, and also to calculation, which, as we were saying, is needful
for them all to learn, and any other things which are required with a view
to war and the management of house and city, and, looking to the same
object, what is useful in the revolutions of the heavenly bodies--the stars
and sun and moon, and the various regulations about these matters which are
necessary for the whole state--I am speaking of the arrangements of days in
periods of months, and of months in years, which are to be observed, in
order that seasons and sacrifices and festivals may have their regular and
natural order, and keep the city alive and awake, the Gods receiving the
honours due to them, and men having a better understanding about them:  all
these things, O my friend, have not yet been sufficiently declared to you
by the legislator.  Attend, then, to what I am now going to say:--We were
telling you, in the first place, that you were not sufficiently informed
about letters, and the objection was to this effect,--that you were never
told whether he who was meant to be a respectable citizen should apply
himself in detail to that sort of learning, or not apply himself at all;
and the same remark holds good of the study of the lyre.  But now we say
that he ought to attend to them.  A fair time for a boy of ten years old to
spend in letters is three years; the age of thirteen is the proper time for
him to begin to handle the lyre, and he may continue at this for another
three years, neither more nor less, and whether his father or himself like
or dislike the study, he is not to be allowed to spend more or less time in
learning music than the law allows.  And let him who disobeys the law be
deprived of those youthful honours of which we shall hereafter speak. 
Hear, however, first of all, what the young ought to learn in the early
years of life, and what their instructors ought to teach them.  They ought
to be occupied with their letters until they are to read and write; but the
acquisition of perfect beauty or quickness in writing, if nature has not
stimulated them to acquire these accomplishments in the given number of
years, they should let alone.  And as to the learning of compositions
committed to writing which are not set to the lyre, whether metrical or
without rhythmical divisions, compositions in prose, as they are termed,
having no rhythm or harmony--seeing how dangerous are the writings handed
down to us by many writers of this class--what will you do with them, O
most excellent guardians of the law? or how can the lawgiver rightly direct
you about them?  I believe that he will be in great difficulty.

CLEINIAS:  What troubles you, Stranger? and why are you so perplexed in
your mind?

ATHENIAN:  You naturally ask, Cleinias, and to you and Megillus, who are my
partners in the work of legislation, I must state the more difficult as
well as the easier parts of the task.

CLEINIAS:  To what do you refer in this instance?

ATHENIAN:  I will tell you.  There is a difficulty in opposing many myriads
of mouths.

CLEINIAS:  Well, and have we not already opposed the popular voice in many
important enactments?

ATHENIAN:  That is quite true; and you mean to imply that the road which we
are taking may be disagreeable to some but is agreeable to as many others,
or if not to as many, at any rate to persons not inferior to the others,
and in company with them you bid me, at whatever risk, to proceed along the
path of legislation which has opened out of our present discourse, and to
be of good cheer, and not to faint.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And I do not faint; I say, indeed, that we have a great many
poets writing in hexameter, trimeter, and all sorts of measures--some who
are serious, others who aim only at raising a laugh--and all mankind
declare that the youth who are rightly educated should be brought up in
them and saturated with them; some insist that they should be constantly
hearing them read aloud, and always learning them, so as to get by heart
entire poets; while others select choice passages and long speeches, and
make compendiums of them, saying that these ought to be committed to
memory, if a man is to be made good and wise by experience and learning of
many things.  And you want me now to tell them plainly in what they are
right and in what they are wrong.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, I do.

ATHENIAN:  But how can I in one word rightly comprehend all of them?  I am
of opinion, and, if I am not mistaken, there is a general agreement, that
every one of these poets has said many things well and many things the
reverse of well; and if this be true, then I do affirm that much learning
is dangerous to youth.

CLEINIAS:  How would you advise the guardian of the law to act?

ATHENIAN:  In what respect?

CLEINIAS:  I mean to what pattern should he look as his guide in permitting
the young to learn some things and forbidding them to learn others.  Do not
shrink from answering.

ATHENIAN:  My good Cleinias, I rather think that I am fortunate.

CLEINIAS:  How so?

ATHENIAN:  I think that I am not wholly in want of a pattern, for when I
consider the words which we have spoken from early dawn until now, and
which, as I believe, have been inspired by Heaven, they appear to me to be
quite like a poem.  When I reflected upon all these words of ours, I
naturally felt pleasure, for of all the discourses which I have ever learnt
or heard, either in poetry or prose, this seemed to me to be the justest,
and most suitable for young men to hear; I cannot imagine any better
pattern than this which the guardian of the law who is also the director of
education can have.  He cannot do better than advise the teachers to teach
the young these words and any which are of a like nature, if he should
happen to find them, either in poetry or prose, or if he come across
unwritten discourses akin to ours, he should certainly preserve them, and
commit them to writing.  And, first of all, he shall constrain the teachers
themselves to learn and approve them, and any of them who will not, shall
not be employed by him, but those whom he finds agreeing in his judgment,
he shall make use of and shall commit to them the instruction and education
of youth.  And here and on this wise let my fanciful tale about letters and
teachers of letters come to an end.

CLEINIAS:  I do not think, Stranger, that we have wandered out of the
proposed limits of the argument; but whether we are right or not in our
whole conception, I cannot be very certain.

ATHENIAN:  The truth, Cleinias, may be expected to become clearer when, as
we have often said, we arrive at the end of the whole discussion about
laws.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And now that we have done with the teacher of letters, the
teacher of the lyre has to receive orders from us.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  I think that we have only to recollect our previous discussions,
and we shall be able to give suitable regulations touching all this part of
instruction and education to the teachers of the lyre.

CLEINIAS:  To what do you refer?

ATHENIAN:  We were saying, if I remember rightly, that the sixty-year-old
choristers of Dionysus were to be specially quick in their perceptions of
rhythm and musical composition, that they might be able to distinguish good
and bad imitation, that is to say, the imitation of the good or bad soul
when under the influence of passion, rejecting the one and displaying the
other in hymns and songs, charming the souls of youth, and inviting them to
follow and attain virtue by the way of imitation.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And with this view, the teacher and the learner ought to use the
sounds of the lyre, because its notes are pure, the player who teaches and
his pupil rendering note for note in unison; but complexity, and variation
of notes, when the strings give one sound and the poet or composer of the
melody gives another,--also when they make concords and harmonies in which
lesser and greater intervals, slow and quick, or high and low notes, are
combined,--or, again, when they make complex variations of rhythms, which
they adapt to the notes of the lyre (compare Republic),--all that sort of
thing is not suited to those who have to acquire a speedy and useful
knowledge of music in three years; for opposite principles are confusing,
and create a difficulty in learning, and our young men should learn
quickly, and their mere necessary acquirements are not few or trifling, as
will be shown in due course.  Let the director of education attend to the
principles concerning music which we are laying down.  As to the songs and
words themselves which the masters of choruses are to teach and the
character of them, they have been already described by us, and are the same
which, when consecrated and adapted to the different festivals, we said
were to benefit cities by affording them an innocent amusement.

CLEINIAS:  That, again, is true.

ATHENIAN:  Then let him who has been elected a director of music receive
these rules from us as containing the very truth; and may he prosper in his
office!  Let us now proceed to lay down other rules in addition to the
preceding about dancing and gymnastic exercise in general.  Having said
what remained to be said about the teaching of music, let us speak in like
manner about gymnastic.  For boys and girls ought to learn to dance and
practise gymnastic exercises--ought they not?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Then the boys ought to have dancing masters, and the girls
dancing mistresses to exercise them.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Then once more let us summon him who has the chief concern in
the business, the superintendent of youth (i.e. the director of education);
he will have plenty to do, if he is to have the charge of music and
gymnastic.

CLEINIAS:  But how will an old man be able to attend to such great charges?

ATHENIAN:  O my friend, there will be no difficulty, for the law has
already given and will give him permission to select as his assistants in
this charge any citizens, male or female, whom he desires; and he will know
whom he ought to choose, and will be anxious not to make a mistake, from a
due sense of responsibility, and from a consciousness of the importance of
his office, and also because he will consider that if young men have been
and are well brought up, then all things go swimmingly, but if not, it is
not meet to say, nor do we say, what will follow, lest the regarders of
omens should take alarm about our infant state.  Many things have been said
by us about dancing and about gymnastic movements in general; for we
include under gymnastics all military exercises, such as archery, and all
hurling of weapons, and the use of the light shield, and all fighting with
heavy arms, and military evolutions, and movements of armies, and
encampings, and all that relates to horsemanship.  Of all these things
there ought to be public teachers, receiving pay from the state, and their
pupils should be the men and boys in the state, and also the girls and
women, who are to know all these things.  While they are yet girls they
should have practised dancing in arms and the whole art of fighting--when
grown-up women, they should apply themselves to evolutions and tactics, and
the mode of grounding and taking up arms; if for no other reason, yet in
case the whole military force should have to leave the city and carry on
operations of war outside, that those who will have to guard the young and
the rest of the city may be equal to the task; and, on the other hand, when
enemies, whether barbarian or Hellenic, come from without with mighty force
and make a violent assault upon them, and thus compel them to fight for the
possession of the city, which is far from being an impossibility, great
would be the disgrace to the state, if the women had been so miserably
trained that they could not fight for their young, as birds will, against
any creature however strong, and die or undergo any danger, but must
instantly rush to the temples and crowd at the altars and shrines, and
bring upon human nature the reproach, that of all animals man is the most
cowardly!

CLEINIAS:  Such a want of education, Stranger, is certainly an unseemly
thing to happen in a state, as well as a great misfortune.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose that we carry our law to the extent of saying that women
ought not to neglect military matters, but that all citizens, male and
female alike, shall attend to them?

CLEINIAS:  I quite agree.

ATHENIAN:  Of wrestling we have spoken in part, but of what I should call
the most important part we have not spoken, and cannot easily speak without
showing at the same time by gesture as well as in word what we mean; when
word and action combine, and not till then, we shall explain clearly what
has been said, pointing out that of all movements wrestling is most akin to
the military art, and is to be pursued for the sake of this, and not this
for the sake of wrestling.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent.

ATHENIAN:  Enough of wrestling; we will now proceed to speak of other
movements of the body.  Such motion may be in general called dancing, and
is of two kinds:  one of nobler figures, imitating the honourable, the
other of the more ignoble figures, imitating the mean; and of both these
there are two further subdivisions.  Of the serious, one kind is of those
engaged in war and vehement action, and is the exercise of a noble person
and a manly heart; the other exhibits a temperate soul in the enjoyment of
prosperity and modest pleasures, and may be truly called and is the dance
of peace.  The warrior dance is different from the peaceful one, and may be
rightly termed Pyrrhic; this imitates the modes of avoiding blows and
missiles by dropping or giving way, or springing aside, or rising up or
falling down; also the opposite postures which are those of action, as, for
example, the imitation of archery and the hurling of javelins, and of all
sorts of blows.  And when the imitation is of brave bodies and souls, and
the action is direct and muscular, giving for the most part a straight
movement to the limbs of the body--that, I say, is the true sort; but the
opposite is not right.  In the dance of peace what we have to consider is
whether a man bears himself naturally and gracefully, and after the manner
of men who duly conform to the law.  But before proceeding I must
distinguish the dancing about which there is any doubt, from that about
which there is no doubt.  Which is the doubtful kind, and how are the two
to be distinguished?  There are dances of the Bacchic sort, both those in
which, as they say, they imitate drunken men, and which are named after the
Nymphs, and Pan, and Silenuses, and Satyrs; and also those in which
purifications are made or mysteries celebrated,--all this sort of dancing
cannot be rightly defined as having either a peaceful or a warlike
character, or indeed as having any meaning whatever and may, I think, be
most truly described as distinct from the warlike dance, and distinct from
the peaceful, and not suited for a city at all.  There let it lie; and so
leaving it to lie, we will proceed to the dances of war and peace, for with
these we are undoubtedly concerned.  Now the unwarlike muse, which honours
in dance the Gods and the sons of the Gods, is entirely associated with the
consciousness of prosperity; this class may be subdivided into two lesser
classes, of which one is expressive of an escape from some labour or danger
into good, and has greater pleasures, the other expressive of preservation
and increase of former good, in which the pleasure is less exciting;--in
all these cases, every man when the pleasure is greater, moves his body
more, and less when the pleasure is less; and, again, if he be more orderly
and has learned courage from discipline he moves less, but if he be a
coward, and has no training or self-control, he makes greater and more
violent movements, and in general when he is speaking or singing he is not
altogether able to keep his body still; and so out of the imitation of
words in gestures the whole art of dancing has arisen.  And in these
various kinds of imitation one man moves in an orderly, another in a
disorderly manner; and as the ancients may be observed to have given many
names which are according to nature and deserving of praise, so there is an
excellent one which they have given to the dances of men who in their times
of prosperity are moderate in their pleasures--the giver of names, whoever
he was, assigned to them a very true, and poetical, and rational name, when
he called them Emmeleiai, or dances of order, thus establishing two kinds
of dances of the nobler sort, the dance of war which he called the Pyrrhic,
and the dance of peace which he called Emmeleia, or the dance of order;
giving to each their appropriate and becoming name (compare Crat.).  These
things the legislator should indicate in general outline, and the guardian
of the law should enquire into them and search them out, combining dancing
with music, and assigning to the several sacrificial feasts that which is
suitable to them; and when he has consecrated all of them in due order, he
shall for the future change nothing, whether of dance or song. 
Thenceforward the city and the citizens shall continue to have the same
pleasures, themselves being as far as possible alike, and shall live well
and happily.

I have described the dances which are appropriate to noble bodies and
generous souls.  But it is necessary also to consider and know uncomely
persons and thoughts, and those which are intended to produce laughter in
comedy, and have a comic character in respect of style, song, and dance,
and of the imitations which these afford.  For serious things cannot be
understood without laughable things, nor opposites at all without
opposites, if a man is really to have intelligence of either; but he cannot
carry out both in action, if he is to have any degree of virtue.  And for
this very reason he should learn them both, in order that he may not in
ignorance do or say anything which is ridiculous and out of place--he
should command slaves and hired strangers to imitate such things, but he
should never take any serious interest in them himself, nor should any
freeman or freewoman be discovered taking pains to learn them; and there
should always be some element of novelty in the imitation.  Let these then
be laid down, both in law and in our discourse, as the regulations of
laughable amusements which are generally called comedy.  And, if any of the
serious poets, as they are termed, who write tragedy, come to us and say--
'O strangers, may we go to your city and country or may we not, and shall
we bring with us our poetry--what is your will about these matters?'--how
shall we answer the divine men?  I think that our answer should be as
follows (compare Republic):--Best of strangers, we will say to them, we
also according to our ability are tragic poets, and our tragedy is the best
and noblest; for our whole state is an imitation of the best and noblest
life, which we affirm to be indeed the very truth of tragedy.  You are
poets and we are poets, both makers of the same strains, rivals and
antagonists in the noblest of dramas, which true law can alone perfect, as
our hope is.  Do not then suppose that we shall all in a moment allow you
to erect your stage in the agora, or introduce the fair voices of your
actors, speaking above our own, and permit you to harangue our women and
children, and the common people, about our institutions, in language other
than our own, and very often the opposite of our own.  For a state would be
mad which gave you this licence, until the magistrates had determined
whether your poetry might be recited, and was fit for publication or not. 
Wherefore, O ye sons and scions of the softer Muses, first of all show your
songs to the magistrates, and let them compare them with our own, and if
they are the same or better we will give you a chorus; but if not, then, my
friends, we cannot.  Let these, then, be the customs ordained by law about
all dances and the teaching of them, and let matters relating to slaves be
separated from those relating to masters, if you do not object.

CLEINIAS:  We can have no hesitation in assenting when you put the matter
thus.

ATHENIAN:  There still remain three studies suitable for freemen. 
Arithmetic is one of them; the measurement of length, surface, and depth is
the second; and the third has to do with the revolutions of the stars in
relation to one another.  Not every one has need to toil through all these
things in a strictly scientific manner, but only a few, and who they are to
be we will hereafter indicate at the end, which will be the proper place;
not to know what is necessary for mankind in general, and what is the
truth, is disgraceful to every one:  and yet to enter into these matters
minutely is neither easy, nor at all possible for every one; but there is
something in them which is necessary and cannot be set aside, and probably
he who made the proverb about God originally had this in view when he said,
that 'not even God himself can fight against necessity;'--he meant, if I am
not mistaken, divine necessity; for as to the human necessities of which
the many speak, when they talk in this manner, nothing can be more
ridiculous than such an application of the words.

CLEINIAS:  And what necessities of knowledge are there, Stranger, which are
divine and not human?

ATHENIAN:  I conceive them to be those of which he who has no use nor any
knowledge at all cannot be a God, or demi-god, or hero to mankind, or able
to take any serious thought or charge of them.  And very unlike a divine
man would he be, who is unable to count one, two, three, or to distinguish
odd and even numbers (compare Republic), or is unable to count at all, or
reckon night and day, and who is totally unacquainted with the revolution
of the sun and moon, and the other stars.  There would be great folly in
supposing that all these are not necessary parts of knowledge to him who
intends to know anything about the highest kinds of knowledge; but which
these are, and how many there are of them, and when they are to be learned,
and what is to be learned together and what apart, and the whole
correlation of them, must be rightly apprehended first; and these leading
the way we may proceed to the other parts of knowledge.  For so necessity
grounded in nature constrains us, against which we say that no God
contends, or ever will contend.

CLEINIAS:  I think, Stranger, that what you have now said is very true and
agreeable to nature.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, Cleinias, that is so.  But it is difficult for the
legislator to begin with these studies; at a more convenient time we will
make regulations for them.

CLEINIAS:  You seem, Stranger, to be afraid of our habitual ignorance of
the subject:  there is no reason why that should prevent you from speaking
out.

ATHENIAN:  I certainly am afraid of the difficulties to which you allude,
but I am still more afraid of those who apply themselves to this sort of
knowledge, and apply themselves badly.  For entire ignorance is not so
terrible or extreme an evil, and is far from being the greatest of all; too
much cleverness and too much learning, accompanied with an ill bringing up,
are far more fatal.  (Compare Republic.)

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  All freemen, I conceive, should learn as much of these branches
of knowledge as every child in Egypt is taught when he learns the alphabet. 
In that country arithmetical games have been invented for the use of mere
children, which they learn as a pleasure and amusement.  They have to
distribute apples and garlands, using the same number sometimes for a
larger and sometimes for a lesser number of persons; and they arrange
pugilists and wrestlers as they pair together by lot or remain over, and
show how their turns come in natural order.  Another mode of amusing them
is to distribute vessels, sometimes of gold, brass, silver, and the like,
intermixed with one another, sometimes of one metal only; as I was saying
they adapt to their amusement the numbers in common use, and in this way
make more intelligible to their pupils the arrangements and movements of
armies and expeditions, in the management of a household they make people
more useful to themselves, and more wide awake; and again in measurements
of things which have length, and breadth, and depth, they free us from that
natural ignorance of all these things which is so ludicrous and
disgraceful.

CLEINIAS:  What kind of ignorance do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  O my dear Cleinias, I, like yourself, have late in life heard
with amazement of our ignorance in these matters; to me we appear to be
more like pigs than men, and I am quite ashamed, not only of myself, but of
all Hellenes.

CLEINIAS:  About what?  Say, Stranger, what you mean.

ATHENIAN:  I will; or rather I will show you my meaning by a question, and
do you please to answer me:  You know, I suppose, what length is?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And what breadth is?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And you know that these are two distinct things, and that there
is a third thing called depth?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  And do not all these seem to you to be commensurable with
themselves?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  That is to say, length is naturally commensurable with length,
and breadth with breadth, and depth in like manner with depth?

CLEINIAS:  Undoubtedly.

ATHENIAN:  But if some things are commensurable and others wholly
incommensurable, and you think that all things are commensurable, what is
your position in regard to them?

CLEINIAS:  Clearly, far from good.

ATHENIAN:  Concerning length and breadth when compared with depth, or
breadth and length when compared with one another, are not all the Hellenes
agreed that these are commensurable with one another in some way?

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  But if they are absolutely incommensurable, and yet all of us
regard them as commensurable, have we not reason to be ashamed of our
compatriots; and might we not say to them:--O ye best of Hellenes, is not
this one of the things of which we were saying that not to know them is
disgraceful, and of which to have a bare knowledge only is no great
distinction?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And there are other things akin to these, in which there spring
up other errors of the same family.

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  The natures of commensurable and incommensurable quantities in
their relation to one another.  A man who is good for anything ought to be
able, when he thinks, to distinguish them; and different persons should
compete with one another in asking questions, which will be a far better
and more graceful way of passing their time than the old man's game of
draughts.

CLEINIAS:  I dare say; and these pastimes are not so very unlike a game of
draughts.

ATHENIAN:  And these, as I maintain, Cleinias, are the studies which our
youth ought to learn, for they are innocent and not difficult; the learning
of them will be an amusement, and they will benefit the state.  If any one
is of another mind, let him say what he has to say.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then if these studies are such as we maintain, we will include
them; if not, they shall be excluded.

CLEINIAS:  Assuredly:  but may we not now, Stranger, prescribe these
studies as necessary, and so fill up the lacunae of our laws?

ATHENIAN:  They shall be regarded as pledges which may be hereafter
redeemed and removed from our state, if they do not please either us who
give them, or you who accept them.

CLEINIAS:  A fair condition.

ATHENIAN:  Next let us see whether we are or are not willing that the study
of astronomy shall be proposed for our youth.  (Compare Republic.)

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Here occurs a strange phenomenon, which certainly cannot in any
point of view be tolerated.

CLEINIAS:  To what are you referring?

ATHENIAN:  Men say that we ought not to enquire into the supreme God and
the nature of the universe, nor busy ourselves in searching out the causes
of things, and that such enquiries are impious; whereas the very opposite
is the truth.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Perhaps what I am saying may seem paradoxical, and at variance
with the usual language of age.  But when any one has any good and true
notion which is for the advantage of the state and in every way acceptable
to God, he cannot abstain from expressing it.

CLEINIAS:  Your words are reasonable enough; but shall we find any good or
true notion about the stars?

ATHENIAN:  My good friends, at this hour all of us Hellenes tell lies, if I
may use such an expression, about those great Gods, the Sun and the Moon.

CLEINIAS:  Lies of what nature?

ATHENIAN:  We say that they and divers other stars do not keep the same
path, and we call them planets or wanderers.

CLEINIAS:  Very true, Stranger; and in the course of my life I have often
myself seen the morning star and the evening star and divers others not
moving in their accustomed course, but wandering out of their path in all
manner of ways, and I have seen the sun and moon doing what we all know
that they do.

ATHENIAN:  Just so, Megillus and Cleinias; and I maintain that our citizens
and our youth ought to learn about the nature of the Gods in heaven, so far
as to be able to offer sacrifices and pray to them in pious language, and
not to blaspheme about them.

CLEINIAS:  There you are right, if such a knowledge be only attainable; and
if we are wrong in our mode of speaking now, and can be better instructed
and learn to use better language, then I quite agree with you that such a
degree of knowledge as will enable us to speak rightly should be acquired
by us.  And now do you try to explain to us your whole meaning, and we, on
our part, will endeavour to understand you.

ATHENIAN:  There is some difficulty in understanding my meaning, but not a
very great one, nor will any great length of time be required.  And of this
I am myself a proof; for I did not know these things long ago, nor in the
days of my youth, and yet I can explain them to you in a brief space of
time; whereas if they had been difficult I could certainly never have
explained them all, old as I am, to old men like yourselves.

CLEINIAS:  True; but what is this study which you describe as wonderful and
fitting for youth to learn, but of which we are ignorant?  Try and explain
the nature of it to us as clearly as you can.

ATHENIAN:  I will.  For, O my good friends, that other doctrine about the
wandering of the sun and the moon and the other stars is not the truth, but
the very reverse of the truth.  Each of them moves in the same path--not in
many paths, but in one only, which is circular, and the varieties are only
apparent.  Nor are we right in supposing that the swiftest of them is the
slowest, nor conversely, that the slowest is the quickest.  And if what I
say is true, only just imagine that we had a similar notion about horses
running at Olympia, or about men who ran in the long course, and that we
addressed the swiftest as the slowest and the slowest as the swiftest, and
sang the praises of the vanquished as though he were the victor,--in that
case our praises would not be true, nor very agreeable to the runners,
though they be but men; and now, to commit the same error about the Gods
which would have been ludicrous and erroneous in the case of men,--is not
that ludicrous and erroneous?

CLEINIAS:  Worse than ludicrous, I should say.

ATHENIAN:  At all events, the Gods cannot like us to be spreading a false
report of them.

CLEINIAS:  Most true, if such is the fact.

ATHENIAN:  And if we can show that such is really the fact, then all these
matters ought to be learned so far as is necessary for the avoidance of
impiety; but if we cannot, they may be let alone, and let this be our
decision.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Enough of laws relating to education and learning.  But hunting
and similar pursuits in like manner claim our attention.  For the
legislator appears to have a duty imposed upon him which goes beyond mere
legislation.  There is something over and above law which lies in a region
between admonition and law, and has several times occurred to us in the
course of discussion; for example, in the education of very young children
there were things, as we maintain, which are not to be defined, and to
regard them as matters of positive law is a great absurdity.  Now, our laws
and the whole constitution of our state having been thus delineated, the
praise of the virtuous citizen is not complete when he is described as the
person who serves the laws best and obeys them most, but the higher form of
praise is that which describes him as the good citizen who passes through
life undefiled and is obedient to the words of the legislator, both when he
is giving laws and when he assigns praise and blame.  This is the truest
word that can be spoken in praise of a citizen; and the true legislator
ought not only to write his laws, but also to interweave with them all such
things as seem to him honourable and dishonourable.  And the perfect
citizen ought to seek to strengthen these no less than the principles of
law which are sanctioned by punishments.  I will adduce an example which
will clear up my meaning, and will be a sort of witness to my words. 
Hunting is of wide extent, and has a name under which many things are
included, for there is a hunting of creatures in the water, and of
creatures in the air, and there is a great deal of hunting of land animals
of all kinds, and not of wild beasts only.  The hunting after man is also
worthy of consideration; there is the hunting after him in war, and there
is often a hunting after him in the way of friendship, which is praised and
also blamed; and there is thieving, and the hunting which is practised by
robbers, and that of armies against armies.  Now the legislator, in laying
down laws about hunting, can neither abstain from noting these things, nor
can he make threatening ordinances which will assign rules and penalties
about all of them.  What is he to do?  He will have to praise and blame
hunting with a view to the exercise and pursuits of youth.  And, on the
other hand, the young man must listen obediently; neither pleasure nor pain
should hinder him, and he should regard as his standard of action the
praises and injunctions of the legislator rather than the punishments which
he imposes by law.  This being premised, there will follow next in order
moderate praise and censure of hunting; the praise being assigned to that
kind which will make the souls of young men better, and the censure to that
which has the opposite effect.  And now let us address young men in the
form of a prayer for their welfare:  O friends, we will say to them, may no
desire or love of hunting in the sea, or of angling or of catching the
creatures in the waters, ever take possession of you, either when you are
awake or when you are asleep, by hook or with weels, which latter is a very
lazy contrivance; and let not any desire of catching men and of piracy by
sea enter into your souls and make you cruel and lawless hunters.  And as
to the desire of thieving in town or country, may it never enter into your
most passing thoughts; nor let the insidious fancy of catching birds, which
is hardly worthy of freemen, come into the head of any youth.  There
remains therefore for our athletes only the hunting and catching of land
animals, of which the one sort is called hunting by night, in which the
hunters sleep in turn and are lazy; this is not to be commended any more
than that which has intervals of rest, in which the wild strength of beasts
is subdued by nets and snares, and not by the victory of a laborious
spirit.  Thus, only the best kind of hunting is allowed at all--that of
quadrupeds, which is carried on with horses and dogs and men's own persons,
and they get the victory over the animals by running them down and striking
them and hurling at them, those who have a care of godlike manhood taking
them with their own hands.  The praise and blame which is assigned to all
these things has now been declared; and let the law be as follows:--Let no
one hinder these who verily are sacred hunters from following the chase
wherever and whithersoever they will; but the hunter by night, who trusts
to his nets and gins, shall not be allowed to hunt anywhere.  The fowler in
the mountains and waste places shall be permitted, but on cultivated ground
and on consecrated wilds he shall not be permitted; and any one who meets
him may stop him.  As to the hunter in waters, he may hunt anywhere except
in harbours or sacred streams or marshes or pools, provided only that he do
not pollute the water with poisonous juices.  And now we may say that all
our enactments about education are complete.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.


BOOK VIII.

ATHENIAN:  Next, with the help of the Delphian oracle, we have to institute
festivals and make laws about them, and to determine what sacrifices will
be for the good of the city, and to what Gods they shall be offered; but
when they shall be offered, and how often, may be partly regulated by us.

CLEINIAS:  The number--yes.

ATHENIAN:  Then we will first determine the number; and let the whole
number be 365--one for every day,--so that one magistrate at least will
sacrifice daily to some God or demi-god on behalf of the city, and the
citizens, and their possessions.  And the interpreters, and priests, and
priestesses, and prophets shall meet, and, in company with the guardians of
the law, ordain those things which the legislator of necessity omits; and I
may remark that they are the very persons who ought to take note of what is
omitted (compare Republic).  The law will say that there are twelve feasts
dedicated to the twelve Gods, after whom the several tribes are named; and
that to each of them they shall sacrifice every month, and appoint
choruses, and musical and gymnastic contests, assigning them so as to suit
the Gods and seasons of the year.  And they shall have festivals for women,
distinguishing those which ought to be separated from the men's festivals,
and those which ought not.  Further, they shall not confuse the infernal
deities and their rites with the Gods who are termed heavenly and their
rites, but shall separate them, giving to Pluto his own in the twelfth
month, which is sacred to him, according to the law.  To such a deity
warlike men should entertain no aversion, but they should honour him as
being always the best friend of man (compare Crat.).  For the connexion of
soul and body is no way better than the dissolution of them, as I am ready
to maintain quite seriously.  Moreover, those who would regulate these
matters rightly should consider, that our city among existing cities has no
fellow, either in respect of leisure or command and of the necessaries of
life, and that like an individual she ought to live happily.  And those who
would live happily should in the first place do no wrong to one another,
and ought not themselves to be wronged by others; to attain the first is
not difficult, but there is great difficulty in acquiring the power of not
being wronged.  No man can be perfectly secure against wrong, unless he has
become perfectly good; and cities are like individuals in this, for a city
if good has a life of peace, but if evil, a life of war within and without. 
Wherefore the citizens ought to practise war--not in time of war, but
rather while they are at peace.  And every city which has any sense, should
take the field at least for one day in every month; and for more if the
magistrates think fit, having no regard to winter cold or summer heat; and
they should go out en masse, including their wives and their children, when
the magistrates determine to lead forth the whole people, or in separate
portions when summoned by them; and they should always provide that there
should be games and sacrificial feasts, and they should have tournaments,
imitating in as lively a manner as they can real battles.  And they should
distribute prizes of victory and valour to the competitors, passing
censures and encomiums on one another according to the characters which
they bear in the contests and their whole life, honouring him who seems to
be the best, and blaming him who is the opposite.  And let poets celebrate
the victors,--not however every poet, but only one who in the first place
is not less than fifty years of age; nor should he be one who, although he
may have musical and poetical gifts, has never in his life done any noble
or illustrious action; but those who are themselves good and also
honourable in the state, creators of noble actions--let their poems be
sung, even though they be not very musical.  And let the judgment of them
rest with the instructor of youth (i.e. the director of education) and the
other guardians of the laws, who shall give them this privilege, and they
alone shall be free to sing; but the rest of the world shall not have this
liberty.  Nor shall any one dare to sing a song which has not been approved
by the judgment of the guardians of the laws, not even if his strain be
sweeter than the songs of Thamyras and Orpheus; but only such poems as have
been judged sacred and dedicated to the Gods, and such as are the works of
good men, in which praise of blame has been awarded and which have been
deemed to fulfil their design fairly.

The regulations about war, and about liberty of speech in poetry, ought to
apply equally to men and women.  The legislator may be supposed to argue
the question in his own mind:--Who are my citizens for whom I have set in
order the city?  Are they not competitors in the greatest of all contests
(compare Republic), and have they not innumerable rivals?  To be sure, will
be the natural reply.  Well, but if we were training boxers, or
pancratiasts, or any other sort of athletes, would they never meet until
the hour of contest arrived; and should we do nothing to prepare ourselves
previously by daily practice?  Surely, if we were boxers, we should have
been learning to fight for many days before, and exercising ourselves in
imitating all those blows and wards which we were intending to use in the
hour of conflict; and in order that we might come as near to reality as
possible, instead of cestuses we should put on boxing gloves, that the
blows and the wards might be practised by us to the utmost of our power. 
And if there were a lack of competitors, the ridicule of fools would not
deter us from hanging up a lifeless image and practising at that.  Or if we
had no adversary at all, animate or inanimate, should we not venture in the
dearth of antagonists to spar by ourselves?  In what other manner could we
ever study the art of self-defence?

CLEINIAS:  The way which you mention, Stranger, would be the only way.

ATHENIAN:  And shall the warriors of our city, who are destined when
occasion calls to enter the greatest of all contests, and to fight for
their lives, and their children, and their property, and the whole city, be
worse prepared than boxers?  And will the legislator, because he is afraid
that their practising with one another may appear to some ridiculous,
abstain from commanding them to go out and fight; will he not ordain that
soldiers shall perform lesser exercises without arms every day, making
dancing and all gymnastic tend to this end; and also will he not require
that they shall practise some gymnastic exercises, greater as well as
lesser, as often as every month; and that they shall have contests one with
another in every part of the country, seizing upon posts and lying in
ambush, and imitating in every respect the reality of war; fighting with
boxing-gloves and hurling javelins, and using weapons somewhat dangerous,
and as nearly as possible like the true ones, in order that the sport may
not be altogether without fear, but may have terrors and to a certain
degree show the man who has and who has not courage; and that the honour
and dishonour which are assigned to them respectively, may prepare the
whole city for the true conflict of life?  If any one dies in these mimic
contests, the homicide is involuntary, and we will make the slayer, when he
has been purified according to law, to be pure of blood, considering that
if a few men should die, others as good as they will be born; but that if
fear is dead, then the citizens will never find a test of superior and
inferior natures, which is a far greater evil to the state than the loss of
a few.

CLEINIAS:  We are quite agreed, Stranger, that we should legislate about
such things, and that the whole state should practise them.

ATHENIAN:  And what is the reason that dances and contests of this sort
hardly ever exist in states, at least not to any extent worth speaking of? 
Is this due to the ignorance of mankind and their legislators?

CLEINIAS:  Perhaps.

ATHENIAN:  Certainly not, sweet Cleinias; there are two causes, which are
quite enough to account for the deficiency.

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  One cause is the love of wealth, which wholly absorbs men, and
never for a moment allows them to think of anything but their own private
possessions; on this the soul of every citizen hangs suspended, and can
attend to nothing but his daily gain; mankind are ready to learn any branch
of knowledge, and to follow any pursuit which tends to this end, and they
laugh at every other:--that is one reason why a city will not be in earnest
about such contests or any other good and honourable pursuit.  But from an
insatiable love of gold and silver, every man will stoop to any art or
contrivance, seemly or unseemly, in the hope of becoming rich; and will
make no objection to performing any action, holy, or unholy and utterly
base, if only like a beast he have the power of eating and drinking all
kinds of things, and procuring for himself in every sort of way the
gratification of his lusts.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Let this, then, be deemed one of the causes which prevent states
from pursuing in an efficient manner the art of war, or any other noble
aim, but makes the orderly and temperate part of mankind into merchants,
and captains of ships, and servants, and converts the valiant sort into
thieves and burglars and robbers of temples, and violent, tyrannical
persons; many of whom are not without ability, but they are unfortunate. 
(Compare Republic.)

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Must not they be truly unfortunate whose souls are compelled to
pass through life always hungering?

CLEINIAS:  Then that is one cause, Stranger; but you spoke of another.

ATHENIAN:  Thank you for reminding me.

CLEINIAS:  The insatiable lifelong love of wealth, as you were saying, is
one clause which absorbs mankind, and prevents them from rightly practising
the arts of war:--Granted; and now tell me, what is the other?

ATHENIAN:  Do you imagine that I delay because I am in a perplexity?

CLEINIAS:  No; but we think that you are too severe upon the money-loving
temper, of which you seem in the present discussion to have a peculiar
dislike.

ATHENIAN:  That is a very fair rebuke, Cleinias; and I will now proceed to
the second cause.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  I say that governments are a cause--democracy, oligarchy,
tyranny, concerning which I have often spoken in the previous discourse; or
rather governments they are not, for none of them exercises a voluntary
rule over voluntary subjects; but they may be truly called states of
discord, in which while the government is voluntary, the subjects always
obey against their will, and have to be coerced; and the ruler fears the
subject, and will not, if he can help, allow him to become either noble, or
rich, or strong, or valiant, or warlike at all (compare Arist. Pol.). 
These two are the chief causes of almost all evils, and of the evils of
which I have been speaking they are notably the causes.  But our state has
escaped both of them; for her citizens have the greatest leisure, and they
are not subject to one another, and will, I think, be made by these laws
the reverse of lovers of money.  Such a constitution may be reasonably
supposed to be the only one existing which will accept the education which
we have described, and the martial pastimes which have been perfected
according to our idea.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Then next we must remember, about all gymnastic contests, that
only the warlike sort of them are to be practised and to have prizes of
victory; and those which are not military are to be given up.  The military
sort had better be completely described and established by law; and first,
let us speak of running and swiftness.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Certainly the most military of all qualities is general activity
of body, whether of foot or hand.  For escaping or for capturing an enemy,
quickness of foot is required; but hand-to-hand conflict and combat need
vigour and strength.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Neither of them can attain their greatest efficiency without
arms.

CLEINIAS:  How can they?

ATHENIAN:  Then our herald, in accordance with the prevailing practice,
will first summon the runner;--he will appear armed, for to an unarmed
competitor we will not give a prize.  And he shall enter first who is to
run the single course bearing arms; next, he who is to run the double
course; third, he who is to run the horse-course; and fourthly, he who is
to run the long course; the fifth whom we start, shall be the first sent
forth in heavy armour, and shall run a course of sixty stadia to some
temple of Ares--and we will send forth another, whom we will style the more
heavily armed, to run over smoother ground.  There remains the archer; and
he shall run in the full equipments of an archer a distance of 100 stadia
over mountains, and across every sort of country, to a temple of Apollo and
Artemis; this shall be the order of the contest, and we will wait for them
until they return, and will give a prize to the conqueror in each.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Let us suppose that there are three kinds of contests,--one of
boys, another of beardless youths, and a third of men.  For the youths we
will fix the length of the contest at two-thirds, and for the boys at half
of the entire course, whether they contend as archers or as heavy-armed. 
Touching the women, let the girls who are not grown up compete naked in the
stadium and the double course, and the horse-course and the long course,
and let them run on the race-ground itself; those who are thirteen years of
age and upwards until their marriage shall continue to share in contests if
they are not more than twenty, and shall be compelled to run up to
eighteen; and they shall descend into the arena in suitable dresses.  Let
these be the regulations about contests in running both for men and women.

Respecting contests of strength, instead of wrestling and similar contests
of the heavier sort, we will institute conflicts in armour of one against
one, and two against two, and so on up to ten against ten.  As to what a
man ought not to suffer or do, and to what extent, in order to gain the
victory--as in wrestling, the masters of the art have laid down what is
fair and what is not fair, so in fighting in armour--we ought to call in
skilful persons, who shall judge for us and be our assessors in the work of
legislation; they shall say who deserves to be victor in combats of this
sort, and what he is not to do or have done to him, and in like manner what
rule determines who is defeated; and let these ordinances apply to women
until they are married as well as to men.  The pancration shall have a
counterpart in a combat of the light-armed; they shall contend with bows
and with light shields and with javelins and in the throwing of stones by
slings and by hand:  and laws shall be made about it, and rewards and
prizes given to him who best fulfils the ordinances of the law.

Next in order we shall have to legislate about the horse contests.  Now we
do not need many horses, for they cannot be of much use in a country like
Crete, and hence we naturally do not take great pains about the rearing of
them or about horse races.  There is no one who keeps a chariot among us,
and any rivalry in such matters would be altogether out of place; there
would be no sense nor any shadow of sense in instituting contests which are
not after the manner of our country.  And therefore we give our prizes for
single horses,--for colts who have not yet cast their teeth, and for those
who are intermediate, and for the full-grown horses themselves; and thus
our equestrian games will accord with the nature of the country.  Let them
have conflict and rivalry in these matters in accordance with the law, and
let the colonels and generals of horse decide together about all courses
and about the armed competitors in them.  But we have nothing to say to the
unarmed either in gymnastic exercises or in these contests.  On the other
hand, the Cretan bowman or javelin-man who fights in armour on horseback is
useful, and therefore we may as well place a competition of this sort among
our amusements.  Women are not to be forced to compete by laws and
ordinances; but if from previous training they have acquired the habit and
are strong enough and like to take part, let them do so, girls as well as
boys, and no blame to them.

Thus the competition in gymnastic and the mode of learning it have been
described; and we have spoken also of the toils of the contest, and of
daily exercises under the superintendence of masters.  Likewise, what
relates to music has been, for the most part, completed.  But as to
rhapsodes and the like, and the contests of choruses which are to perform
at feasts, all this shall be arranged when the months and days and years
have been appointed for Gods and demi-gods, whether every third year, or
again every fifth year, or in whatever way or manner the Gods may put into
men's minds the distribution and order of them.  At the same time, we may
expect that the musical contests will be celebrated in their turn by the
command of the judges and the director of education and the guardians of
the law meeting together for this purpose, and themselves becoming
legislators of the times and nature and conditions of the choral contests
and of dancing in general.  What they ought severally to be in language and
song, and in the admixture of harmony with rhythm and the dance, has been
often declared by the original legislator; and his successors ought to
follow him, making the games and sacrifices duly to correspond at fitting
times, and appointing public festivals.  It is not difficult to determine
how these and the like matters may have a regular order; nor, again, will
the alteration of them do any great good or harm to the state.  There is,
however, another matter of great importance and difficulty, concerning
which God should legislate, if there were any possibility of obtaining from
Him an ordinance about it.  But seeing that divine aid is not to be had,
there appears to be a need of some bold man who specially honours plainness
of speech, and will say outright what he thinks best for the city and
citizens,--ordaining what is good and convenient for the whole state amid
the corruptions of human souls, opposing the mightiest lusts, and having no
man his helper but himself standing alone and following reason only.

CLEINIAS:  What is this, Stranger, that you are saying?  For we do not as
yet understand your meaning.

ATHENIAN:  Very likely; I will endeavour to explain myself more clearly. 
When I came to the subject of education, I beheld young men and maidens
holding friendly intercourse with one another.  And there naturally arose
in my mind a sort of apprehension--I could not help thinking how one is to
deal with a city in which youths and maidens are well nurtured, and have
nothing to do, and are not undergoing the excessive and servile toils which
extinguish wantonness, and whose only cares during their whole life are
sacrifices and festivals and dances.  How, in such a state as this, will
they abstain from desires which thrust many a man and woman into perdition;
and from which reason, assuming the functions of law, commands them to
abstain?  The ordinances already made may possibly get the better of most
of these desires; the prohibition of excessive wealth is a very
considerable gain in the direction of temperance, and the whole education
of our youth imposes a law of moderation on them; moreover, the eye of the
rulers is required always to watch over the young, and never to lose sight
of them; and these provisions do, as far as human means can effect
anything, exercise a regulating influence upon the desires in general.  But
how can we take precautions against the unnatural loves of either sex, from
which innumerable evils have come upon individuals and cities?  How shall
we devise a remedy and way of escape out of so great a danger?  Truly,
Cleinias, here is a difficulty.  In many ways Crete and Lacedaemon furnish
a great help to those who make peculiar laws; but in the matter of love, as
we are alone, I must confess that they are quite against us.  For if any
one following nature should lay down the law which existed before the days
of Laius, and denounce these lusts as contrary to nature, adducing the
animals as a proof that such unions were monstrous, he might prove his
point, but he would be wholly at variance with the custom of your states. 
Further, they are repugnant to a principle which we say that a legislator
should always observe; for we are always enquiring which of our enactments
tends to virtue and which not.  And suppose we grant that these loves are
accounted by law to be honourable, or at least not disgraceful, in what
degree will they contribute to virtue?  Will such passions implant in the
soul of him who is seduced the habit of courage, or in the soul of the
seducer the principle of temperance?  Who will ever believe this?--or
rather, who will not blame the effeminacy of him who yields to pleasures
and is unable to hold out against them?  Will not all men censure as
womanly him who imitates the woman?  And who would ever think of
establishing such a practice by law?  Certainly no one who had in his mind
the image of true law.  How can we prove that what I am saying is true?  He
who would rightly consider these matters must see the nature of friendship
and desire, and of these so-called loves, for they are of two kinds, and
out of the two arises a third kind, having the same name; and this
similarity of name causes all the difficulty and obscurity.

CLEINIAS:  How is that?

ATHENIAN:  Dear is the like in virtue to the like, and the equal to the
equal; dear also, though unlike, is he who has abundance to him who is in
want.  And when either of these friendships becomes excessive, we term the
excess love.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  The friendship which arises from contraries is horrible and
coarse, and has often no tie of communion; but that which arises from
likeness is gentle, and has a tie of communion which lasts through life. 
As to the mixed sort which is made up of them both, there is, first of all,
a difficulty in determining what he who is possessed by this third love
desires; moreover, he is drawn different ways, and is in doubt between the
two principles; the one exhorting him to enjoy the beauty of youth, and the
other forbidding him.  For the one is a lover of the body, and hungers
after beauty, like ripe fruit, and would fain satisfy himself without any
regard to the character of the beloved; the other holds the desire of the
body to be a secondary matter, and looking rather than loving and with his
soul desiring the soul of the other in a becoming manner, regards the
satisfaction of the bodily love as wantonness (compare Phaedr.); he
reverences and respects temperance and courage and magnanimity and wisdom,
and wishes to live chastely with the chaste object of his affection.  Now
the sort of love which is made up of the other two is that which we have
described as the third.  Seeing then that there are these three sorts of
love, ought the law to prohibit and forbid them all to exist among us?  Is
it not rather clear that we should wish to have in the state the love which
is of virtue and which desires the beloved youth to be the best possible;
and the other two, if possible, we should hinder?  What do you say, friend
Megillus?

MEGILLUS:  I think, Stranger, that you are perfectly right in what you have
been now saying.

ATHENIAN:  I knew well, my friend, that I should obtain your assent, which
I accept, and therefore have no need to analyze your custom any further. 
Cleinias shall be prevailed upon to give me his assent at some other time. 
Enough of this; and now let us proceed to the laws.

MEGILLUS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Upon reflection I see a way of imposing the law, which, in one
respect, is easy, but, in another, is of the utmost difficulty.

MEGILLUS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  We are all aware that most men, in spite of their lawless
natures, are very strictly and precisely restrained from intercourse with
the fair, and this is not at all against their will, but entirely with
their will.

MEGILLUS:  When do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  When any one has a brother or sister who is fair; and about a
son or daughter the same unwritten law holds, and is a most perfect
safeguard, so that no open or secret connexion ever takes place between
them.  Nor does the thought of such a thing ever enter at all into the
minds of most of them.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Does not a little word extinguish all pleasures of that sort?

MEGILLUS:  What word?

ATHENIAN:  The declaration that they are unholy, hated of God, and most
infamous; and is not the reason of this that no one has ever said the
opposite, but every one from his earliest childhood has heard men speaking
in the same manner about them always and everywhere, whether in comedy or
in the graver language of tragedy?  When the poet introduces on the stage a
Thyestes or an Oedipus, or a Macareus having secret intercourse with his
sister, he represents him, when found out, ready to kill himself as the
penalty of his sin.

MEGILLUS:  You are very right in saying that tradition, if no breath of
opposition ever assails it, has a marvellous power.

ATHENIAN:  Am I not also right in saying that the legislator who wants to
master any of the passions which master man may easily know how to subdue
them?  He will consecrate the tradition of their evil character among all,
slaves and freemen, women and children, throughout the city:--that will be
the surest foundation of the law which he can make.

MEGILLUS:  Yes; but will he ever succeed in making all mankind use the same
language about them?

ATHENIAN:  A good objection; but was I not just now saying that I had a way
to make men use natural love and abstain from unnatural, not intentionally
destroying the seeds of human increase, or sowing them in stony places, in
which they will take no root; and that I would command them to abstain too
from any female field of increase in which that which is sown is not likely
to grow?  Now if a law to this effect could only be made perpetual, and
gain an authority such as already prevents intercourse of parents and
children--such a law, extending to other sensual desires, and conquering
them, would be the source of ten thousand blessings.  For, in the first
place, moderation is the appointment of nature, and deters men from all
frenzy and madness of love, and from all adulteries and immoderate use of
meats and drinks, and makes them good friends to their own wives.  And
innumerable other benefits would result if such a could only be enforced. 
I can imagine some lusty youth who is standing by, and who, on hearing this
enactment, declares in scurrilous terms that we are making foolish and
impossible laws, and fills the world with his outcry.  And therefore I said
that I knew a way of enacting and perpetuating such a law, which was very
easy in one respect, but in another most difficult.  There is no difficulty
in seeing that such a law is possible, and in what way; for, as I was
saying, the ordinance once consecrated would master the soul of every man,
and terrify him into obedience.  But matters have now come to such a pass
that even then the desired result seems as if it could not be attained,
just as the continuance of an entire state in the practice of common meals
is also deemed impossible.  And although this latter is partly disproven by
the fact of their existence among you, still even in your cities the common
meals of women would be regarded as unnatural and impossible.  I was
thinking of the rebelliousness of the human heart when I said that the
permanent establishment of these things is very difficult.

MEGILLUS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Shall I try and find some sort of persuasive argument which will
prove to you that such enactments are possible, and not beyond human
nature?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Is a man more likely to abstain from the pleasures of love and
to do what he is bidden about them, when his body is in a good condition,
or when he is in an ill condition, and out of training?

CLEINIAS:  He will be far more temperate when he is in training.

ATHENIAN:  And have we not heard of Iccus of Tarentum, who, with a view to
the Olympic and other contests, in his zeal for his art, ind also because
he was of a manly and temperate disposition, never had any connexion with a
woman or a youth during the whole time of his training?  And the same is
said of Crison and Astylus and Diopompus and many others; and yet,
Cleinias, they were far worse educated in their minds than your and my
citizens, and in their bodies far more lusty.

CLEINIAS:  No doubt this fact has been often affirmed positively by the
ancients of these athletes. 

ATHENIAN:  And had they the courage to abstain from what is ordinarily
deemed a pleasure for the sake of a victory in wrestling, running, and the
like; and shall our young men be incapable of a similar endurance for the
sake of a much nobler victory, which is the noblest of all, as from their
youth upwards we will tell them, charming them, as we hope, into the belief
of this by tales and sayings and songs?

CLEINIAS:  Of what victory are you speaking?

ATHENIAN:  Of the victory over pleasure, which if they win, they will live
happily; or if they are conquered, the reverse of happily.  And, further,
may we not suppose that the fear of impiety will enable them to master that
which other inferior people have mastered?

CLEINIAS:  I dare say.

ATHENIAN:  And since we have reached this point in our legislation, and
have fallen into a difficulty by reason of the vices of mankind, I affirm
that our ordinance should simply run in the following terms:  Our citizens
ought not to fall below the nature of birds and beasts in general, who are
born in great multitudes, and yet remain until the age for procreation
virgin and unmarried, but when they have reached the proper time of life
are coupled, male and female, and lovingly pair together, and live the rest
of their lives in holiness and innocence, abiding firmly in their original
compact:--surely, we will say to them, you should be better than the
animals.  But if they are corrupted by the other Hellenes and the common
practice of barbarians, and they see with their eyes and hear with their
ears of the so-called free love everywhere prevailing among them, and they
themselves are not able to get the better of the temptation, the guardians
of the law, exercising the functions of lawgivers, shall devise a second
law against them.

CLEINIAS:  And what law would you advise them to pass if this one failed?

ATHENIAN:  Clearly, Cleinias, the one which would naturally follow.

CLEINIAS:  What is that?

ATHENIAN:  Our citizens should not allow pleasures to strengthen with
indulgence, but should by toil divert the aliment and exuberance of them
into other parts of the body; and this will happen if no immodesty be
allowed in the practice of love.  Then they will be ashamed of frequent
intercourse, and they will find pleasure, if seldom enjoyed, to be a less
imperious mistress.  They should not be found out doing anything of the
sort.  Concealment shall be honourable, and sanctioned by custom and made
law by unwritten prescription; on the other hand, to be detected shall be
esteemed dishonourable, but not, to abstain wholly.  In this way there will
be a second legal standard of honourable and dishonourable, involving a
second notion of right.  Three principles will comprehend all those corrupt
natures whom we call inferior to themselves, and who form but one class,
and will compel them not to transgress.

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  The principle of piety, the love of honour, and the desire of
beauty, not in the body but in the soul.  These are, perhaps, romantic
aspirations; but they are the noblest of aspirations, if they could only be
realized in all states, and, God willing, in the matter of love we may be
able to enforce one of two things--either that no one shall venture to
touch any person of the freeborn or noble class except his wedded wife, or
sow the unconsecrated and bastard seed among harlots, or in barren and
unnatural lusts; or at least we may abolish altogether the connexion of men
with men; and as to women, if any man has to do with any but those who come
into his house duly married by sacred rites, whether they be bought or
acquired in any other way, and he offends publicly in the face of all
mankind, we shall be right in enacting that he be deprived of civic honours
and privileges, and be deemed to be, as he truly is, a stranger.  Let this
law, then, whether it is one, or ought rather to be called two, be laid
down respecting love in general, and the intercourse of the sexes which
arises out of the desires, whether rightly or wrongly indulged.

MEGILLUS:  I, for my part, Stranger, would gladly receive this law. 
Cleinias shall speak for himself, and tell you what is his opinion.

CLEINIAS:  I will, Megillus, when an opportunity offers; at present, I
think that we had better allow the Stranger to proceed with his laws.

MEGILLUS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  We had got about as far as the establishment of the common
tables, which in most places would be difficult, but in Crete no one would
think of introducing any other custom.  There might arise a question about
the manner of them--whether they shall be such as they are here in Crete,
or such as they are in Lacedaemon,--or is there a third kind which may be
better than either of them (compare Arist. Pol.)?  The answer to this
question might be easily discovered, but the discovery would do no great
good, for at present they are very well ordered.

Leaving the common tables, we may therefore proceed to the means of
providing food.  Now, in cities the means of life are gained in many ways
and from divers sources, and in general from two sources, whereas our city
has only one.  For most of the Hellenes obtain their food from sea and
land, but our citizens from land only.  And this makes the task of the
legislator less difficult--half as many laws will be enough, and much less
than half; and they will be of a kind better suited to free men.  For he
has nothing to do with laws about shipowners and merchants and retailers
and innkeepers and tax collectors and mines and moneylending and compound
interest and innumerable other things--bidding good-bye to these, he gives
laws to husbandmen and shepherds and bee-keepers, and to the guardians and
superintendents of their implements; and he has already legislated for
greater matters, as for example, respecting marriage and the procreation
and nurture of children, and for education, and the establishment of
offices--and now he must direct his laws to those who provide food and
labour in preparing it.

Let us first of all, then, have a class of laws which shall be called the
laws of husbandmen.  And let the first of them be the law of Zeus, the god
of boundaries.  Let no one shift the boundary line either of a fellow-
citizen who is a neighbour, or, if he dwells at the extremity of the land,
of any stranger who is conterminous with him, considering that this is
truly 'to move the immovable,' and every one should be more willing to move
the largest rock which is not a landmark, than the least stone which is the
sworn mark of friendship and hatred between neighbours; for Zeus, the god
of kindred, is the witness of the citizen, and Zeus, the god of strangers,
of the stranger, and when aroused, terrible are the wars which they stir
up.  He who obeys the law will never know the fatal consequences of
disobedience, but he who despises the law shall be liable to a double
penalty, the first coming from the Gods, and the second from the law.  For
let no one wilfully remove the boundaries of his neighbour's land, and if
any one does, let him who will inform the landowners, and let them bring
him into court, and if he be convicted of re-dividing the land by stealth
or by force, let the court determine what he ought to suffer or pay.  In
the next place, many small injuries done by neighbours to one another,
through their multiplication, may cause a weight of enmity, and make
neighbourhood a very disagreeable and bitter thing.  Wherefore a man ought
to be very careful of committing any offence against his neighbour, and
especially of encroaching on his neighbour's land; for any man may easily
do harm, but not every man can do good to another.  He who encroaches on
his neighbour's land, and transgresses his boundaries, shall make good the
damage, and, to cure him of his impudence and also of his meanness, he
shall pay a double penalty to the injured party.  Of these and the like
matters the wardens of the country shall take cognizance, and be the judges
of them and assessors of the damage; in the more important cases, as has
been already said, the whole number of them belonging to any one of the
twelve divisions shall decide, and in the lesser cases the commanders:  or,
again, if any one pastures his cattle on his neighbour's land, they shall
see the injury, and adjudge the penalty.  And if any one, by decoying the
bees, gets possession of another's swarms, and draws them to himself by
making noises, he shall pay the damage; or if any one sets fire to his own
wood and takes no care of his neighbour's property, he shall be fined at
the discretion of the magistrates.  And if in planting he does not leave a
fair distance between his own and his neighbour's land, he shall be
punished, in accordance with the enactments of many lawgivers, which we may
use, not deeming it necessary that the great legislator of our state should
determine all the trifles which might be decided by any body; for example,
husbandmen have had of old excellent laws about waters, and there is no
reason why we should propose to divert their course:  He who likes may draw
water from the fountain-head of the common stream on to his own land, if he
do not cut off the spring which clearly belongs to some other owner; and he
may take the water in any direction which he pleases, except through a
house or temple or sepulchre, but he must be careful to do no harm beyond
the channel.  And if there be in any place a natural dryness of the earth,
which keeps in the rain from heaven, and causes a deficiency in the supply
of water, let him dig down on his own land as far as the clay, and if at
this depth he finds no water, let him obtain water from his neighbours, as
much as is required for his servants' drinking, and if his neighbours, too,
are limited in their supply, let him have a fixed measure, which shall be
determined by the wardens of the country.  This he shall receive each day,
and on these terms have a share of his neighbours' water.  If there be
heavy rain, and one of those on the lower ground injures some tiller of the
upper ground, or some one who has a common wall, by refusing to give them
an outlet for water; or, again, if some one living on the higher ground
recklessly lets off the water on his lower neighbour, and they cannot come
to terms with one another, let him who will call in a warden of the city,
if he be in the city, or if he be in the country, a warden of the country,
and let him obtain a decision determining what each of them is to do.  And
he who will not abide by the decision shall suffer for his malignant and
morose temper, and pay a fine to the injured party, equivalent to double
the value of the injury, because he was unwilling to submit to the
magistrates.

Now the participation of fruits shall be ordered on this wise.  The goddess
of Autumn has two gracious gifts:  one, the joy of Dionysus which is not
treasured up; the other, which nature intends to be stored.  Let this be
the law, then, concerning the fruits of autumn:  He who tastes the common
or storing fruits of autumn, whether grapes or figs, before the season of
vintage which coincides with Arcturus, either on his own land or on that of
others,--let him pay fifty drachmae, which shall be sacred to Dionysus, if
he pluck them from his own land; and if from his neighbour's land, a mina,
and if from any others', two-thirds of a mina.  And he who would gather the
'choice' grapes or the 'choice' figs, as they are now termed, if he take
them off his own land, let him pluck them how and when he likes; but if he
take them from the ground of others without their leave, let him in that
case be always punished in accordance with the law which ordains that he
should not move what he has not laid down.  And if a slave touches any
fruit of this sort, without the consent of the owner of the land, he shall
be beaten with as many blows as there are grapes on the bunch, or figs on
the fig-tree.  Let a metic purchase the 'choice' autumnal fruit, and then,
if he pleases, he may gather it; but if a stranger is passing along the
road, and desires to eat, let him take of the 'choice' grape for himself
and a single follower without payment, as a tribute of hospitality.  The
law however forbids strangers from sharing in the sort which is not used
for eating; and if any one, whether he be master or slave, takes of them in
ignorance, let the slave be beaten, and the freeman dismissed with
admonitions, and instructed to take of the other autumnal fruits which are
unfit for making raisins and wine, or for laying by as dried figs.  As to
pears, and apples, and pomegranates, and similar fruits, there shall be no
disgrace in taking them secretly; but he who is caught, if he be of less
than thirty years of age, shall be struck and beaten off, but not wounded;
and no freeman shall have any right of satisfaction for such blows.  Of
these fruits the stranger may partake, just as he may of the fruits of
autumn.  And if an elder, who is more than thirty years of age, eat of them
on the spot, let him, like the stranger, be allowed to partake of all such
fruits, but he must carry away nothing.  If, however, he will not obey the
law, let him run risk of failing in the competition of virtue, in case any
one takes notice of his actions before the judges at the time.

Water is the greatest element of nutrition in gardens, but is easily
polluted.  You cannot poison the soil, or the sun, or the air, which are
the other elements of nutrition in plants, or divert them, or steal them;
but all these things may very likely happen in regard to water, which must
therefore be protected by law.  And let this be the law:--If any one
intentionally pollutes the water of another, whether the water of a spring,
or collected in reservoirs, either by poisonous substances, or by digging,
or by theft, let the injured party bring the cause before the wardens of
the city, and claim in writing the value of the loss; if the accused be
found guilty of injuring the water by deleterious substances, let him not
only pay damages, but purify the stream or the cistern which contains the
water, in such manner as the laws of the interpreters order the
purification to be made by the offender in each case.

With respect to the gathering in of the fruits of the soil, let a man, if
he pleases, carry his own fruits through any place in which he either does
no harm to any one, or himself gains three times as much as his neighbour
loses.  Now of these things the magistrates should be cognisant, as of all
other things in which a man intentionally does injury to another or to the
property of another, by fraud or force, in the use which he makes of his
own property.  All these matters a man should lay before the magistrates,
and receive damages, supposing the injury to be not more than three minae;
or if he have a charge against another which involves a larger amount, let
him bring his suit into the public courts and have the evil-doer punished. 
But if any of the magistrates appear to adjudge the penalties which he
imposes in an unjust spirit, let him be liable to pay double to the injured
party.  Any one may bring the offences of magistrates, in any particular
case, before the public courts.  There are innumerable little matters
relating to the modes of punishment, and applications for suits, and
summonses and the witnesses to summonses--for example, whether two
witnesses should be required for a summons, or how many--and all such
details, which cannot be omitted in legislation, but are beneath the wisdom
of an aged legislator.  These lesser matters, as they indeed are in
comparison with the greater ones, let a younger generation regulate by law,
after the patterns which have preceded, and according to their own
experience of the usefulness and necessity of such laws; and when they are
duly regulated let there be no alteration, but let the citizens live in the
observance of them.

Now of artisans, let the regulations be as follows:--In the first place,
let no citizen or servant of a citizen be occupied in handicraft arts; for
he who is to secure and preserve the public order of the state, has an art
which requires much study and many kinds of knowledge, and does not admit
of being made a secondary occupation; and hardly any human being is capable
of pursuing two professions or two arts rightly, or of practising one art
himself, and superintending some one else who is practising another.  Let
this, then, be our first principle in the state:--No one who is a smith
shall also be a carpenter, and if he be a carpenter, he shall not
superintend the smith's art rather than his own, under the pretext that in
superintending many servants who are working for him, he is likely to
superintend them better, because more revenue will accrue to him from them
than from his own art; but let every man in the state have one art, and get
his living by that.  Let the wardens of the city labour to maintain this
law, and if any citizen incline to any other art than the study of virtue,
let them punish him with disgrace and infamy, until they bring him back
into his own right course; and if any stranger profess two arts, let them
chastise him with bonds and money penalties, and expulsion from the state,
until they compel him to be one only and not many.  (Compare Republic.)

But as touching payments for hire, and contracts of work, or in case any
one does wrong to any of the citizens, or they do wrong to any other, up to
fifty drachmae, let the wardens of the city decide the case; but if a
greater amount be involved, then let the public courts decide according to
law.  Let no one pay any duty either on the importation or exportation of
goods; and as to frankincense and similar perfumes, used in the service of
the Gods, which come from abroad, and purple and other dyes which are not
produced in the country, or the materials of any art which have to be
imported, and which are not necessary--no one should import them; nor,
again, should any one export anything which is wanted in the country.  Of
all these things let there be inspectors and superintendents, taken from
the guardians of the law; and they shall be the twelve next in order to the
five seniors.  Concerning arms, and all implements which are required for
military purposes, if there be need of introducing any art, or plant, or
metal, or chains of any kind, or animals for use in war, let the commanders
of the horse and the generals have authority over their importation and
exportation; the city shall send them out and also receive them, and the
guardians of the law shall make fit and proper laws about them.  But let
there be no retail trade (compare Arist. Pol.) for the sake of moneymaking,
either in these or any other articles, in the city or country at all.

With respect to food and the distribution of the produce of the country,
the right and proper way seems to be nearly that which is the custom of
Crete; for all should be required to distribute the fruits of the soil into
twelve parts, and in this way consume them.  Let the twelfth portion of
each (as for instance of wheat and barley, to which the rest of the fruits
of the earth shall be added, as well as the animals which are for sale in
each of the twelve divisions) be divided in due proportion into three
parts; one part for freemen, another for their servants, and a third for
craftsmen and in general for strangers, whether sojourners who may be
dwelling in the city, and like other men must live, or those who come on
some business which they have with the state, or with some individual.  Let
only this third part of all necessaries be required to be sold; out of the
other two-thirds no one shall be compelled to sell.  And how will they be
best distributed?  In the first place, we see clearly that the distribution
will be of equals in one point of view, and in another point of view of
unequals.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that the earth of necessity produces and nourishes the
various articles of food, sometimes better and sometimes worse.

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  Such being the case, let no one of the three portions be greater
than either of the other two;--neither that which is assigned to masters or
to slaves, nor again that of the stranger; but let the distribution to all
be equal and alike, and let every citizen take his two portions and
distribute them among slaves and freemen, he having power to determine the
quantity and quality.  And what remains he shall distribute by measure and
number among the animals who have to be sustained from the earth, taking
the whole number of them.

In the second place, our citizens should have separate houses duly ordered,
and this will be the order proper for men like them.  There shall be twelve
hamlets, one in the middle of each twelfth portion, and in each hamlet they
shall first set apart a market-place, and the temples of the Gods, and of
their attendant demi-gods; and if there be any local deities of the
Magnetes, or holy seats of other ancient deities, whose memory has been
preserved, to these let them pay their ancient honours.  But Hestia, and
Zeus, and Athene will have temples everywhere together with the God who
presides in each of the twelve districts.  And the first erection of houses
shall be around these temples, where the ground is highest, in order to
provide the safest and most defensible place of retreat for the guards. 
All the rest of the country they shall settle in the following manner:--
They shall make thirteen divisions of the craftsmen; one of them they shall
establish in the city, and this, again, they shall subdivide into twelve
lesser divisions, among the twelve districts of the city, and the remainder
shall be distributed in the country round about; and in each village they
shall settle various classes of craftsmen, with a view to the convenience
of the husbandmen.  And the chief officers of the wardens of the country
shall superintend all these matters, and see how many of them, and which
class of them, each place requires; and fix them where they are likely to
be least troublesome, and most useful to the husbandman.  And the wardens
of the city shall see to similar matters in the city.

Now the wardens of the agora ought to see to the details of the agora. 
Their first care, after the temples which are in the agora have been seen
to, should be to prevent any one from doing any wrong in dealings between
man and man; in the second place, as being inspectors of temperance and
violence, they should chastise him who requires chastisement.  Touching
articles of sale, they should first see whether the articles which the
citizens are under regulations to sell to strangers are sold to them, as
the law ordains.  And let the law be as follows:--On the first day of the
month, the persons in charge, whoever they are, whether strangers or
slaves, who have the charge on behalf of the citizens, shall produce to the
strangers the portion which falls to them, in the first place, a twelfth
portion of the corn;--the stranger shall purchase corn for the whole month,
and other cereals, on the first market day; and on the tenth day of the
month the one party shall sell, and the other buy, liquids sufficient to
last during the whole month; and on the twenty-third day there shall be a
sale of animals by those who are willing to sell to the people who want to
buy, and of implements and other things which husbandmen sell (such as
skins and all kinds of clothing, either woven or made of felt and other
goods of the same sort,) and which strangers are compelled to buy and
purchase of others.  As to the retail trade in these things, whether of
barley or wheat set apart for meal and flour, or any other kind of food, no
one shall sell them to citizens or their slaves, nor shall any one buy of a
citizen; but let the stranger sell them in the market of strangers, to
artisans and their slaves, making an exchange of wine and food, which is
commonly called retail trade.  And butchers shall offer for sale parts of
dismembered animals to the strangers, and artisans, and their servants. 
Let any stranger who likes buy fuel from day to day wholesale, from those
who have the care of it in the country, and let him sell to the strangers
as much he pleases and when he pleases.  As to other goods and implements
which are likely to be wanted, they shall sell them in the common market,
at any place which the guardians of the law and the wardens of the market
and city, choosing according to their judgment, shall determine; at such
places they shall exchange money for goods, and goods for money, neither
party giving credit to the other; and he who gives credit must be
satisfied, whether he obtain his money not, for in such exchanges he will
not be protected by law.  But whenever property has been bought or sold,
greater in quantity or value than is allowed by the law, which has
determined within what limits a man may increase and diminish his
possessions, let the excess be registered in the books of the guardians of
the law; or in case of diminution, let there be an erasure made.  And let
the same rule be observed about the registration of the property of the
metics.  Any one who likes may come and be a metic on certain conditions; a
foreigner, if he likes, and is able to settle, may dwell in the land, but
he must practise an art, and not abide more than twenty years from the time
at which he has registered himself; and he shall pay no sojourner's tax,
however small, except good conduct, nor any other tax for buying and
selling.  But when the twenty years have expired, he shall take his
property with him and depart.  And if in the course of these years he
should chance to distinguish himself by any considerable benefit which he
confers on the state, and he thinks that he can persuade the council and
assembly, either to grant him delay in leaving the country, or to allow him
to remain for the whole of his life, let him go and persuade the city, and
whatever they assent to at his instance shall take effect.  For the
children of the metics, being artisans, and of fifteen years of age, let
the time of their sojourn commence after their fifteenth year; and let them
remain for twenty years, and then go where they like; but any of them who
wishes to remain, may do so, if he can persuade the council and assembly. 
And if he depart, let him erase all the entries which have been made by him
in the register kept by the magistrates.


BOOK IX.

Next to all the matters which have preceded in the natural order of
legislation will come suits of law.  Of suits those which relate to
agriculture have been already described, but the more important have not
been described.  Having mentioned them severally under their usual names,
we will proceed to say what punishments are to be inflicted for each
offence, and who are to be the judges of them.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  There is a sense of disgrace in legislating, as we are about to
do, for all the details of crime in a state which, as we say, is to be well
regulated and will be perfectly adapted to the practice of virtue.  To
assume that in such a state there will arise some one who will be guilty of
crimes as heinous as any which are ever perpetrated in other states, and
that we must legislate for him by anticipation, and threaten and make laws
against him if he should arise, in order to deter him, and punish his acts,
under the idea that he will arise--this, as I was saying, is in a manner
disgraceful.  Yet seeing that we are not like the ancient legislators, who
gave laws to heroes and sons of gods, being, according to the popular
belief, themselves the offspring of the gods, and legislating for others,
who were also the children of divine parents, but that we are only men who
are legislating for the sons of men, there is no uncharitableness in
apprehending that some one of our citizens may be like a seed which has
touched the ox's horn, having a heart so hard that it cannot be softened
any more than those seeds can be softened by fire.  Among our citizens
there may be those who cannot be subdued by all the strength of the laws;
and for their sake, though an ungracious task, I will proclaim my first law
about the robbing of temples, in case any one should dare to commit such a
crime.  I do not expect or imagine that any well-brought-up citizen will
ever take the infection, but their servants, and strangers, and strangers'
servants may be guilty of many impieties.  And with a view to them
especially, and yet not without a provident eye to the weakness of human
nature generally, I will proclaim the law about robbers of temples and
similar incurable, or almost incurable, criminals.  Having already agreed
that such enactments ought always to have a short prelude, we may speak to
the criminal, whom some tormenting desire by night and by day tempts to go
and rob a temple, the fewest possible words of admonition and exhortation:
--O sir, we will say to him, the impulse which moves you to rob temples is
not an ordinary human malady, nor yet a visitation of heaven, but a madness
which is begotten in a man from ancient and unexpiated crimes of his race,
an ever-recurring curse;--against this you must guard with all your might,
and how you are to guard we will explain to you.  When any such thought
comes into your mind, go and perform expiations, go as a suppliant to the
temples of the Gods who avert evils, go to the society of those who are
called good men among you; hear them tell and yourself try to repeat after
them, that every man should honour the noble and the just.  Fly from the
company of the wicked--fly and turn not back; and if your disorder is
lightened by these remedies, well and good, but if not, then acknowledge
death to be nobler than life, and depart hence.

Such are the preludes which we sing to all who have thoughts of unholy and
treasonable actions, and to him who hearkens to them the law has nothing to
say.  But to him who is disobedient when the prelude is over, cry with a
loud voice--He who is taken in the act of robbing temples, if he be a slave
or stranger, shall have his evil deed engraven on his face and hands, and
shall be beaten with as many stripes as may seem good to the judges, and be
cast naked beyond the borders of the land.  And if he suffers this
punishment he will probably return to his right mind and be improved; for
no penalty which the law inflicts is designed for evil, but always makes
him who suffers either better or not so much worse as he would have been
(compare Protag.; Gorg.).  But if any citizen be found guilty of any great
or unmentionable wrong, either in relation to the gods, or his parents, or
the state, let the judge deem him to be incurable, remembering that after
receiving such an excellent education and training from youth upward, he
has not abstained from the greatest of crimes (compare Statesman).  His
punishment shall be death, which to him will be the least of evils; and his
example will benefit others, if he perish ingloriously, and be cast beyond
the borders of the land.  But let his children and family, if they avoid
the ways of their father, have glory, and let honourable mention be made of
them, as having nobly and manfully escaped out of evil into good.  None of
them should have their goods confiscated to the state, for the lots of the
citizens ought always to continue the same and equal.

Touching the exaction of penalties, when a man appears to have done
anything which deserves a fine, he shall pay the fine, if he have anything
in excess of the lot which is assigned to him; but more than that he shall
not pay.  And to secure exactness, let the guardians of the law refer to
the registers, and inform the judges of the precise truth, in order that
none of the lots may go uncultivated for want of money.  But if any one
seems to deserve a greater penalty, let him undergo a long and public
imprisonment and be dishonoured, unless some of his friends are willing to
be surety for him, and liberate him by assisting him to pay the fine.  No
criminal shall go unpunished, not even for a single offence, nor if he have
fled the country; but let the penalty be according to his deserts,--death,
or bonds, or blows, or degrading places of sitting or standing, or removal
to some temple on the borders of the land; or let him pay fines, as we said
before.  In cases of death, let the judges be the guardians of the law, and
a court selected by merit from the last year's magistrates.  But how the
causes are to be brought into court, how the summonses are to be served,
the the like, these things may be left to the younger generation of
legislators to determine; the manner of voting we must determine ourselves.

Let the vote be given openly; but before they come to the vote let the
judges sit in order of seniority over against plaintiff and defendant, and
let all the citizens who can spare time hear and take a serious interest in
listening to such causes.  First of all the plaintiff shall make one
speech, and then the defendant shall make another; and after the speeches
have been made the eldest judge shall begin to examine the parties, and
proceed to make an adequate enquiry into what has been said; and after the
oldest has spoken, the rest shall proceed in order to examine either party
as to what he finds defective in the evidence, whether of statement or
omission; and he who has nothing to ask shall hand over the examination to
another.  And on so much of what has been said as is to the purpose all the
judges shall set their seals, and place the writings on the altar of
Hestia.  On the next day they shall meet again, and in like manner put
their questions and go through the cause, and again set their seals upon
the evidence; and when they have three times done this, and have had
witnesses and evidence enough, they shall each of them give a holy vote,
after promising by Hestia that they will decide justly and truly to the
utmost of their power; and so they shall put an end to the suit.

Next, after what relates to the Gods, follows what relates to the
dissolution of the state:--Whoever by promoting a man to power enslaves the
laws, and subjects the city to factions, using violence and stirring up
sedition contrary to law, him we will deem the greatest enemy of the whole
state.  But he who takes no part in such proceedings, and, being one of the
chief magistrates of the state, has no knowledge of the treason, or, having
knowledge of it, by reason of cowardice does not interfere on behalf of his
country, such an one we must consider nearly as bad.  Every man who is
worth anything will inform the magistrates, and bring the conspirator to
trial for making a violent and illegal attempt to change the government. 
The judges of such cases shall be the same as of the robbers of temples;
and let the whole proceeding be carried on in the same way, and the vote of
the majority condemn to death.  But let there be a general rule, that the
disgrace and punishment of the father is not to be visited on the children,
except in the case of some one whose father, grandfather, and great-
grandfather have successively undergone the penalty of death.  Such persons
the city shall send away with all their possessions to the city and country
of their ancestors, retaining only and wholly their appointed lot.  And out
of the citizens who have more than one son of not less than ten years of
age, they shall select ten whom their father or grandfather by the mother's
or father's side shall appoint, and let them send to Delphi the names of
those who are selected, and him whom the God chooses they shall establish
as heir of the house which has failed; and may he have better fortune than
his predecessors!

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Once more let there be a third general law respecting the judges
who are to give judgment, and the manner of conducting suits against those
who are tried on an accusation of treason; and as concerning the remaining
or departure of their descendants,--there shall be one law for all three,
for the traitor, and the robber of temples, and the subverter by violence
of the laws of the state.  For a thief, whether he steal much or little,
let there be one law, and one punishment for all alike:  in the first
place, let him pay double the amount of the theft if he be convicted, and
if he have so much over and above the allotment;--if he have not, he shall
be bound until he pay the penalty, or persuade him who has obtained the
sentence against him to forgive him.  But if a person be convicted of a
theft against the state, then if he can persuade the city, or if he will
pay back twice the amount of the theft, he shall be set free from his
bonds.

CLEINIAS:  What makes you say, Stranger, that a theft is all one, whether
the thief may have taken much or little, and either from sacred or secular
places--and these are not the only differences in thefts:--seeing, then,
that they are of many kinds, ought not the legislator to adapt himself to
them, and impose upon them entirely different penalties?

ATHENIAN:  Excellent.  I was running on too fast, Cleinias, and you
impinged upon me, and brought me to my senses, reminding me of what,
indeed, had occurred to my mind already, that legislation was never yet
rightly worked out, as I may say in passing.--Do you remember the image in
which I likened the men for whom laws are now made to slaves who are
doctored by slaves?  For of this you may be very sure, that if one of those
empirical physicians, who practise medicine without science, were to come
upon the gentleman physician talking to his gentleman patient, and using
the language almost of philosophy, beginning at the beginning of the
disease and discoursing about the whole nature of the body, he would burst
into a hearty laugh--he would say what most of those who are called doctors
always have at their tongue's end:--Foolish fellow, he would say, you are
not healing the sick man, but you are educating him; and he does not want
to be made a doctor, but to get well.

CLEINIAS:  And would he not be right?

ATHENIAN:  Perhaps he would; and he might remark upon us, that he who
discourses about laws, as we are now doing, is giving the citizens
education and not laws; that would be rather a telling observation.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  But we are fortunate.

CLEINIAS:  In what way?

ATHENIAN:  Inasmuch as we are not compelled to give laws, but we may take
into consideration every form of government, and ascertain what is best and
what is most needful, and how they may both be carried into execution; and
we may also, if we please, at this very moment choose what is best, or, if
we prefer, what is most necessary--which shall we do?

CLEINIAS:  There is something ridiculous, Stranger, in our proposing such
an alternative, as if we were legislators, simply bound under some great
necessity which cannot be deferred to the morrow.  But we, as I may by the
grace of Heaven affirm, like gatherers of stones or beginners of some
composite work, may gather a heap of materials, and out of this, at our
leisure, select what is suitable for our projected construction.  Let us
then suppose ourselves to be at leisure, not of necessity building, but
rather like men who are partly providing materials, and partly putting them
together.  And we may truly say that some of our laws, like stones, are
already fixed in their places, and others lie at hand.

ATHENIAN:  Certainly, in that case, Cleinias, our view of law will be more
in accordance with nature.  For there is another matter affecting
legislators, which I must earnestly entreat you to consider.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  There are many writings to be found in cities, and among them
there are discourses composed by legislators as well as by other persons.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  Shall we give heed rather to the writings of those others,--
poets and the like, who either in metre or out of metre have recorded their
advice about the conduct of life, and not to the writings of legislators?
or shall we give heed to them above all?

CLEINIAS:  Yes; to them far above all others.

ATHENIAN:  And ought the legislator alone among writers to withhold his
opinion about the beautiful, the good, and the just, and not to teach what
they are, and how they are to be pursued by those who intend to be happy?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  And is it disgraceful for Homer and Tyrtaeus and other poets to
lay down evil precepts in their writings respecting life and the pursuits
of men, but not so disgraceful for Lycurgus and Solon and others who were
legislators as well as writers?  Is it not true that of all the writings to
be found in cities, those which relate to laws, when you unfold and read
them, ought to be by far the noblest and the best? and should not other
writings either agree with them, or if they disagree, be deemed ridiculous? 
We should consider whether the laws of states ought not to have the
character of loving and wise parents, rather than of tyrants and masters,
who command and threaten, and, after writing their decrees on walls, go
their ways; and whether, in discoursing of laws, we should not take the
gentler view of them which may or may not be attainable,--at any rate, we
will show our readiness to entertain such a view, and be prepared to
undergo whatever may be the result.  And may the result be good, and if God
be gracious, it will be good!

CLEINIAS:  Excellent; let us do as you say.

ATHENIAN:  Then we will now consider accurately, as we proposed, what
relates to robbers of temples, and all kinds of thefts, and offences in
general; and we must not be annoyed if, in the course of legislation, we
have enacted some things, and have not made up our minds about some others;
for as yet we are not legislators, but we may soon be.  Let us, if you
please, consider these matters.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Concerning all things honourable and just, let us then endeavour
to ascertain how far we are consistent with ourselves, and how far we are
inconsistent, and how far the many, from whom at any rate we should profess
a desire to differ, agree and disagree among themselves.

CLEINIAS:  What are the inconsistencies which you observe in us?

ATHENIAN:  I will endeavour to explain.  If I am not mistaken, we are all
agreed that justice, and just men and things and actions, are all fair,
and, if a person were to maintain that just men, even when they are
deformed in body, are still perfectly beautiful in respect of the excellent
justice of their minds, no one would say that there was any inconsistency
in this.

CLEINIAS:  They would be quite right.

ATHENIAN:  Perhaps; but let us consider further, that if all things which
are just are fair and honourable, in the term 'all' we must include just
sufferings which are the correlatives of just actions.

CLEINIAS:  And what is the inference?

ATHENIAN:  The inference is, that a just action in partaking of the just
partakes also in the same degree of the fair and honourable.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And must not a suffering which partakes of the just principle be
admitted to be in the same degree fair and honourable, if the argument is
consistently carried out?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  But then if we admit suffering to be just and yet dishonourable,
and the term 'dishonourable' is applied to justice, will not the just and
the honourable disagree?

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  A thing not difficult to understand; the laws which have been
already enacted would seem to announce principles directly opposed to what
we are saying.

CLEINIAS:  To what?

ATHENIAN:  We had enacted, if I am not mistaken, that the robber of
temples, and he who was the enemy of law and order, might justly be put to
death, and we were proceeding to make divers other enactments of a similar
nature.  But we stopped short, because we saw that these sufferings are
infinite in number and degree, and that they are, at once, the most just
and also the most dishonourable of all sufferings.  And if this be true,
are not the just and the honourable at one time all the same, and at
another time in the most diametrical opposition?

CLEINIAS:  Such appears to be the case.

ATHENIAN:  In this discordant and inconsistent fashion does the language of
the many rend asunder the honourable and just.

CLEINIAS:  Very true, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Then now, Cleinias, let us see how far we ourselves are
consistent about these matters.

CLEINIAS:  Consistent in what?

ATHENIAN:  I think that I have clearly stated in the former part of the
discussion, but if I did not, let me now state--

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  That all bad men are always involuntarily bad; and from this
must proceed to draw a further inference.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  That the unjust man may be bad, but that he is bad against his
will.  Now that an action which is voluntary should be done involuntarily
is a contradiction; wherefore he who maintains that injustice is
involuntary will deem that the unjust does injustice involuntarily.  I too
admit that all men do injustice involuntarily, and if any contentious or
disputatious person says that men are unjust against their will, and yet
that many do injustice willingly, I do not agree with him.  But, then, how
can I avoid being inconsistent with myself, if you, Cleinias, and you,
Megillus, say to me,--Well, Stranger, if all this be as you say, how about
legislating for the city of the Magnetes--shall we legislate or not--what
do you advise?  Certainly we will, I should reply.  Then will you determine
for them what are voluntary and what are involuntary crimes, and shall we
make the punishments greater of voluntary errors and crimes and less for
the involuntary? or shall we make the punishment of all to be alike, under
the idea that there is no such thing as voluntary crime?

CLEINIAS:  Very good, Stranger; and what shall we say in answer to these
objections?

ATHENIAN:  That is a very fair question.  In the first place, let us--

CLEINIAS:  Do what?

ATHENIAN:  Let us remember what has been well said by us already, that our
ideas of justice are in the highest degree confused and contradictory.
Bearing this in mind, let us proceed to ask ourselves once more whether we
have discovered a way out of the difficulty.  Have we ever determined in
what respect these two classes of actions differ from one another?  For in
all states and by all legislators whatsoever, two kinds of actions have
been distinguished--the one, voluntary, the other, involuntary; and they
have legislated about them accordingly.  But shall this new word of ours,
like an oracle of God, be only spoken, and get away without giving any
explanation or verification of itself?  How can a word not understood be
the basis of legislation?  Impossible.  Before proceeding to legislate,
then, we must prove that they are two, and what is the difference between
them, that when we impose the penalty upon either, every one may understand
our proposal, and be able in some way to judge whether the penalty is fitly
or unfitly inflicted.

CLEINIAS:  I agree with you, Stranger; for one of two things is certain: 
either we must not say that all unjust acts are involuntary, or we must
show the meaning and truth of this statement.

ATHENIAN:  Of these two alternatives, the one is quite intolerable--not to
speak what I believe to be the truth would be to me unlawful and unholy. 
But if acts of injustice cannot be divided into voluntary and involuntary,
I must endeavour to find some other distinction between them.

CLEINIAS:  Very true, Stranger; there cannot be two opinions among us upon
that point.

ATHENIAN:  Reflect, then; there are hurts of various kinds done by the
citizens to one another in the intercourse of life, affording plentiful
examples both of the voluntary and involuntary.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  I would not have any one suppose that all these hurts are
injuries, and that these injuries are of two kinds--one, voluntary, and the
other, involuntary; for the involuntary hurts of all men are quite as many
and as great as the voluntary (compare Arist. N.E.).  And please to
consider whether I am right or quite wrong in what I am going to say; for I
deny, Cleinias and Megillus, that he who harms another involuntarily does
him an injury involuntarily, nor should I legislate about such an act under
the idea that I am legislating for an involuntary injury.  But I should
rather say that such a hurt, whether great or small, is not an injury at
all; and, on the other hand, if I am right, when a benefit is wrongly
conferred, the author of the benefit may often be said to injure.  For I
maintain, O my friends, that the mere giving or taking away of anything is
not to be described either as just or unjust; but the legislator has to
consider whether mankind do good or harm to one another out of a just
principle and intention.  On the distinction between injustice and hurt he
must fix his eye; and when there is hurt, he must, as far as he can, make
the hurt good by law, and save that which is ruined, and raise up that
which is fallen, and make that which is dead or wounded whole.  And when
compensation has been given for injustice, the law must always seek to win
over the doers and sufferers of the several hurts from feelings of enmity
to those of friendship.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Then as to unjust hurts (and gains also, supposing the injustice
to bring gain), of these we may heal as many as are capable of being
healed, regarding them as diseases of the soul; and the cure of injustice
will take the following direction.

CLEINIAS:  What direction?

ATHENIAN:  When any one commits any injustice, small or great, the law will
admonish and compel him either never at all to do the like again, or never
voluntarily, or at any rate in a far less degree; and he must in addition
pay for the hurt.  Whether the end is to be attained by word or action,
with pleasure or pain, by giving or taking away privileges, by means of
fines or gifts, or in whatsoever way the law shall proceed to make a man
hate injustice, and love or not hate the nature of the just,--this is quite
the noblest work of law.  But if the legislator sees any one who is
incurable, for him he will appoint a law and a penalty.  He knows quite
well that to such men themselves there is no profit in the continuance of
their lives, and that they would do a double good to the rest of mankind if
they would take their departure, inasmuch as they would be an example to
other men not to offend, and they would relieve the city of bad citizens. 
In such cases, and in such cases only, the legislator ought to inflict
death as the punishment of offences.

CLEINIAS:  What you have said appears to me to be very reasonable, but will
you favour me by stating a little more clearly the difference between hurt
and injustice, and the various complications of the voluntary and
involuntary which enter into them?

ATHENIAN:  I will endeavour to do as you wish:--Concerning the soul, thus
much would be generally said and allowed, that one element in her nature is
passion, which may be described either as a state or a part of her, and is
hard to be striven against and contended with, and by irrational force
overturns many things.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  And pleasure is not the same with passion, but has an opposite
power, working her will by persuasion and by the force of deceit in all
things.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  A man may truly say that ignorance is a third cause of crimes. 
Ignorance, however, may be conveniently divided by the legislator into two
sorts:  there is simple ignorance, which is the source of lighter offences,
and double ignorance, which is accompanied by a conceit of wisdom; and he
who is under the influence of the latter fancies that he knows all about
matters of which he knows nothing.  This second kind of ignorance, when
possessed of power and strength, will be held by the legislator to be the
source of great and monstrous times, but when attended with weakness, will
only result in the errors of children and old men; and these he will treat
as errors, and will make laws accordingly for those who commit them, which
will be the mildest and most merciful of all laws.

CLEINIAS:  You are perfectly right.

ATHENIAN:  We all of us remark of one man that he is superior to pleasure
and passion, and of another that he is inferior to them; and this is true. 
(Compare Republic.)

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  But no one was ever yet heard to say that one of us is superior
and another inferior to ignorance.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  We are speaking of motives which incite men to the fulfilment of
their will; although an individual may be often drawn by them in opposite
directions at the same time.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, often.

ATHENIAN:  And now I can define to you clearly, and without ambiguity, what
I mean by the just and unjust, according to my notion of them:--When anger
and fear, and pleasure and pain, and jealousies and desires, tyrannize over
the soul, whether they do any harm or not,--I call all this injustice.  But
when the opinion of the best, in whatever part of human nature states or
individuals may suppose that to dwell, has dominion in the soul and orders
the life of every man, even if it be sometimes mistaken, yet what is done
in accordance therewith, the principle in individuals which obeys this
rule, and is best for the whole life of man, is to be called just; although
the hurt done by mistake is thought by many to be involuntary injustice. 
Leaving the question of names, about which we are not going to quarrel, and
having already delineated three sources of error, we may begin by recalling
them somewhat more vividly to our memory:--One of them was of the painful
sort, which we denominate anger and fear.

CLEINIAS:  Quite right.

ATHENIAN:  There was a second consisting of pleasures and desires, and a
third of hopes, which aimed at true opinion about the best.  The latter
being subdivided into three, we now get five sources of actions, and for
these five we will make laws of two kinds.

CLEINIAS:  What are the two kinds?

ATHENIAN:  There is one kind of actions done by violence and in the light
of day, and another kind of actions which are done in darkness and with
secret deceit, or sometimes both with violence and deceit; the laws
concerning these last ought to have a character of severity.

CLEINIAS:  Naturally.

ATHENIAN:  And now let us return from this digression and complete the work
of legislation.  Laws have been already enacted by us concerning the
robbers of the Gods, and concerning traitors, and also concerning those who
corrupt the laws for the purpose of subverting the government.  A man may
very likely commit some of these crimes, either in a state of madness or
when affected by disease, or under the influence of extreme old age, or in
a fit of childish wantonness, himself no better than a child.  And if this
be made evident to the judges elected to try the cause, on the appeal of
the criminal or his advocate, and he be judged to have been in this state
when he committed the offence, he shall simply pay for the hurt which he
may have done to another; but he shall be exempt from other penalties,
unless he have slain some one, and have on his hands the stain of blood. 
And in that case he shall go to another land and country, and there dwell
for a year; and if he return before the expiration of the time which the
law appoints, or even set his foot at all on his native land, he shall be
bound by the guardians of the law in the public prison for two years, and
then go free.

Having begun to speak of homicide, let us endeavour to lay down laws
concerning every different kind of homicide; and, first of all, concerning
violent and involuntary homicides.  If any one in an athletic contest, and
at the public games, involuntarily kills a friend, and he dies either at
the time or afterwards of the blows which he has received; or if the like
misfortune happens to any one in war, or military exercises, or mimic
contests of which the magistrates enjoin the practice, whether with or
without arms, when he has been purified according to the law brought from
Delphi relating to these matters, he shall be innocent.  And so in the case
of physicians:  if their patient dies against their will, they shall be
held guiltless by the law.  And if one slay another with his own hand, but
unintentionally, whether he be unarmed or have some instrument or dart in
his hand; or if he kill him by administering food or drink, or by the
application of fire or cold, or by suffocating him, whether he do the deed
by his own hand, or by the agency of others, he shall be deemed the agent,
and shall suffer one of the following penalties:--If he kill the slave of
another in the belief that he is his own, he shall bear the master of the
dead man harmless from loss, or shall pay a penalty of twice the value of
the dead man, which the judges shall assess; but purifications must be used
greater and more numerous than for those who committed homicide at the
games;--what they are to be, the interpreters whom the God appoints shall
be authorized to declare.  And if a man kills his own slave, when he has
been purified according to law, he shall be quit of the homicide.  And if a
man kills a freeman unintentionally, he shall undergo the same purification
as he did who killed the slave.  But let him not forget also a tale of
olden time, which is to this effect:--He who has suffered a violent end,
when newly dead, if he has had the soul of a freeman in life, is angry with
the author of his death; and being himself full of fear and panic by reason
of his violent end, when he sees his murderer walking about in his own
accustomed haunts, he is stricken with terror and becomes disordered, and
this disorder of his, aided by the guilty recollection of the other, is
communicated by him with overwhelming force to the murderer and his deeds. 
Wherefore also the murderer must go out of the way of his victim for the
entire period of a year, and not himself be found in any spot which was
familiar to him throughout the country.  And if the dead man be a stranger,
the homicide shall be kept from the country of the stranger during a like
period.  If any one voluntarily obeys this law, the next of kin to the
deceased, seeing all that has happened, shall take pity on him, and make
peace with him, and show him all gentleness.  But if any one is
disobedient, either ventures to go to any of the temples and sacrifice
unpurified, or will not continue in exile during the appointed time, the
next of kin to the deceased shall proceed against him for murder; and if he
be convicted, every part of his punishment shall be doubled.  And if the
next of kin do not proceed against the perpetrator of the crime, then the
pollution shall be deemed to fall upon his own head;--the murdered man will
fix the guilt upon his kinsman, and he who has a mind to proceed against
him may compel him to be absent from his country during five years,
according to law.  If a stranger unintentionally kill a stranger who is
dwelling in the city, he who likes shall prosecute the cause according to
the same rules.  If he be a metic, let him be absent for a year, or if he
be an entire stranger, in addition to the purification, whether he have
slain a stranger, or a metic, or a citizen, he shall be banished for life
from the country which is in possession of our laws.  And if he return
contrary to law, let the guardians of the law punish him with death; and
let them hand over his property, if he have any, to him who is next of kin
to the sufferer.  And if he be wrecked, and driven on the coast against his
will, he shall take up his abode on the seashore, wetting his feet in the
sea, and watching for an opportunity of sailing; but if he be brought by
land, and is not his own master, let the magistrate whom he first comes
across in the city, release him and send him unharmed over the border.

If any one slays a freeman with his own hand, and the deed be done in
passion, in the case of such actions we must begin by making a distinction. 
For a deed is done from passion either when men suddenly, and without
intention to kill, cause the death of another by blows and the like on a
momentary impulse, and are sorry for the deed immediately afterwards; or
again, when after having been insulted in deed or word, men pursue revenge,
and kill a person intentionally, and are not sorry for the act.  And,
therefore, we must assume that these homicides are of two kinds, both of
them arising from passion, which may be justly said to be in a mean between
the voluntary and involuntary; at the same time, they are neither of them
anything more than a likeness or shadow of either.  He who treasures up his
anger, and avenges himself, not immediately and at the moment, but with
insidious design, and after an interval, is like the voluntary; but he who
does not treasure up his anger, and takes vengeance on the instant, and
without malice prepense, approaches to the involuntary; and yet even he is
not altogether involuntary, but only the image or shadow of the
involuntary; wherefore about homicides committed in hot blood, there is a
difficulty in determining whether in legislating we shall reckon them as
voluntary or as partly involuntary.  The best and truest view is to regard
them respectively as likenesses only of the voluntary and involuntary, and
to distinguish them accordingly as they are done with or without
premeditation.  And we should make the penalties heavier for those who
commit homicide with angry premeditation, and lighter for those who do not
premeditate, but smite upon the instant; for that which is like a greater
evil should be punished more severely, and that which is like a less evil
should be punished less severely:  this shall be the rule of our laws.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Let us proceed:--If any one slays a freeman with his own hand,
and the deed be done in a moment of anger, and without premeditation, let
the offender suffer in other respects as the involuntary homicide would
have suffered, and also undergo an exile of two years, that he may learn to
school his passions.  But he who slays another from passion, yet with
premeditation, shall in other respects suffer as the former; and to this
shall be added an exile of three instead of two years,--his punishment is
to be longer because his passion is greater.  The manner of their return
shall be on this wise:  (and here the law has difficulty in determining
exactly; for in some cases the murderer who is judged by the law to be the
worse may really be the less cruel, and he who is judged the less cruel may
be really the worse, and may have executed the murder in a more savage
manner, whereas the other may have been gentler.  But in general the
degrees of guilt will be such as we have described them.  Of all these
things the guardians of the law must take cognizance):--When a homicide of
either kind has completed his term of exile, the guardians shall send
twelve judges to the borders of the land; these during the interval shall
have informed themselves of the actions of the criminals, and they shall
judge respecting their pardon and reception; and the homicides shall abide
by their judgment.  But if after they have returned home, any one of them
in a moment of anger repeats the deed, let him be an exile, and return no
more; or if he returns, let him suffer as the stranger was to suffer in a
similar case.  He who kills his own slave shall undergo a purification, but
if he kills the slave of another in anger, he shall pay twice the amount of
the loss to his owner.  And if any homicide is disobedient to the law, and
without purification pollutes the agora, or the games, or the temples, he
who pleases may bring to trial the next of kin to the dead man for
permitting him, and the murderer with him, and may compel the one to exact
and the other to suffer a double amount of fines and purifications; and the
accuser shall himself receive the fine in accordance with the law.  If a
slave in a fit of passion kills his master, the kindred of the deceased man
may do with the murderer (provided only they do not spare his life)
whatever they please, and they will be pure; or if he kills a freeman, who
is not his master, the owner shall give up the slave to the relatives of
the deceased, and they shall be under an obligation to put him to death,
but this may be done in any manner which they please.  And if (which is a
rare occurrence, but does sometimes happen) a father or a mother in a
moment of passion slays a son or daughter by blows, or some other violence,
the slayer shall undergo the same purification as in other cases, and be
exiled during three years; but when the exile returns the wife shall
separate from the husband, and the husband from the wife, and they shall
never afterwards beget children together, or live under the same roof, or
partake of the same sacred rites with those whom they have deprived of a
child or of a brother.  And he who is impious and disobedient in such a
case shall be brought to trial for impiety by any one who pleases.  If in a
fit of anger a husband kills his wedded wife, or the wife her husband, the
slayer shall undergo the same purification, and the term of exile shall be
three years.  And when he who has committed any such crime returns, let him
have no communication in sacred rites with his children, neither let him
sit at the same table with them, and the father or son who disobeys shall
be liable to be brought to trial for impiety by any one who pleases.  If a
brother or a sister in a fit of passion kills a brother or a sister, they
shall undergo purification and exile, as was the case with parents who
killed their offspring:  they shall not come under the same roof, or share
in the sacred rites of those whom they have deprived of their brethren, or
of their children.  And he who is disobedient shall be justly liable to the
law concerning impiety, which relates to these matters.  If any one is so
violent in his passion against his parents, that in the madness of his
anger he dares to kill one of them, if the murdered person before dying
freely forgives the murderer, let him undergo the purification which is
assigned to those who have been guilty of involuntary homicide, and do as
they do, and he shall be pure.  But if he be not acquitted, the perpetrator
of such a deed shall be amenable to many laws;--he shall be amenable to the
extreme punishments for assault, and impiety, and robbing of temples, for
he has robbed his parent of life; and if a man could be slain more than
once, most justly would he who in a fit of passion has slain father or
mother, undergo many deaths.  How can he, whom, alone of all men, even in
defence of his life, and when about to suffer death at the hands of his
parents, no law will allow to kill his father or his mother who are the
authors of his being, and whom the legislator will command to endure any
extremity rather than do this--how can he, I say, lawfully receive any
other punishment?  Let death then be the appointed punishment of him who in
a fit of passion slays his father or his mother.  But if brother kills
brother in a civil broil, or under other like circumstances, if the other
has begun, and he only defends himself, let him be free from guilt, as he
would be if he had slain an enemy; and the same rule will apply if a
citizen kill a citizen, or a stranger a stranger.  Or if a stranger kill a
citizen or a citizen a stranger in self-defence, let him be free from guilt
in like manner; and so in the case of a slave who has killed a slave; but
if a slave have killed a freeman in self-defence, let him be subject to the
same law as he who has killed a father; and let the law about the remission
of penalties in the case of parricide apply equally to every other
remission.  Whenever any sufferer of his own accord remits the guilt of
homicide to another, under the idea that his act was involuntary, let the
perpetrator of the deed undergo a purification and remain in exile for a
year, according to law.

Enough has been said of murders violent and involuntary and committed in
passion:  we have now to speak of voluntary crimes done with injustice of
every kind and with premeditation, through the influence of pleasures, and
desires, and jealousies.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Let us first speak, as far as we are able, of their various
kinds.  The greatest cause of them is lust, which gets the mastery of the
soul maddened by desire; and this is most commonly found to exist where the
passion reigns which is strongest and most prevalent among the mass of
mankind:  I mean where the power of wealth breeds endless desires of never-
to-be-satisfied acquisition, originating in natural disposition, and a
miserable want of education.  Of this want of education, the false praise
of wealth which is bruited about both among Hellenes and barbarians is the
cause; they deem that to be the first of goods which in reality is only the
third.  And in this way they wrong both posterity and themselves, for
nothing can be nobler and better than that the truth about wealth should be
spoken in all states--namely, that riches are for the sake of the body, as
the body is for the sake of the soul.  They are good, and wealth is
intended by nature to be for the sake of them, and is therefore inferior to
them both, and third in order of excellence.  This argument teaches us that
he who would be happy ought not to seek to be rich, or rather he should
seek to be rich justly and temperately, and then there would be no murders
in states requiring to be purged away by other murders.  But now, as I said
at first, avarice is the chiefest cause and source of the worst trials for
voluntary homicide.  A second cause is ambition:  this creates jealousies,
which are troublesome companions, above all to the jealous man himself, and
in a less degree to the chiefs of the state.  And a third cause is cowardly
and unjust fear, which has been the occasion of many murders.  When a man
is doing or has done something which he desires that no one should know him
to be doing or to have done, he will take the life of those who are likely
to inform of such things, if he have no other means of getting rid of them. 
Let this be said as a prelude concerning crimes of violence in general; and
I must not omit to mention a tradition which is firmly believed by many,
and has been received by them from those who are learned in the mysteries: 
they say that such deeds will be punished in the world below, and also that
when the perpetrators return to this world they will pay the natural
penalty which is due to the sufferer, and end their lives in like manner by
the hand of another.  If he who is about to commit murder believes this,
and is made by the mere prelude to dread such a penalty, there is no need
to proceed with the proclamation of the law.  But if he will not listen,
let the following law be declared and registered against him:--Whoever
shall wrongfully and of design slay with his own hand any of his kinsmen,
shall in the first place be deprived of legal privileges; and he shall not
pollute the temples, or the agora, or the harbours, or any other place of
meeting, whether he is forbidden of men or not; for the law, which
represents the whole state, forbids him, and always is and will be in the
attitude of forbidding him.  And if a cousin or nearer relative of the
deceased, whether on the male or female side, does not prosecute the
homicide when he ought, and have him proclaimed an outlaw, he shall in the
first place be involved in the pollution, and incur the hatred of the Gods,
even as the curse of the law stirs up the voices of men against him; and in
the second place he shall be liable to be prosecuted by any one who is
willing to inflict retribution on behalf of the dead.  And he who would
avenge a murder shall observe all the precautionary ceremonies of lavation,
and any others which the God commands in cases of this kind.  Let him have
proclamation made, and then go forth and compel the perpetrator to suffer
the execution of justice according to the law.  Now the legislator may
easily show that these things must be accomplished by prayers and
sacrifices to certain Gods, who are concerned with the prevention of
murders in states.  But who these Gods are, and what should be the true
manner of instituting such trials with due regard to religion, the
guardians of the law, aided by the interpreters, and the prophets, and the
God, shall determine, and when they have determined let them carry on the
prosecution at law.  The cause shall have the same judges who are appointed
to decide in the case of those who plunder temples.  Let him who is
convicted be punished with death, and let him not be buried in the country
of the murdered man, for this would be shameless as well as impious.  But
if he fly and will not stand his trial, let him fly for ever; or, if he set
foot anywhere on any part of the murdered man's country, let any relation
of the deceased, or any other citizen who may first happen to meet with
him, kill him with impunity, or bind and deliver him to those among the
judges of the case who are magistrates, that they may put him to death. 
And let the prosecutor demand surety of him whom he prosecutes; three
sureties sufficient in the opinion of the magistrates who try the cause
shall be provided by him, and they shall undertake to produce him at the
trial.  But if he be unwilling or unable to provide sureties, then the
magistrates shall take him and keep him in bonds, and produce him at the
day of trial.

If a man do not commit a murder with his own hand, but contrives the death
of another, and is the author of the deed in intention and design, and he
continues to dwell in the city, having his soul not pure of the guilt of
murder, let him be tried in the same way, except in what relates to the
sureties; and also, if he be found guilty, his body after execution may
have burial in his native land, but in all other respects his case shall be
as the former; and whether a stranger shall kill a citizen, or a citizen a
stranger, or a slave a slave, there shall be no difference as touching
murder by one's own hand or by contrivance, except in the matter of
sureties; and these, as has been said, shall be required of the actual
murderer only, and he who brings the accusation shall bind them over at the
time.  If a slave be convicted of slaying a freeman voluntarily, either by
his own hand or by contrivance, let the public executioner take him in the
direction of the sepulchre, to a place whence he can see the tomb of the
dead man, and inflict upon him as many stripes as the person who caught him
orders, and if he survive, let him put him to death.  And if any one kills
a slave who has done no wrong, because he is afraid that he may inform of
some base and evil deeds of his own, or for any similar reason, in such a
case let him pay the penalty of murder, as he would have done if he had
slain a citizen.  There are things about which it is terrible and
unpleasant to legislate, but impossible not to legislate.  If, for example,
there should be murders of kinsmen, either perpetrated by the hands of
kinsmen, or by their contrivance, voluntary and purely malicious, which
most often happen in ill-regulated and ill-educated states, and may perhaps
occur even in a country where a man would not expect to find them, we must
repeat once more the tale which we narrated a little while ago, in the hope
that he who hears us will be the more disposed to abstain voluntarily on
these grounds from murders which are utterly abominable.  For the myth, or
saying, or whatever we ought to call it, has been plainly set forth by
priests of old; they have pronounced that the justice which guards and
avenges the blood of kindred, follows the law of retaliation, and ordains
that he who has done any murderous act should of necessity suffer that
which he has done.  He who has slain a father shall himself be slain at
some time or other by his children,--if a mother, he shall of necessity
take a woman's nature, and lose his life at the hands of his offspring in
after ages; for where the blood of a family has been polluted there is no
other purification, nor can the pollution be washed out until the homicidal
soul which the deed has given life for life, and has propitiated and laid
to sleep the wrath of the whole family.  These are the retributions of
Heaven, and by such punishments men should be deterred.  But if they are
not deterred, and any one should be incited by some fatality to deprive his
father, or mother, or brethren, or children, of life voluntarily and of
purpose, for him the earthly lawgiver legislates as follows:--There shall
be the same proclamations about outlawry, and there shall be the same
sureties which have been enacted in the former cases.  But in his case, if
he be convicted, the servants of the judges and the magistrates shall slay
him at an appointed place without the city where three ways meet, and there
expose his body naked, and each of the magistrates on behalf of the whole
city shall take a stone and cast it upon the head of the dead man, and so
deliver the city from pollution; after that, they shall bear him to the
borders of the land, and cast him forth unburied, according to law.  And
what shall he suffer who slays him who of all men, as they say, is his own
best friend?  I mean the suicide, who deprives himself by violence of his
appointed share of life, not because the law of the state requires him, nor
yet under the compulsion of some painful and inevitable misfortune which
has come upon him, nor because he has had to suffer from irremediable and
intolerable shame, but who from sloth or want of manliness imposes upon
himself an unjust penalty.  For him, what ceremonies there are to be of
purification and burial God knows, and about these the next of kin should
enquire of the interpreters and of the laws thereto relating, and do
according to their injunctions.  They who meet their death in this way
shall be buried alone, and none shall be laid by their side; they shall be
buried ingloriously in the borders of the twelve portions of the land, in
such places as are uncultivated and nameless, and no column or inscription
shall mark the place of their interment.  And if a beast of burden or other
animal cause the death of any one, except in the case of anything of that
kind happening to a competitor in the public contests, the kinsmen of the
deceased shall prosecute the slayer for murder, and the wardens of the
country, such, and so many as the kinsmen appoint, shall try the cause, and
let the beast when condemned be slain by them, and let them cast it beyond
the borders.  And if any lifeless thing deprive a man of life, except in
the case of a thunderbolt or other fatal dart sent from the Gods,--whether
a man is killed by lifeless objects falling upon him, or by his falling
upon them, the nearest of kin shall appoint the nearest neighbour to be a
judge, and thereby acquit himself and the whole family of guilt.  And he
shall cast forth the guilty thing beyond the border, as has been said about
the animals.

If a man is found dead, and his murderer be unknown, and after a diligent
search cannot be detected, there shall be the same proclamation as in the
previous cases, and the same interdict on the murderer; and having
proceeded against him, they shall proclaim in the agora by a herald, that
he who has slain such and such a person, and has been convicted of murder,
shall not set his foot in the temples, nor at all in the country of the
murdered man, and if he appears and is discovered, he shall die, and be
cast forth unburied beyond the border.  Let this one law then be laid down
by us about murder; and let cases of this sort be so regarded.

And now let us say in what cases and under what circumstances the murderer
is rightly free from guilt:--If a man catch a thief coming into his house
by night to steal, and he take and kill him, or if he slay a footpad in
self-defence, he shall be guiltless.  And any one who does violence to a
free woman or a youth, shall be slain with impunity by the injured person,
or by his or her father or brothers or sons.  If a man find his wife
suffering violence, he may kill the violator, and be guiltless in the eye
of the law; or if a person kill another in warding off death from his
father or mother or children or brethren or wife who are doing no wrong, he
shall assuredly be guiltless.

Thus much as to the nurture and education of the living soul of man, having
which, he can, and without which, if he unfortunately be without them, he
cannot live; and also concerning the punishments which are to be inflicted
for violent deaths, let thus much be enacted.  Of the nurture and education
of the body we have spoken before, and next in order we have to speak of
deeds of violence, voluntary and involuntary, which men do to one another;
these we will now distinguish, as far as we are able, according to their
nature and number, and determine what will be the suitable penalties of
each, and so assign to them their proper place in the series of our
enactments.  The poorest legislator will have no difficulty in determining
that wounds and mutilations arising out of wounds should follow next in
order after deaths.  Let wounds be divided as homicides were divided--into
those which are involuntary, and which are given in passion or from fear,
and those inflicted voluntarily and with premeditation.  Concerning all
this, we must make some such proclamation as the following:--Mankind must
have laws, and conform to them, or their life would be as bad as that of
the most savage beast (compare Arist. Pol.).  And the reason of this is
that no man's nature is able to know what is best for human society; or
knowing, always able and willing to do what is best.  In the first place,
there is a difficulty in apprehending that the true art of politics is
concerned, not with private but with public good (for public good binds
together states, but private only distracts them); and that both the public
and private good as well of individuals as of states is greater when the
state and not the individual is first considered.  In the second place,
although a person knows in the abstract that this is true, yet if he be
possessed of absolute and irresponsible power, he will never remain firm in
his principles or persist in regarding the public good as primary in the
state, and the private good as secondary.  Human nature will be always
drawing him into avarice and selfishness, avoiding pain and pursuing
pleasure without any reason, and will bring these to the front, obscuring
the juster and better; and so working darkness in his soul will at last
fill with evils both him and the whole city.  For if a man were born so
divinely gifted that he could naturally apprehend the truth, he would have
no need of laws to rule over him (compare Statesman); for there is no law
or order which is above knowledge, nor can mind, without impiety, be deemed
the subject or slave of any man, but rather the lord of all.  I speak of
mind, true and free, and in harmony with nature.  But then there is no such
mind anywhere, or at least not much; and therefore we must choose law and
order, which are second best.  These look at things as they exist for the
most part only, and are unable to survey the whole of them.  And therefore
I have spoken as I have.

And now we will determine what penalty he ought to pay or suffer who has
hurt or wounded another.  Any one may easily imagine the questions which
have to be asked in all such cases:--What did he wound, or whom, or how, or
when? for there are innumerable particulars of this sort which greatly vary
from one another.  And to allow courts of law to determine all these
things, or not to determine any of them, is alike impossible.  There is one
particular which they must determine in all cases--the question of fact. 
And then, again, that the legislator should not permit them to determine
what punishment is to be inflicted in any of these cases, but should
himself decide about all of them, small or great, is next to impossible.

CLEINIAS:  Then what is to be the inference?

ATHENIAN:  The inference is, that some things should be left to courts of
law; others the legislator must decide for himself.

CLEINIAS:  And what ought the legislator to decide, and what ought he to
leave to courts of law?

ATHENIAN:  I may reply, that in a state in which the courts are bad and
mute, because the judges conceal their opinions and decide causes
clandestinely; or what is worse, when they are disorderly and noisy, as in
a theatre, clapping or hooting in turn this or that orator--I say that then
there is a very serious evil, which affects the whole state.  Unfortunate
is the necessity of having to legislate for such courts, but where the
necessity exists, the legislator should only allow them to ordain the
penalties for the smallest offences; if the state for which he is
legislating be of this character, he must take most matters into his own
hands and speak distinctly.  But when a state has good courts, and the
judges are well trained and scrupulously tested, the determination of the
penalties or punishments which shall be inflicted on the guilty may fairly
and with advantage be left to them.  And we are not to be blamed for not
legislating concerning all that large class of matters which judges far
worse educated than ours would be able to determine, assigning to each
offence what is due both to the perpetrator and to the sufferer.  We
believe those for whom we are legislating to be best able to judge, and
therefore to them the greater part may be left.  At the same time, as I
have often said, we should exhibit to the judges, as we have done, the
outline and form of the punishments to be inflicted, and then they will not
transgress the just rule.  That was an excellent practice, which we
observed before, and which now that we are resuming the work of
legislation, may with advantage be repeated by us.

Let the enactment about wounding be in the following terms:--If any one has
a purpose and intention to slay another who is not his enemy, and whom the
law does not permit him to slay, and he wounds him, but is unable to kill
him, he who had the intent and has wounded him is not to be pitied--he
deserves no consideration, but should be regarded as a murderer and be
tried for murder.  Still having respect to the fortune which has in a
manner favoured him, and to the providence which in pity to him and to the
wounded man saved the one from a fatal blow, and the other from an accursed
fate and calamity--as a thank-offering to this deity, and in order not to
oppose his will--in such a case the law will remit the punishment of death,
and only compel the offender to emigrate to a neighbouring city for the
rest of his life, where he shall remain in the enjoyment of all his
possessions.  But if he have injured the wounded man, he shall make such
compensation for the injury as the court deciding the cause shall assess,
and the same judges shall decide who would have decided if the man had died
of his wounds.  And if a child intentionally wound his parents, or a
servant his master, death shall be the penalty.  And if a brother or a
sister intentionally wound a brother or a sister, and is found guilty,
death shall be the penalty.  And if a husband wound a wife, or a wife a
husband, with intent to kill, let him or her undergo perpetual exile; if
they have sons or daughters who are still young, the guardians shall take
care of their property, and have charge of the children as orphans.  If
their sons are grown up, they shall be under no obligation to support the
exiled parent, but they shall possess the property themselves.  And if he
who meets with such a misfortune has no children, the kindred of the exiled
man to the degree of sons of cousins, both on the male and female side,
shall meet together, and after taking counsel with the guardians of the law
and the priests, shall appoint a 5040th citizen to be the heir of the
house, considering and reasoning that no house of all the 5040 belongs to
the inhabitant or to the whole family, but is the public and private
property of the state.  Now the state should seek to have its houses as
holy and happy as possible.  And if any one of the houses be unfortunate,
and stained with impiety, and the owner leave no posterity, but dies
unmarried, or married and childless, having suffered death as the penalty
of murder or some other crime committed against the Gods or against his
fellow-citizens, of which death is the penalty distinctly laid down in the
law; or if any of the citizens be in perpetual exile, and also childless,
that house shall first of all be purified and undergo expiation according
to law; and then let the kinsmen of the house, as we were just now saying,
and the guardians of the law, meet and consider what family there is in the
state which is of the highest repute for virtue and also for good fortune,
in which there are a number of sons; from that family let them take one and
introduce him to the father and forefathers of the dead man as their son,
and, for the sake of the omen, let him be called so, that he may be the
continuer of their family, the keeper of their hearth, and the minister of
their sacred rites with better fortune than his father had; and when they
have made this supplication, they shall make him heir according to law, and
the offending person they shall leave nameless and childless and
portionless when calamities such as these overtake him.

Now the boundaries of some things do not touch one another, but there is a
borderland which comes in between, preventing them from touching.  And we
were saying that actions done from passion are of this nature, and come in
between the voluntary and involuntary.  If a person be convicted of having
inflicted wounds in a passion, in the first place he shall pay twice the
amount of the injury, if the wound be curable, or, if incurable, four times
the amount of the injury; or if the wound be curable, and at the same time
cause great and notable disgrace to the wounded person, he shall pay
fourfold.  And whenever any one in wounding another injures not only the
sufferer, but also the city, and makes him incapable of defending his
country against the enemy, he, besides the other penalties, shall pay a
penalty for the loss which the state has incurred.  And the penalty shall
be, that in addition to his own times of service, he shall serve on behalf
of the disabled person, and shall take his place in war; or, if he refuse,
he shall be liable to be convicted by law of refusal to serve.  The
compensation for the injury, whether to be twofold or threefold or
fourfold, shall be fixed by the judges who convict him.  And if, in like
manner, a brother wounds a brother, the parents and kindred of either sex,
including the children of cousins, whether on the male or female side,
shall meet, and when they have judged the cause, they shall entrust the
assessment of damages to the parents, as is natural; and if the estimate be
disputed, then the kinsmen on the male side shall make the estimate, or if
they cannot, they shall commit the matter to the guardians of the law.  And
when similar charges of wounding are brought by children against their
parents, those who are more than sixty years of age, having children of
their own, not adopted, shall be required to decide; and if any one is
convicted, they shall determine whether he or she ought to die, or suffer
some other punishment either greater than death, or, at any rate, not much
less.  A kinsman of the offender shall not be allowed to judge the cause,
not even if he be of the age which is prescribed by the law.  If a slave in
a fit of anger wound a freeman, the owner of the slave shall give him up to
the wounded man, who may do as he pleases with him, and if be not give him
up he shall himself make good the injury.  And if any one says that the
slave and the wounded man are conspiring together, let him argue the point,
and if he is cast, he shall pay for the wrong three times over, but if he
gains his case, the freeman who conspired with the slave shall be liable to
an action for kidnapping.  And if any one unintentionally wounds another he
shall simply pay for the harm, for no legislator is able to control chance. 
In such a case the judges shall be the same as those who are appointed in
the case of children suing their parents; and they shall estimate the
amount of the injury.

All the preceding injuries and every kind of assault are deeds of violence;
and every man, woman, or child ought to consider that the elder has the
precedence of the younger in honour (compare Republic), both among the Gods
and also among men who would live in security and happiness.  Wherefore it
is a foul thing and hateful to the Gods to see an elder man assaulted by a
younger in the city; and it is reasonable that a young man when struck by
an elder should lightly endure his anger, laying up in store for himself a
like honour when he is old.  Let this be the law:--Every one shall
reverence his elder in word and deed; he shall respect any one who is
twenty years older than himself, whether male or female, regarding him or
her as his father or mother; and he shall abstain from laying hands on any
one who is of an age to have been his father or his mother, out of
reverence to the Gods who preside over birth; similarly he shall keep his
hands from a stranger, whether he be an old inhabitant or newly arrived; he
shall not venture to correct such an one by blows, either as the aggressor
or in self-defence.  If he thinks that some stranger has struck him out of
wantonness or insolence, and ought to be punished, he shall take him to the
wardens of the city, but let him not strike him, that the stranger may be
kept far away from the possibility of lifting up his hand against a
citizen, and let the wardens of the city take the offender and examine him,
not forgetting their duty to the God of Strangers, and in case the stranger
appears to have struck the citizen unjustly, let them inflict upon him as
many blows with the scourge as he has himself inflicted, and quell his
presumption.  But if he be innocent, they shall threaten and rebuke the man
who arrested him, and let them both go.  If a person strikes another of the
same age or somewhat older than himself, who has no children, whether he be
an old man who strikes an old man or a young man who strikes a young man,
let the person struck defend himself in the natural way without a weapon
and with his hands only.  He who, being more than forty years of age, dares
to fight with another, whether he be the aggressor or in self-defence,
shall be regarded as rude and ill-mannered and slavish;--this will be a
disgraceful punishment, and therefore suitable to him.  The obedient nature
will readily yield to such exhortations, but the disobedient, who heeds not
the prelude, shall have the law ready for him:--If any man smite another
who is older than himself, either by twenty or by more years, in the first
place, he who is at hand, not being younger than the combatants, nor their
equal in age, shall separate them, or be disgraced according to law; but if
he be the equal in age of the person who is struck or younger, he shall
defend the person injured as he would a brother or father or still older
relative.  Further, let him who dares to smite an elder be tried for
assault, as I have said, and if he be found guilty, let him be imprisoned
for a period of not less than a year, or if the judges approve of a longer
period, their decision shall be final.  But if a stranger or metic smite
one who is older by twenty years or more, the same law shall hold about the
bystanders assisting, and he who is found guilty in such a suit, if he be a
stranger but not resident, shall be imprisoned during a period of two
years; and a metic who disobeys the laws shall be imprisoned for three
years, unless the court assign him a longer term.  And let him who was
present in any of these cases and did not assist according to law be
punished, if he be of the highest class, by paying a fine of a mina; or if
he be of the second class, of fifty drachmas; or if of the third class, by
a fine of thirty drachmas; or if he be of the fourth class, by a fine of
twenty drachmas; and the generals and taxiarchs and phylarchs and hipparchs
shall form the court in such cases.

Laws are partly framed for the sake of good men, in order to instruct them
how they thay live on friendly terms with one another, and partly for the
sake of those who refuse to be instructed, whose spirit cannot be subdued,
or softened, or hindered from plunging into evil.  These are the persons
who cause the word to be spoken which I am about to utter; for them the
legislator legislates of necessity, and in the hope that there may be no
need of his laws.  He who shall dare to lay violent hands upon his father
or mother, or any still older relative, having no fear either of the wrath
of the Gods above, or of the punishments that are spoken of in the world
below, but transgresses in contempt of ancient and universal traditions as
though he were too wise to believe in them, requires some extreme measure
of prevention.  Now death is not the worst that can happen to men; far
worse are the punishments which are said to pursue them in the world below. 
But although they are most true tales, they work on such souls no
prevention; for if they had any effect there would be no slayers of
mothers, or impious hands lifted up against parents; and therefore the
punishments of this world which are inflicted during life ought not in such
cases to fall short, if possible, of the terrors of the world below.  Let
our enactment then be as follows:--If a man dare to strike his father or
his mother, or their fathers or mothers, he being at the time of sound
mind, then let any one who is at hand come to the rescue as has been
already said, and the metic or stranger who comes to the rescue shall be
called to the first place in the games; but if he do not come he shall
suffer the punishment of perpetual exile.  He who is not a metic, if he
comes to the rescue, shall have praise, and if he do not come, blame.  And
if a slave come to the rescue, let him be made free, but if he do not come
the rescue, let him receive 100 strokes of the whip, by order of the
wardens of the agora, if the occurrence take place in the agora; or if
somewhere in the city beyond the limits of the agora, any warden of the
city who is in residence shall punish him; or if in the country, then the
commanders of the wardens of the country.  If those who are near at the
time be inhabitants of the same place, whether they be youths, or men, or
women, let them come to the rescue and denounce him as the impious one; and
he who does not come to the rescue shall fall under the curse of Zeus, the
God of kindred and of ancestors, according to law.  And if any one is found
guilty of assaulting a parent, let him in the first place be for ever
banished from the city into the country, and let him abstain from the
temples; and if he do not abstain, the wardens of the country shall punish
him with blows, or in any way which they please, and if he return he shall
be put to death.  And if any freeman eat or drink, or have any other sort
of intercourse with him, or only meeting him have voluntarily touched him,
he shall not enter into any temple, nor into the agora, nor into the city,
until he is purified; for he should consider that he has become tainted by
a curse.  And if he disobeys the law, and pollutes the city and the temples
contrary to law, and one of the magistrates sees him and does not indict
him, when he gives in his account this omission shall be a most serious
charge.

If a slave strike a freeman, whether a stranger or a citizen, let any one
who is present come to the rescue, or pay the penalty already mentioned;
and let the bystanders bind him, and deliver him up to the injured person,
and he receiving him shall put him in chains, and inflict on him as many
stripes as he pleases; but having punished him he must surrender him to his
master according to law, and not deprive him of his property.  Let the law
be as follows:--The slave who strikes a freeman, not at the command of the
magistrates, his owner shall receive bound from the man whom he has
stricken, and not release him until the slave has persuaded the man whom he
has stricken that he ought to be released.  And let there be the same laws
about women in relation to women, and about men and women in relation to
one another.


BOOK X.

And now having spoken of assaults, let us sum up all acts of violence under
a single law, which shall be as follows:--No one shall take or carry away
any of his neighbour's goods, neither shall he use anything which is his
neighbour's without the consent of the owner; for these are the offences
which are and have been, and will ever be, the source of all the aforesaid
evils.  The greatest of them are excesses and insolences of youth, and are
offences against the greatest when they are done against religion; and
especially great when in violation of public and holy rites, or of the
partly-common rites in which tribes and phratries share; and in the second
degree great when they are committed against private rites and sepulchres,
and in the third degree (not to repeat the acts formerly mentioned), when
insults are offered to parents; the fourth kind of violence is when any
one, regardless of the authority of the rulers, takes or carries away or
makes use of anything which belongs to them, not having their consent; and
the fifth kind is when the violation of the civil rights of an individual
demands reparation.  There should be a common law embracing all these
cases.  For we have already said in general terms what shall be the
punishment of sacrilege, whether fraudulent or violent, and now we have to
determine what is to be the punishment of those who speak or act insolently
toward the Gods.  But first we must give them an admonition which may be in
the following terms:--No one who in obedience to the laws believed that
there were Gods, ever intentionally did any unholy act, or uttered any
unlawful word; but he who did must have supposed one of three things,--
either that they did not exist,--which is the first possibility, or
secondly, that, if they did, they took no care of man, or thirdly, that
they were easily appeased and turned aside from their purpose by sacrifices
and prayers.

CLEINIAS:  What shall we say or do to these persons?

ATHENIAN:  My good friend, let us first hear the jests which I suspect that
they in their superiority will utter against us.

CLEINIAS:  What jests?

ATHENIAN:  They will make some irreverent speech of this sort:--'O
inhabitants of Athens, and Sparta, and Cnosus,' they will reply, 'in that
you speak truly; for some of us deny the very existence of the Gods, while
others, as you say, are of opinion that they do not care about us; and
others that they are turned from their course by gifts.  Now we have a
right to claim, as you yourself allowed, in the matter of laws, that before
you are hard upon us and threaten us, you should argue with us and convince
us--you should first attempt to teach and persuade us that there are Gods
by reasonable evidences, and also that they are too good to be unrighteous,
or to be propitiated, or turned from their course by gifts.  For when we
hear such things said of them by those who are esteemed to be the best of
poets, and orators, and prophets, and priests, and by innumerable others,
the thoughts of most of us are not set upon abstaining from unrighteous
acts, but upon doing them and atoning for them (compare Republic).  When
lawgivers profess that they are gentle and not stern, we think that they
should first of all use persuasion to us, and show us the existence of
Gods, if not in a better manner than other men, at any rate in a truer; and
who knows but that we shall hearken to you?  If then our request is a fair
one, please to accept our challenge.'

CLEINIAS:  But is there any difficulty in proving the existence of the
Gods?

ATHENIAN:  How would you prove it?

CLEINIAS:  How?  In the first place, the earth and the sun, and the stars
and the universe, and the fair order of the seasons, and the division of
them into years and months, furnish proofs of their existence; and also
there is the fact that all Hellenes and barbarians believe in them.

ATHENIAN:  I fear, my sweet friend, though I will not say that I much
regard, the contempt with which the profane will be likely to assail us. 
For you do not understand the nature of their complaint, and you fancy that
they rush into impiety only from a love of sensual pleasure.

CLEINIAS:  Why, Stranger, what other reason is there?

ATHENIAN:  One which you who live in a different atmosphere would never
guess.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  A very grievous sort of ignorance which is imagined to be the
greatest wisdom.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  At Athens there are tales preserved in writing which the virtue
of your state, as I am informed, refuses to admit.  They speak of the Gods
in prose as well as verse, and the oldest of them tell of the origin of the
heavens and of the world, and not far from the beginning of their story
they proceed to narrate the birth of the Gods, and how after they were born
they behaved to one another.  Whether these stories have in other ways a
good or a bad influence, I should not like to be severe upon them, because
they are ancient; but, looking at them with reference to the duties of
children to their parents, I cannot praise them, or think that they are
useful, or at all true (compare Republic).  Of the words of the ancients I
have nothing more to say; and I should wish to say of them only what is
pleasing to the Gods.  But as to our younger generation and their wisdom, I
cannot let them off when they do mischief.  For do but mark the effect of
their words:  when you and I argue for the existence of the Gods, and
produce the sun, moon, stars, and earth, claiming for them a divine being,
if we would listen to the aforesaid philosophers we should say that they
are earth and stones only (compare Apology), which can have no care at all
of human affairs, and that all religion is a cooking up of words and a
make-believe.

CLEINIAS:  One such teacher, O Stranger, would be bad enough, and you imply
that there are many of them, which is worse.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then; what shall we say or do?--Shall we assume that some
one is accusing us among unholy men, who are trying to escape from the
effect of our legislation; and that they say of us--How dreadful that you
should legislate on the supposition that there are Gods!  Shall we make a
defence of ourselves? or shall we leave them and return to our laws, lest
the prelude should become longer than the law?  For the discourse will
certainly extend to great length, if we are to treat the impiously disposed
as they desire, partly demonstrating to them at some length the things of
which they demand an explanation, partly making them afraid or
dissatisfied, and then proceed to the requisite enactments.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, Stranger; but then how often have we repeated already that
on the present occasion there is no reason why brevity should be preferred
to length; for who is 'at our heels?'--as the saying goes, and it would be
paltry and ridiculous to prefer the shorter to the better.  It is a matter
of no small consequence, in some way or other to prove that there are Gods,
and that they are good, and regard justice more than men do.  The
demonstration of this would be the best and noblest prelude of all our
laws.  And therefore, without impatience, and without hurry, let us
unreservedly consider the whole matter, summoning up all the power of
persuasion which we possess.

ATHENIAN:  Seeing you thus in earnest, I would fain offer up a prayer that
I may succeed:--but I must proceed at once.  Who can be calm when he is
called upon to prove the existence of the Gods?  Who can avoid hating and
abhorring the men who are and have been the cause of this argument; I speak
of those who will not believe the tales which they have heard as babes and
sucklings from their mothers and nurses, repeated by them both in jest and
earnest, like charms, who have also heard them in the sacrificial prayers,
and seen sights accompanying them--sights and sounds delightful to
children,--and their parents during the sacrifices showing an intense
earnestness on behalf of their children and of themselves, and with eager
interest talking to the Gods, and beseeching them, as though they were
firmly convinced of their existence; who likewise see and hear the
prostrations and invocations which are made by Hellenes and barbarians at
the rising and setting of the sun and moon, in all the vicissitudes of
life, not as if they thought that there were no Gods, but as if there could
be no doubt of their existence, and no suspicion of their non-existence;
when men, knowing all these things, despise them on no real grounds, as
would be admitted by all who have any particle of intelligence, and when
they force us to say what we are now saying, how can any one in gentle
terms remonstrate with the like of them, when he has to begin by proving to
them the very existence of the Gods?  Yet the attempt must be made; for it
would be unseemly that one half of mankind should go mad in their lust of
pleasure, and the other half in their indignation at such persons.  Our
address to these lost and perverted natures should not be spoken in
passion; let us suppose ourselves to select some one of them, and gently
reason with him, smothering our anger:--O my son, we will say to him, you
are young, and the advance of time will make you reverse may of the
opinions which you now hold.  Wait awhile, and do not attempt to judge at
present of the highest things; and that is the highest of which you now
think nothing--to know the Gods rightly and to live accordingly.  And in
the first place let me indicate to you one point which is of great
importance, and about which I cannot be deceived:--You and your friends are
not the first who have held this opinion about the Gods.  There have always
been persons more or less numerous who have had the same disorder.  I have
known many of them, and can tell you, that no one who had taken up in youth
this opinion, that the Gods do not exist, ever continued in the same until
he was old; the two other notions certainly do continue in some cases, but
not in many; the notion, I mean, that the Gods exist, but take no heed of
human things, and the other notion that they do take heed of them, but are
easily propitiated with sacrifices and prayers.  As to the opinion about
the Gods which may some day become clear to you, I advise you to wait and
consider if it be true or not; ask of others, and above all of the
legislator.  In the meantime take care that you do not offend against the
Gods.  For the duty of the legislator is and always will be to teach you
the truth of these matters.

CLEINIAS:  Our address, Stranger, thus far, is excellent.

ATHENIAN:  Quite true, Megillus and Cleinias, but I am afraid that we have
unconsciously lighted on a strange doctrine.

CLEINIAS:  What doctrine do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  The wisest of all doctrines, in the opinion of many.

CLEINIAS:  I wish that you would speak plainer.

ATHENIAN:  The doctrine that all things do become, have become, and will
become, some by nature, some by art, and some by chance.

CLEINIAS:  Is not that true?

ATHENIAN:  Well, philosophers are probably right; at any rate we may as
well follow in their track, and examine what is the meaning of them and
their disciples.

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  They say that the greatest and fairest things are the work of
nature and of chance, the lesser of art, which, receiving from nature the
greater and primeval creations, moulds and fashions all those lesser works
which are generally termed artificial.

CLEINIAS:  How is that?

ATHENIAN:  I will explain my meaning still more clearly.  They say that
fire and water, and earth and air, all exist by nature and chance, and none
of them by art, and that as to the bodies which come next in order,--earth,
and sun, and moon, and stars,--they have been created by means of these
absolutely inanimate existences.  The elements are severally moved by
chance and some inherent force according to certain affinities among them--
of hot with cold, or of dry with moist, or of soft with hard, and according
to all the other accidental admixtures of opposites which have been formed
by necessity.  After this fashion and in this manner the whole heaven has
been created, and all that is in the heaven, as well as animals and all
plants, and all the seasons come from these elements, not by the action of
mind, as they say, or of any God, or from art, but as I was saying, by
nature and chance only.  Art sprang up afterwards and out of these, mortal
and of mortal birth, and produced in play certain images and very partial
imitations of the truth, having an affinity to one another, such as music
and painting create and their companion arts.  And there are other arts
which have a serious purpose, and these co-operate with nature, such, for
example, as medicine, and husbandry, and gymnastic.  And they say that
politics cooperate with nature, but in a less degree, and have more of art;
also that legislation is entirely a work of art, and is based on
assumptions which are not true.

CLEINIAS:  How do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  In the first place, my dear friend, these people would say that
the Gods exist not by nature, but by art, and by the laws of states, which
are different in different places, according to the agreement of those who
make them; and that the honourable is one thing by nature and another thing
by law, and that the principles of justice have no existence at all in
nature, but that mankind are always disputing about them and altering them;
and that the alterations which are made by art and by law have no basis in
nature, but are of authority for the moment and at the time at which they
are made.--These, my friends, are the sayings of wise men, poets and prose
writers, which find a way into the minds of youth.  They are told by them
that the highest right is might, and in this way the young fall into
impieties, under the idea that the Gods are not such as the law bids them
imagine; and hence arise factions, these philosophers inviting them to lead
a true life according to nature, that is, to live in real dominion over
others, and not in legal subjection to them.  (Compare Gorg.)

CLEINIAS:  What a dreadful picture, Stranger, have you given, and how great
is the injury which is thus inflicted on young men to the ruin both of
states and families!

ATHENIAN:  True, Cleinias; but then what should the lawgiver do when this
evil is of long standing? should he only rise up in the state and threaten
all mankind, proclaiming that if they will not say and think that the Gods
are such as the law ordains (and this may be extended generally to the
honourable, the just, and to all the highest things, and to all that
relates to virtue and vice), and if they will not make their actions
conform to the copy which the law gives them, then he who refuses to obey
the law shall die, or suffer stripes and bonds, or privation of
citizenship, or in some cases be punished by loss of property and exile? 
Should he not rather, when he is making laws for men, at the same time
infuse the spirit of persuasion into his words, and mitigate the severity
of them as far as he can?

CLEINIAS:  Why, Stranger, if such persuasion be at all possible, then a
legislator who has anything in him ought never to weary of persuading men;
he ought to leave nothing unsaid in support of the ancient opinion that
there are Gods, and of all those other truths which you were just now
mentioning; he ought to support the law and also art, and acknowledge that
both alike exist by nature, and no less than nature, if they are the
creations of mind in accordance with right reason, as you appear to me to
maintain, and I am disposed to agree with you in thinking.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, my enthusiastic Cleinias; but are not these things when
spoken to a multitude hard to be understood, not to mention that they take
up a dismal length of time?

CLEINIAS:  Why, Stranger, shall we, whose patience failed not when drinking
or music were the themes of discourse, weary now of discoursing about the
Gods, and about divine things?  And the greatest help to rational
legislation is that the laws when once written down are always at rest;
they can be put to the test at any future time, and therefore, if on first
hearing they seem difficult, there is no reason for apprehension about
them, because any man however dull can go over them and consider them again
and again; nor if they are tedious but useful, is there any reason or
religion, as it seems to me, in any man refusing to maintain the principles
of them to the utmost of his power.

MEGILLUS:  Stranger, I like what Cleinias is saying.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, Megillus, and we should do as he proposes; for if impious
discourses were not scattered, as I may say, throughout the world, there
would have been no need for any vindication of the existence of the Gods--
but seeing that they are spread far and wide, such arguments are needed;
and who should come to the rescue of the greatest laws, when they are being
undermined by bad men, but the legislator himself?

MEGILLUS:  There is no more proper champion of them.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, tell me, Cleinias--for I must ask you to be my
partner,--does not he who talks in this way conceive fire and water and
earth and air to be the first elements of all things (compare Timaeus)?
these he calls nature, and out of these he supposes the soul to be formed
afterwards; and this is not a mere conjecture of ours about his meaning,
but is what he really means.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Then, by Heaven, we have discovered the source of this vain
opinion of all those physical investigators; and I would have you examine
their arguments with the utmost care, for their impiety is a very serious
matter; they not only make a bad and mistaken use of argument, but they
lead away the minds of others:  that is my opinion of them.

CLEINIAS:  You are right; but I should like to know how this happens.

ATHENIAN:  I fear that the argument may seem singular.

CLEINIAS:  Do not hesitate, Stranger; I see that you are afraid of such a
discussion carrying you beyond the limits of legislation.  But if there be
no other way of showing our agreement in the belief that there are Gods, of
whom the law is said now to approve, let us take this way, my good sir.

ATHENIAN:  Then I suppose that I must repeat the singular argument of those
who manufacture the soul according to their own impious notions; they
affirm that which is the first cause of the generation and destruction of
all things, to be not first, but last, and that which is last to be first,
and hence they have fallen into error about the true nature of the Gods.

CLEINIAS:  Still I do not understand you.

ATHENIAN:  Nearly all of them, my friends, seem to be ignorant of the
nature and power of the soul, especially in what relates to her origin: 
they do not know that she is among the first of things, and before all
bodies, and is the chief author of their changes and transpositions.  And
if this is true, and if the soul is older than the body, must not the
things which are of the soul's kindred be of necessity prior to those which
appertain to the body?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then thought and attention and mind and art and law will be
prior to that which is hard and soft and heavy and light; and the great and
primitive works and actions will be works of art; they will be the first,
and after them will come nature and works of nature, which however is a
wrong term for men to apply to them; these will follow, and will be under
the government of art and mind.

CLEINIAS:  But why is the word 'nature' wrong?

ATHENIAN:  Because those who use the term mean to say that nature is the
first creative power; but if the soul turn out to be the primeval element,
and not fire or air, then in the truest sense and beyond other things the
soul may be said to exist by nature; and this would be true if you proved
that the soul is older than the body, but not otherwise.

CLEINIAS:  You are quite right.

ATHENIAN:  Shall we, then, take this as the next point to which our
attention should be directed?

CLEINIAS:  By all means.

ATHENIAN:  Let us be on our guard lest this most deceptive argument with
its youthful looks, beguiling us old men, give us the slip and make a
laughing-stock of us.  Who knows but we may be aiming at the greater, and
fail of attaining the lesser?  Suppose that we three have to pass a rapid
river, and I, being the youngest of the three and experienced in rivers,
take upon me the duty of making the attempt first by myself; leaving you in
safety on the bank, I am to examine whether the river is passable by older
men like yourselves, and if such appears to be the case then I shall invite
you to follow, and my experience will help to convey you across; but if the
river is impassable by you, then there will have been no danger to anybody
but myself,--would not that seem to be a very fair proposal?  I mean to say
that the argument in prospect is likely to be too much for you, out of your
depth and beyond your strength, and I should be afraid that the stream of
my questions might create in you who are not in the habit of answering,
giddiness and confusion of mind, and hence a feeling of unpleasantness and
unsuitableness might arise.  I think therefore that I had better first ask
the questions and then answer them myself while you listen in safety; in
that way I can carry on the argument until I have completed the proof that
the soul is prior to the body.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent, Stranger, and I hope that you will do as you propose.

ATHENIAN:  Come, then, and if ever we are to call upon the Gods, let us
call upon them now in all seriousness to come to the demonstration of their
own existence.  And so holding fast to the rope we will venture upon the
depths of the argument.  When questions of this sort are asked of me, my
safest answer would appear to be as follows:--Some one says to me, 'O
Stranger, are all things at rest and nothing in motion, or is the exact
opposite of this true, or are some things in motion and others at rest?'--
To this I shall reply that some things are in motion and others at rest. 
'And do not things which move in a place, and are not the things which are
at rest at rest in a place?'  Certainly.  'And some move or rest in one
place and some in more places than one?'  You mean to say, we shall rejoin,
that those things which rest at the centre move in one place, just as the
circumference goes round of globes which are said to be at rest?  'Yes.' 
And we observe that, in the revolution, the motion which carries round the
larger and the lesser circle at the same time is proportionally distributed
to greater and smaller, and is greater and smaller in a certain proportion. 
Here is a wonder which might be thought an impossibility, that the same
motion should impart swiftness and slowness in due proportion to larger and
lesser circles.  'Very true.'  And when you speak of bodies moving in many
places, you seem to me to mean those which move from one place to another,
and sometimes have one centre of motion and sometimes more than one because
they turn upon their axis; and whenever they meet anything, if it be
stationary, they are divided by it; but if they get in the midst between
bodies which are approaching and moving towards the same spot from opposite
directions, they unite with them.  'I admit the truth of what you are
saying.'  Also when they unite they grow, and when they are divided they
waste away,--that is, supposing the constitution of each to remain, or if
that fails, then there is a second reason of their dissolution.  'And when
are all things created and how?'  Clearly, they are created when the first
principle receives increase and attains to the second dimension, and from
this arrives at the one which is neighbour to this, and after reaching the
third becomes perceptible to sense.  Everything which is thus changing and
moving is in process of generation; only when at rest has it real
existence, but when passing into another state it is destroyed utterly. 
Have we not mentioned all motions that there are, and comprehended them
under their kinds and numbered them with the exception, my friends, of two?

CLEINIAS:  Which are they?

ATHENIAN:  Just the two, with which our present enquiry is concerned.

CLEINIAS:  Speak plainer.

ATHENIAN:  I suppose that our enquiry has reference to the soul?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Let us assume that there is a motion able to move other things,
but not to move itself;--that is one kind; and there is another kind which
can move itself as well as other things, working in composition and
decomposition, by increase and diminution and generation and destruction,--
that is also one of the many kinds of motion.

CLEINIAS:  Granted.

ATHENIAN:  And we will assume that which moves other, and is changed by
other, to be the ninth, and that which changes itself and others, and is
co-incident with every action and every passion, and is the true principle
of change and motion in all that is,--that we shall be inclined to call the
tenth.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And which of these ten motions ought we to prefer as being the
mightiest and most efficient?

CLEINIAS:  I must say that the motion which is able to move itself is ten
thousand times superior to all the others.  (Compare Timaeus.)

ATHENIAN:  Very good; but may I make one or two corrections in what I have
been saying?

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  When I spoke of the tenth sort of motion, that was not quite
correct.

CLEINIAS:  What was the error?

ATHENIAN:  According to the true order, the tenth was really the first in
generation and power; then follows the second, which was strangely enough
termed the ninth by us.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean this:  when one thing changes another, and that another,
of such will there be any primary changing element?  How can a thing which
is moved by another ever be the beginning of change?  Impossible.  But when
the self-moved changes other, and that again other, and thus thousands upon
tens of thousands of bodies are set in motion, must not the beginning of
all this motion be the change of the self-moving principle?  (Compare
Phaedr.)

CLEINIAS:  Very true, and I quite agree.

ATHENIAN:  Or, to put the question in another way, making answer to
ourselves:--If, as most of these philosophers have the audacity to affirm,
all things were at rest in one mass, which of the above-mentioned
principles of motion would first spring up among them?

CLEINIAS:  Clearly the self-moving; for there could be no change in them
arising out of any external cause; the change must first take place in
themselves.

ATHENIAN:  Then we must say that self-motion being the origin of all
motions, and the first which arises among things at rest as well as among
things in motion, is the eldest and mightiest principle of change, and that
which is changed by another and yet moves other is second.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  At this stage of the argument let us put a question.

CLEINIAS:  What question?

ATHENIAN:  If we were to see this power existing in any earthy, watery, or
fiery substance, simple or compound--how should we describe it?

CLEINIAS:  You mean to ask whether we should call such a self-moving power
life?

ATHENIAN:  I do.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly we should.

ATHENIAN:  And when we see soul in anything, must we not do the same--must
we not admit that this is life?

CLEINIAS:  We must.

ATHENIAN:  And now, I beseech you, reflect;--you would admit that we have a
threefold knowledge of things?

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that we know the essence, and that we know the definition
of the essence, and the name,--these are the three; and there are two
questions which may be raised about anything.

CLEINIAS:  How two?

ATHENIAN:  Sometimes a person may give the name and ask the definition; or
he may give the definition and ask the name.  I may illustrate what I mean
in this way.

CLEINIAS:  How?

ATHENIAN:  Number like some other things is capable of being divided into
equal parts; when thus divided, number is named 'even,' and the definition
of the name 'even' is 'number divisible into two equal parts'?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  I mean, that when we are asked about the definition and give the
name, or when we are asked about the name and give the definition--in
either case, whether we give name or definition, we speak of the same
thing, calling 'even' the number which is divided into two equal parts.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  And what is the definition of that which is named 'soul'?  Can
we conceive of any other than that which has been already given--the motion
which can move itself?

CLEINIAS:  You mean to say that the essence which is defined as the self-
moved is the same with that which has the name soul?

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and if this is true, do we still maintain that there is
anything wanting in the proof that the soul is the first origin and moving
power of all that is, or has become, or will be, and their contraries, when
she has been clearly shown to be the source of change and motion in all
things?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not; the soul as being the source of motion, has been
most satisfactorily shown to be the oldest of all things.

ATHENIAN:  And is not that motion which is produced in another, by reason
of another, but never has any self-moving power at all, being in truth the
change of an inanimate body, to be reckoned second, or by any lower number
which you may prefer?

CLEINIAS:  Exactly.

ATHENIAN:  Then we are right, and speak the most perfect and absolute
truth, when we say that the soul is prior to the body, and that the body is
second and comes afterwards, and is born to obey the soul, which is the
ruler?

CLEINIAS:  Nothing can be more true.

ATHENIAN:  Do you remember our old admission, that if the soul was prior to
the body the things of the soul were also prior to those of the body?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then characters and manners, and wishes and reasonings, and true
opinions, and reflections, and recollections are prior to length and
breadth and depth and strength of bodies, if the soul is prior to the body.

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  In the next place, must we not of necessity admit that the soul
is the cause of good and evil, base and honourable, just and unjust, and of
all other opposites, if we suppose her to be the cause of all things?

CLEINIAS:  We must.

ATHENIAN:  And as the soul orders and inhabits all things that move,
however moving, must we not say that she orders also the heavens?

CLEINIAS:  Of course.

ATHENIAN:  One soul or more?  More than one--I will answer for you; at any
rate, we must not suppose that there are less than two--one the author of
good, and the other of evil.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, very true; the soul then directs all things in heaven, and
earth, and sea by her movements, and these are described by the terms--
will, consideration, attention, deliberation, opinion true and false, joy
and sorrow, confidence, fear, hatred, love, and other primary motions akin
to these; which again receive the secondary motions of corporeal
substances, and guide all things to growth and decay, to composition and
decomposition, and to the qualities which accompany them, such as heat and
cold, heaviness and lightness, hardness and softness, blackness and
whiteness, bitterness and sweetness, and all those other qualities which
the soul uses, herself a goddess, when truly receiving the divine mind she
disciplines all things rightly to their happiness; but when she is the
companion of folly, she does the very contrary of all this.  Shall we
assume so much, or do we still entertain doubts?

CLEINIAS:  There is no room at all for doubt.

ATHENIAN:  Shall we say then that it is the soul which controls heaven and
earth, and the whole world?--that it is a principle of wisdom and virtue,
or a principle which has neither wisdom nor virtue?  Suppose that we make
answer as follows:--

CLEINIAS:  How would you answer?

ATHENIAN:  If, my friend, we say that the whole path and movement of
heaven, and of all that is therein, is by nature akin to the movement and
revolution and calculation of mind, and proceeds by kindred laws, then, as
is plain, we must say that the best soul takes care of the world and guides
it along the good path.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  But if the world moves wildly and irregularly, then the evil
soul guides it.

CLEINIAS:  True again.

ATHENIAN:  Of what nature is the movement of mind?--To this question it is
not easy to give an intelligent answer; and therefore I ought to assist you
in framing one.

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Then let us not answer as if we would look straight at the sun,
making ourselves darkness at midday (compare Republic),--I mean as if we
were under the impression that we could see with mortal eyes, or know
adequately the nature of mind;--it will be safer to look at the image only.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Let us select of the ten motions the one which mind chiefly
resembles; this I will bring to your recollection, and will then make the
answer on behalf of us all.

CLEINIAS:  That will be excellent.

ATHENIAN:  You will surely remember our saying that all things were either
at rest or in motion?

CLEINIAS:  I do.

ATHENIAN:  And that of things in motion some were moving in one place, and
others in more than one?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  Of these two kinds of motion, that which moves in one place must
move about a centre like globes made in a lathe, and is most entirely akin
and similar to the circular movement of mind.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  In saying that both mind and the motion which is in one place
move in the same and like manner, in and about the same, and in relation to
the same, and according to one proportion and order, and are like the
motion of a globe, we invented a fair image, which does no discredit to our
ingenuity.

CLEINIAS:  It does us great credit.

ATHENIAN:  And the motion of the other sort which is not after the same
manner, nor in the same, nor about the same, nor in relation to the same,
nor in one place, nor in order, nor according to any rule or proportion,
may be said to be akin to senselessness and folly?

CLEINIAS:  That is most true.

ATHENIAN:  Then, after what has been said, there is no difficulty in
distinctly stating, that since soul carries all things round, either the
best soul or the contrary must of necessity carry round and order and
arrange the revolution of the heaven.

CLEINIAS:  And judging from what has been said, Stranger, there would be
impiety in asserting that any but the most perfect soul or souls carries
round the heavens.

ATHENIAN:  You have understood my meaning right well, Cleinias, and now let
me ask you another question.

CLEINIAS:  What are you going to ask?

ATHENIAN:  If the soul carries round the sun and moon, and the other stars,
does she not carry round each individual of them?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Then of one of them let us speak, and the same argument will
apply to all.

CLEINIAS:  Which will you take?

ATHENIAN:  Every one sees the body of the sun, but no one sees his soul,
nor the soul of any other body living or dead; and yet there is great
reason to believe that this nature, unperceived by any of our senses, is
circumfused around them all, but is perceived by mind; and therefore by
mind and reflection only let us apprehend the following point.

CLEINIAS:  What is that?

ATHENIAN:  If the soul carries round the sun, we shall not be far wrong in
supposing one of three alternatives.

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  Either the soul which moves the sun this way and that, resides
within the circular and visible body, like the soul which carries us about
every way; or the soul provides herself with an external body of fire or
air, as some affirm, and violently propels body by body; or thirdly, she is
without such a body, but guides the sun by some extraordinary and wonderful
power.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, certainly; the soul can only order all things in one of
these three ways.

ATHENIAN:  And this soul of the sun, which is therefore better than the
sun, whether taking the sun about in a chariot to give light to men, or
acting from without, or in whatever way, ought by every man to be deemed a
God.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, by every man who has the least particle of sense.

ATHENIAN:  And of the stars too, and of the moon, and of the years and
months and seasons, must we not say in like manner, that since a soul or
souls having every sort of excellence are the causes of all of them, those
souls are Gods, whether they are living beings and reside in bodies, and in
this way order the whole heaven, or whatever be the place and mode of their
existence;--and will any one who admits all this venture to deny that all
things are full of Gods?

CLEINIAS:  No one, Stranger, would be such a madman.

ATHENIAN:  And now, Megillus and Cleinias, let us offer terms to him who
has hitherto denied the existence of the Gods, and leave him.

CLEINIAS:  What terms?

ATHENIAN:  Either he shall teach us that we were wrong in saying that the
soul is the original of all things, and arguing accordingly; or, if he be
not able to say anything better, then he must yield to us and live for the
remainder of his life in the belief that there are Gods.--Let us see, then,
whether we have said enough or not enough to those who deny that there are
Gods.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly,--quite enough, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Then to them we will say no more.  And now we are to address him
who, believing that there are Gods, believes also that they take no heed of
human affairs:  To him we say,--O thou best of men, in believing that there
are Gods you are led by some affinity to them, which attracts you towards
your kindred and makes you honour and believe in them.  But the fortunes of
evil and unrighteous men in private as well as public life, which, though
not really happy, are wrongly counted happy in the judgment of men, and are
celebrated both by poets and prose writers (compare Republic)--these draw
you aside from your natural piety.  Perhaps you have seen impious men
growing old and leaving their children's children in high offices, and
their prosperity shakes your faith--you have known or heard or been
yourself an eyewitness of many monstrous impieties, and have beheld men by
such criminal means from small beginnings attaining to sovereignty and the
pinnacle of greatness; and considering all these things you do not like to
accuse the Gods of them, because they are your relatives; and so from some
want of reasoning power, and also from an unwillingness to find fault with
them, you have come to believe that they exist indeed, but have no thought
or care of human things.  Now, that your present evil opinion may not grow
to still greater impiety, and that we may if possible use arguments which
may conjure away the evil before it arrives, we will add another argument
to that originally addressed to him who utterly denied the existence of the
Gods.  And do you, Megillus and Cleinias, answer for the young man as you
did before; and if any impediment comes in our way, I will take the word
out of your mouths, and carry you over the river as I did just now.

CLEINIAS:  Very good; do as you say, and we will help you as well as we
can.

ATHENIAN:  There will probably be no difficulty in proving to him that the
Gods care about the small as well as about the great.  For he was present
and heard what was said, that they are perfectly good, and that the care of
all things is most entirely natural to them.

CLEINIAS:  No doubt he heard that.

ATHENIAN:  Let us consider together in the next place what we mean by this
virtue which we ascribe to them.  Surely we should say that to be temperate
and to possess mind belongs to virtue, and the contrary to vice?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Yes; and courage is a part of virtue, and cowardice of vice?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And the one is honourable, and the other dishonourable?

CLEINIAS:  To be sure.

ATHENIAN:  And the one, like other meaner things, is a human quality, but
the Gods have no part in anything of the sort?

CLEINIAS:  That again is what everybody will admit.

ATHENIAN:  But do we imagine carelessness and idleness and luxury to be
virtues?  What do you think?

CLEINIAS:  Decidedly not.

ATHENIAN:  They rank under the opposite class?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And their opposites, therefore, would fall under the opposite
class?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  But are we to suppose that one who possesses all these good
qualities will be luxurious and heedless and idle, like those whom the poet
compares to stingless drones?  (Hesiod, Works and Days.)

CLEINIAS:  And the comparison is a most just one.

ATHENIAN:  Surely God must not be supposed to have a nature which He
Himself hates?--he who dares to say this sort of thing must not be
tolerated for a moment.

CLEINIAS:  Of course not.  How could He have?

ATHENIAN:  Should we not on any principle be entirely mistaken in praising
any one who has some special business entrusted to him, if he have a mind
which takes care of great matters and no care of small ones?  Reflect; he
who acts in this way, whether he be God or man, must act from one of two
principles.

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  Either he must think that the neglect of the small matters is of
no consequence to the whole, or if he knows that they are of consequence,
and he neglects them, his neglect must be attributed to carelessness and
indolence.  Is there any other way in which his neglect can be explained? 
For surely, when it is impossible for him to take care of all, he is not
negligent if he fails to attend to these things great or small, which a God
or some inferior being might be wanting in strength or capacity to manage?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not.

ATHENIAN:  Now, then, let us examine the offenders, who both alike confess
that there are Gods, but with a difference,--the one saying that they may
be appeased, and the other that they have no care of small matters:  there
are three of us and two of them, and we will say to them,--In the first
place, you both acknowledge that the Gods hear and see and know all things,
and that nothing can escape them which is matter of sense and knowledge:--
do you admit this?

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  And do you admit also that they have all power which mortals and
immortals can have?

CLEINIAS:  They will, of course, admit this also.

ATHENIAN:  And surely we three and they two--five in all--have acknowledged
that they are good and perfect?

CLEINIAS:  Assuredly.

ATHENIAN:  But, if they are such as we conceive them to be, can we possibly
suppose that they ever act in the spirit of carelessness and indolence? 
For in us inactivity is the child of cowardice, and carelessness of
inactivity and indolence.

CLEINIAS:  Most true.

ATHENIAN:  Then not from inactivity and carelessness is any God ever
negligent; for there is no cowardice in them.

CLEINIAS:  That is very true.

ATHENIAN:  Then the alternative which remains is, that if the Gods neglect
the lighter and lesser concerns of the universe, they neglect them because
they know that they ought not to care about such matters--what other
alternative is there but the opposite of their knowing?

CLEINIAS:  There is none.

ATHENIAN:  And, O most excellent and best of men, do I understand you to
mean that they are careless because they are ignorant, and do not know that
they ought to take care, or that they know, and yet like the meanest sort
of men, knowing the better, choose the worse because they are overcome by
pleasures and pains?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  Do not all human things partake of the nature of soul?  And is
not man the most religious of all animals?  (Compare Timaeus.)

CLEINIAS:  That is not to be denied.

ATHENIAN:  And we acknowledge that all mortal creatures are the property of
the Gods, to whom also the whole of heaven belongs?  (Compare Phaedo.)

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And, therefore, whether a person says that these things are to
the Gods great or small--in either case it would not be natural for the
Gods who own us, and who are the most careful and the best of owners, to
neglect us.--There is also a further consideration.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  Sensation and power are in an inverse ratio to each other in
respect to their ease and difficulty.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean that there is greater difficulty in seeing and hearing
the small than the great, but more facility in moving and controlling and
taking care of small and unimportant things than of their opposites.

CLEINIAS:  Far more.

ATHENIAN:  Suppose the case of a physician who is willing and able to cure
some living thing as a whole,--how will the whole fare at his hands if he
takes care only of the greater and neglects the parts which are lesser?

CLEINIAS:  Decidedly not well.

ATHENIAN:  No better would be the result with pilots or generals, or
householders or statesmen, or any other such class, if they neglected the
small and regarded only the great;--as the builders say, the larger stones
do not lie well without the lesser.

CLEINIAS:  Of course not.

ATHENIAN:  Let us not, then, deem God inferior to human workmen, who, in
proportion to their skill, finish and perfect their works, small as well as
great, by one and the same art; or that God, the wisest of beings, who is
both willing and able to take care, is like a lazy good-for-nothing, or a
coward, who turns his back upon labour and gives no thought to smaller and
easier matters, but to the greater only.

CLEINIAS:  Never, Stranger, let us admit a supposition about the Gods which
is both impious and false.

ATHENIAN:  I think that we have now argued enough with him who delights to
accuse the Gods of neglect.

CLEINIAS:  Yes.

ATHENIAN:  He has been forced to acknowledge that he is in error, but he
still seems to me to need some words of consolation.

CLEINIAS:  What consolation will you offer him?

ATHENIAN:  Let us say to the youth:--The ruler of the universe has ordered
all things with a view to the excellence and preservation of the whole, and
each part, as far as may be, has an action and passion appropriate to it. 
Over these, down to the least fraction of them, ministers have been
appointed to preside, who have wrought out their perfection with
infinitesimal exactness.  And one of these portions of the universe is
thine own, unhappy man, which, however little, contributes to the whole;
and you do not seem to be aware that this and every other creation is for
the sake of the whole, and in order that the life of the whole may be
blessed; and that you are created for the sake of the whole, and not the
whole for the sake of you.  For every physician and every skilled artist
does all things for the sake of the whole, directing his effort towards the
common good, executing the part for the sake of the whole, and not the
whole for the sake of the part.  And you are annoyed because you are
ignorant how what is best for you happens to you and to the universe, as
far as the laws of the common creation admit.  Now, as the soul combining
first with one body and then with another undergoes all sorts of changes,
either of herself, or through the influence of another soul, all that
remains to the player of the game is that he should shift the pieces;
sending the better nature to the better place, and the worse to the worse,
and so assigning to them their proper portion.

CLEINIAS:  In what way do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  In a way which may be supposed to make the care of all things
easy to the Gods.  If any one were to form or fashion all things without
any regard to the whole,--if, for example, he formed a living element of
water out of fire, instead of forming many things out of one or one out of
many in regular order attaining to a first or second or third birth
(compare Timaeus), the transmutation would have been infinite; but now the
ruler of the world has a wonderfully easy task.

CLEINIAS:  How so?

ATHENIAN:  I will explain:--When the king saw that our actions had life,
and that there was much virtue in them and much vice, and that the soul and
body, although not, like the Gods of popular opinion, eternal, yet having
once come into existence, were indestructible (for if either of them had
been destroyed, there would have been no generation of living beings); and
when he observed that the good of the soul was ever by nature designed to
profit men, and the evil to harm them--he, seeing all this, contrived so to
place each of the parts that their position might in the easiest and best
manner procure the victory of good and the defeat of evil in the whole. 
And he contrived a general plan by which a thing of a certain nature found
a certain seat and room.  But the formation of qualities he left to the
wills of individuals.  For every one of us is made pretty much what he is
by the bent of his desires and the nature of his soul.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, that is probably true.

ATHENIAN:  Then all things which have a soul change, and possess in
themselves a principle of change, and in changing move according to law and
to the order of destiny:  natures which have undergone a lesser change move
less and on the earth's surface, but those which have suffered more change
and have become more criminal sink into the abyss, that is to say, into
Hades and other places in the world below, of which the very names terrify
men, and which they picture to themselves as in a dream, both while alive
and when released from the body.  And whenever the soul receives more of
good or evil from her own energy and the strong influence of others--when
she has communion with divine virtue and becomes divine, she is carried
into another and better place, which is perfect in holiness; but when she
has communion with evil, then she also changes the place of her life.

'This is the justice of the Gods who inhabit Olympus.'  (Homer Odyss.)

O youth or young man, who fancy that you are neglected by the Gods, know
that if you become worse you shall go to the worse souls, or if better to
the better, and in every succession of life and death you will do and
suffer what like may fitly suffer at the hands of like.  This is the
justice of heaven, which neither you nor any other unfortunate will ever
glory in escaping, and which the ordaining powers have specially ordained;
take good heed thereof, for it will be sure to take heed of you.  If you
say:--I am small and will creep into the depths of the earth, or I am high
and will fly up to heaven, you are not so small or so high but that you
shall pay the fitting penalty, either here or in the world below or in some
still more savage place whither you shall be conveyed.  This is also the
explanation of the fate of those whom you saw, who had done unholy and evil
deeds, and from small beginnings had grown great, and you fancied that from
being miserable they had become happy; and in their actions, as in a
mirror, you seemed to see the universal neglect of the Gods, not knowing
how they make all things work together and contribute to the great whole. 
And thinkest thou, bold man, that thou needest not to know this?--he who
knows it not can never form any true idea of the happiness or unhappiness
of life or hold any rational discourse respecting either.  If Cleinias and
this our reverend company succeed in proving to you that you know not what
you say of the Gods, then will God help you; but should you desire to hear
more, listen to what we say to the third opponent, if you have any
understanding whatsoever.  For I think that we have sufficiently proved the
existence of the Gods, and that they care for men:--The other notion that
they are appeased by the wicked, and take gifts, is what we must not
concede to any one, and what every man should disprove to the utmost of his
power.

CLEINIAS:  Very good; let us do as you say.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, by the Gods themselves I conjure you to tell me,--if
they are to be propitiated, how are they to be propitiated?  Who are they,
and what is their nature?  Must they not be at least rulers who have to
order unceasingly the whole heaven?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And to what earthly rulers can they be compared, or who to them? 
How in the less can we find an image of the greater?  Are they charioteers
of contending pairs of steeds, or pilots of vessels?  Perhaps they might be
compared to the generals of armies, or they might be likened to physicians
providing against the diseases which make war upon the body, or to
husbandmen observing anxiously the effects of the seasons on the growth of
plants; or perhaps to shepherds of flocks.  For as we acknowledge the world
to be full of many goods and also of evils, and of more evils than goods,
there is, as we affirm, an immortal conflict going on among us, which
requires marvellous watchfulness; and in that conflict the Gods and
demigods are our allies, and we are their property.  Injustice and
insolence and folly are the destruction of us, and justice and temperance
and wisdom are our salvation; and the place of these latter is in the life
of the Gods, although some vestige of them may occasionally be discerned
among mankind.  But upon this earth we know that there dwell souls
possessing an unjust spirit, who may be compared to brute animals, which
fawn upon their keepers, whether dogs or shepherds, or the best and most
perfect masters; for they in like manner, as the voices of the wicked
declare, prevail by flattery and prayers and incantations, and are allowed
to make their gains with impunity.  And this sin, which is termed
dishonesty, is an evil of the same kind as what is termed disease in living
bodies or pestilence in years or seasons of the year, and in cities and
governments has another name, which is injustice.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  What else can he say who declares that the Gods are always
lenient to the doers of unjust acts, if they divide the spoil with them? 
As if wolves were to toss a portion of their prey to the dogs, and they,
mollified by the gift, suffered them to tear the flocks (compare Republic). 
Must not he who maintains that the Gods can be propitiated argue thus?

CLEINIAS:  Precisely so.

ATHENIAN:  And to which of the above-mentioned classes of guardians would
any man compare the Gods without absurdity?  Will he say that they are like
pilots, who are themselves turned away from their duty by 'libations of
wine and the savour of fat,' and at last overturn both ship and sailors?

CLEINIAS:  Assuredly not.

ATHENIAN:  And surely they are not like charioteers who are bribed to give
up the victory to other chariots?

CLEINIAS:  That would be a fearful image of the Gods.

ATHENIAN:  Nor are they like generals, or physicians, or husbandmen, or
shepherds; and no one would compare them to dogs who have been silenced by
wolves.

CLEINIAS:  A thing not to be spoken of.

ATHENIAN:  And are not all the Gods the chiefest of all guardians, and do
they not guard our highest interests?

CLEINIAS:  Yes; the chiefest.

ATHENIAN:  And shall we say that those who guard our noblest interests, and
are the best of guardians, are inferior in virtue to dogs, and to men even
of moderate excellence, who would never betray justice for the sake of
gifts which unjust men impiously offer them?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not:  nor is such a notion to be endured, and he who
holds this opinion may be fairly singled out and characterized as of all
impious men the wickedest and most impious.

ATHENIAN:  Then are the three assertions--that the Gods exist, and that
they take care of men, and that they can never be persuaded to do
injustice, now sufficiently demonstrated?  May we say that they are?

CLEINIAS:  You have our entire assent to your words.

ATHENIAN:  I have spoken with vehemence because I am zealous against evil
men; and I will tell dear Cleinias, why I am so.  I would not have the
wicked think that, having the superiority in argument, they may do as they
please and act according to their various imaginations about the Gods; and
this zeal has led me to speak too vehemently; but if we have at all
succeeded in persuading the men to hate themselves and love their
opposites, the prelude of our laws about impiety will not have been spoken
in vain.

CLEINIAS:  So let us hope; and even if we have failed, the style of our
argument will not discredit the lawgiver.

ATHENIAN:  After the prelude shall follow a discourse, which will be the
interpreter of the law; this shall proclaim to all impious persons that
they must depart from their ways and go over to the pious.  And to those
who disobey, let the law about impiety be as follows:--If a man is guilty
of any impiety in word or deed, any one who happens to be present shall
give information to the magistrates, in aid of the law; and let the
magistrates who first receive the information bring him before the
appointed court according to the law; and if a magistrate, after receiving
information, refuses to act, he shall be tried for impiety at the instance
of any one who is willing to vindicate the laws; and if any one be cast,
the court shall estimate the punishment of each act of impiety; and let all
such criminals be imprisoned.  There shall be three prisons in the state: 
the first of them is to be the common prison in the neighbourhood of the
agora for the safe-keeping of the generality of offenders; another is to be
in the neighbourhood of the nocturnal council, and is to be called the
'House of Reformation'; another, to be situated in some wild and desolate
region in the centre of the country, shall be called by some name
expressive of retribution.  Now, men fall into impiety from three causes,
which have been already mentioned, and from each of these causes arise two
sorts of impiety, in all six, which are worth distinguishing, and should
not all have the same punishment.  For he who does not believe in the Gods,
and yet has a righteous nature, hates the wicked and dislikes and refuses
to do injustice, and avoids unrighteous men, and loves the righteous.  But
they who besides believing that the world is devoid of Gods are
intemperate, and have at the same time good memories and quick wits, are
worse; although both of them are unbelievers, much less injury is done by
the one than by the other.  The one may talk loosely about the Gods and
about sacrifices and oaths, and perhaps by laughing at other men he may
make them like himself, if he be not punished.  But the other who holds the
same opinions and is called a clever man, is full of stratagem and deceit--
men of this class deal in prophecy and jugglery of all kinds, and out of
their ranks sometimes come tyrants and demagogues and generals and
hierophants of private mysteries and the Sophists, as they are termed, with
their ingenious devices.  There are many kinds of unbelievers, but two only
for whom legislation is required; one the hypocritical sort, whose crime is
deserving of death many times over, while the other needs only bonds and
admonition.  In like manner also the notion that the Gods take no thought
of men produces two other sorts of crimes, and the notion that they may be
propitiated produces two more.  Assuming these divisions, let those who
have been made what they are only from want of understanding, and not from
malice or an evil nature, be placed by the judge in the House of
Reformation, and ordered to suffer imprisonment during a period of not less
than five years.  And in the meantime let them have no intercourse with the
other citizens, except with members of the nocturnal council, and with them
let them converse with a view to the improvement of their soul's health. 
And when the time of their imprisonment has expired, if any of them be of
sound mind let him be restored to sane company, but if not, and if he be
condemned a second time, let him be punished with death.  As to that class
of monstrous natures who not only believe that there are no Gods, or that
they are negligent, or to be propitiated, but in contempt of mankind
conjure the souls of the living (compare Republic) and say that they can
conjure the dead and promise to charm the Gods with sacrifices and prayers,
and will utterly overthrow individuals and whole houses and states for the
sake of money--let him who is guilty of any of these things be condemned by
the court to be bound according to law in the prison which is in the centre
of the land, and let no freeman ever approach him, but let him receive the
rations of food appointed by the guardians of the law from the hands of the
public slaves; and when he is dead let him be cast beyond the borders
unburied, and if any freeman assist in burying him, let him pay the penalty
of impiety to any one who is willing to bring a suit against him.  But if
he leaves behind him children who are fit to be citizens, let the guardians
of orphans take care of them, just as they would of any other orphans, from
the day on which their father is convicted.

In all these cases there should be one law, which will make men in general
less liable to transgress in word or deed, and less foolish, because they
will not be allowed to practise religious rites contrary to law.  And let
this be the simple form of the law:--No man shall have sacred rites in a
private house.  When he would sacrifice, let him go to the temples and hand
over his offerings to the priests and priestesses, who see to the sanctity
of such things, and let him pray himself, and let any one who pleases join
with him in prayer.  The reason of this is as follows:--Gods and temples
are not easily instituted, and to establish them rightly is the work of a
mighty intellect.  And women especially, and men too, when they are sick or
in danger, or in any sort of difficulty, or again on their receiving any
good fortune, have a way of consecrating the occasion, vowing sacrifices,
and promising shrines to Gods, demigods, and sons of Gods; and when they
are awakened by terrible apparitions and dreams or remember visions, they
find in altars and temples the remedies of them, and will fill every house
and village with them, placing them in the open air, or wherever they may
have had such visions; and with a view to all these cases we should obey
the law.  The law has also regard to the impious, and would not have them
fancy that by the secret performance of these actions--by raising temples
and by building altars in private houses, they can propitiate the God
secretly with sacrifices and prayers, while they are really multiplying
their crimes infinitely, bringing guilt from heaven upon themselves, and
also upon those who permit them, and who are better men than they are; and
the consequence is that the whole state reaps the fruit of their impiety,
which, in a certain sense, is deserved.  Assuredly God will not blame the
legislator, who will enact the following law:--No one shall possess shrines
of the Gods in private houses, and he who is found to possess them, and
perform any sacred rites not publicly authorized,--supposing the offender
to be some man or woman who is not guilty of any other great and impious
crime,--shall be informed against by him who is acquainted with the fact,
which shall be announced by him to the guardians of the law; and let them
issue orders that he or she shall carry away their private rites to the
public temples, and if they do not persuade them, let them inflict a
penalty on them until they comply.  And if a person be proven guilty of
impiety, not merely from childish levity, but such as grown-up men may be
guilty of, whether he have sacrificed publicly or privately to any Gods,
let him be punished with death, for his sacrifice is impure.  Whether the
deed has been done in earnest, or only from childish levity, let the
guardians of the law determine, before they bring the matter into court and
prosecute the offender for impiety.


BOOK XI.

In the next place, dealings between man and man require to be suitably
regulated.  The principle of them is very simple:--Thou shalt not, if thou
canst help, touch that which is mine, or remove the least thing which
belongs to me without my consent; and may I be of a sound mind, and do to
others as I would that they should do to me.  First, let us speak of
treasure-trove:--May I never pray the Gods to find the hidden treasure,
which another has laid up for himself and his family, he not being one of
my ancestors, nor lift, if I should find, such a treasure.  And may I never
have any dealings with those who are called diviners, and who in any way or
manner counsel me to take up the deposit entrusted to the earth, for I
should not gain so much in the increase of my possessions, if I take up the
prize, as I should grow in justice and virtue of soul, if I abstain; and
this will be a better possession to me than the other in a better part of
myself; for the possession of justice in the soul is preferable to the
possession of wealth.  And of many things it is well said,--'Move not the
immovables,' and this may be regarded as one of them.  And we shall do well
to believe the common tradition which says, that such deeds prevent a man
from having a family.  Now as to him who is careless about having children
and regardless of the legislator, taking up that which neither he
deposited, nor any ancestor of his, without the consent of the depositor,
violating the simplest and noblest of laws which was the enactment of no
mean man:--'Take not up that which was not laid down by thee,'--of him, I
say, who despises these two legislators, and takes up, not some small
matter which he has not deposited, but perhaps a great heap of treasure,
what he ought to suffer at the hands of the Gods, God only knows; but I
would have the first person who sees him go and tell the wardens of the
city, if the occurrence has taken place in the city, or if the occurrence
has taken place in the agora he shall tell the wardens of the agora, or if
in the country he shall tell the wardens of the country and their
commanders.  When information has been received the city shall send to
Delphi, and, whatever the God answers about the money and the remover of
the money, that the city shall do in obedience to the oracle; the informer,
if he be a freeman, shall have the honour of doing rightly, and he who
informs not, the dishonour of doing wrongly; and if he be a slave who gives
information, let him be freed, as he ought to be, by the state, which shall
give his master the price of him; but if he do not inform he shall be
punished with death.  Next in order shall follow a similar law, which shall
apply equally to matters great and small:--If a man happens to leave behind
him some part of his property, whether intentionally or unintentionally,
let him who may come upon the left property suffer it to remain, reflecting
that such things are under the protection of the Goddess of ways, and are
dedicated to her by the law.  But if any one defies the law, and takes the
property home with him, let him, if the thing is of little worth, and the
man who takes it a slave, be beaten with many stripes by him, being a
person of not less than thirty years of age.  Or if he be a freeman, in
addition to being thought a mean person and a despiser of the laws, let him
pay ten times the value of the treasure which he has moved to the leaver. 
And if some one accuses another of having anything which belongs to him,
whether little or much, and the other admits that he has this thing, but
denies that the property in dispute belongs to the other, if the property
be registered with the magistrates according to law, the claimant shall
summon the possessor, who shall bring it before the magistrates; and when
it is brought into court, if it be registered in the public registers, to
which of the litigants it belonged, let him take it and go his way.  Or if
the property be registered as belonging to some one who is not present,
whoever will offer sufficient surety on behalf of the absent person that he
will give it up to him, shall take it away as the representative of the
other.  But if the property which is deposited be not registered with the
magistrates, let it remain until the time of trial with three of the eldest
of the magistrates; and if it be an animal which is deposited, then he who
loses the suit shall pay the magistrates for its keep, and they shall
determine the cause within three days.

Any one who is of sound mind may arrest his own slave, and do with him
whatever he will of such things as are lawful; and he may arrest the
runaway slave of any of his friends or kindred with a view to his safe-
keeping.  And if any one takes away him who is being carried off as a
slave, intending to liberate him, he who is carrying him off shall let him
go; but he who takes him away shall give three sufficient sureties; and if
he give them, and not without giving them, he may take him away, but if he
take him away after any other manner he shall be deemed guilty of violence,
and being convicted shall pay as a penalty double the amount of the damages
claimed to him who has been deprived of the slave.  Any man may also carry
off a freedman, if he do not pay respect or sufficient respect to him who
freed him.  Now the respect shall be, that the freedman go three times in
the month to the hearth of the person who freed him, and offer to do
whatever he ought, so far as he can; and he shall agree to make such a
marriage as his former master approves.  He shall not be permitted to have
more property than he who gave him liberty, and what more he has shall
belong to his master.  The freedman shall not remain in the state more than
twenty years, but like other foreigners shall go away, taking his entire
property with him, unless he has the consent of the magistrates and of his
former master to remain.  If a freedman or any other stranger has a
property greater than the census of the third class, at the expiration of
thirty days from the day on which this comes to pass, he shall take that
which is his and go his way, and in this case he shall not be allowed to
remain any longer by the magistrates.  And if any one disobeys this
regulation, and is brought into court and convicted, he shall be punished
with death, his property shall be confiscated.  Suits about these matters
shall take place before the tribes, unless the plaintiff and defendant have
got rid of the accusation either before their neighbours or before judges
chosen by them.  If a man lay claim to any animal or anything else which he
declares to be his, let the possessor refer to the seller or to some honest
and trustworthy person, who has given, or in some legitimate way made over
the property to him; if he be a citizen or a metic, sojourning in the city,
within thirty days, or, if the property have been delivered to him by a
stranger, within five months, of which the middle month shall include the
summer solstice.  When goods are exchanged by selling and buying, a man
shall deliver them, and receive the price of them, at a fixed place in the
agora, and have done with the matter; but he shall not buy or sell anywhere
else, nor give credit.  And if in any other manner or in any other place
there be an exchange of one thing for another, and the seller give credit
to the man who buys from him, he must do this on the understanding that the
law gives no protection in cases of things sold not in accordance with
these regulations.  Again, as to contributions, any man who likes may go
about collecting contributions as a friend among friends, but if any
difference arises about the collection, he is to act on the understanding
that the law gives no protection in such cases.  He who sells anything
above the value of fifty drachmas shall be required to remain in the city
for ten days, and the purchaser shall be informed of the house of the
seller, with a view to the sort of charges which are apt to arise in such
cases, and the restitutions which the law allows.  And let legal
restitution be on this wise:--If a man sells a slave who is in a
consumption, or who has the disease of the stone, or of strangury, or
epilepsy, or some other tedious and incurable disorder of body or mind,
which is not discernible to the ordinary man, if the purchaser be a
physician or trainer, he shall have no right of restitution; nor shall
there be any right of restitution if the seller has told the truth
beforehand to the buyer.  But if a skilled person sells to another who is
not skilled, let the buyer appeal for restitution within six months, except
in the case of epilepsy, and then the appeal may be made within a year. 
The cause shall be determined by such physicians as the parties may agree
to choose; and the defendant, if he lose the suit, shall pay double the
price at which he sold.  If a private person sell to another private
person, he shall have the right of restitution, and the decision shall be
given as before, but the defendant, if he be cast, shall only pay back the
price of the slave.  If a person sells a homicide to another, and they both
know of the fact, let there be no restitution in such a case, but if he do
not know of the fact, there shall be a right of restitution, whenever the
buyer makes the discovery; and the decision shall rest with the five
youngest guardians of the law, and if the decision be that the seller was
cognisant of the fact, he shall purify the house of the purchaser,
according to the law of the interpreters, and shall pay back three times
the purchase-money.

If man exchanges either money for money, or anything whatever for anything
else, either with or without life, let him give and receive them genuine
and unadulterated, in accordance with the law.  And let us have a prelude
about all this sort of roguery, like the preludes of our other laws.  Every
man should regard adulteration as of one and the same class with falsehood
and deceit, concerning which the many are too fond of saying that at proper
times and places the practice may often be right.  But they leave the
occasion, and the when, and the where, undefined and unsettled, and from
this want of definiteness in their language they do a great deal of harm to
themselves and to others.  Now a legislator ought not to leave the matter
undetermined; he ought to prescribe some limit, either greater or less. 
Let this be the rule prescribed:--No one shall call the Gods to witness,
when he says or does anything false or deceitful or dishonest, unless he
would be the most hateful of mankind to them.  And he is most hateful to
them who takes a false oath, and pays no heed to the Gods; and in the next
degree, he who tells a falsehood in the presence of his superiors.  Now
better men are the superiors of worse men, and in general elders are the
superiors of the young; wherefore also parents are the superiors of their
offspring, and men of women and children, and rulers of their subjects; for
all men ought to reverence any one who is in any position of authority, and
especially those who are in state offices.  And this is the reason why I
have spoken of these matters.  For every one who is guilty of adulteration
in the agora tells a falsehood, and deceives, and when he invokes the Gods,
according to the customs and cautions of the wardens of the agora, he does
but swear without any respect for God or man.  Certainly, it is an
excellent rule not lightly to defile the names of the Gods, after the
fashion of men in general, who care little about piety and purity in their
religious actions.  But if a man will not conform to this rule, let the law
be as follows:--He who sells anything in the agora shall not ask two prices
for that which he sells, but he shall ask one price, and if he do not
obtain this, he shall take away his goods; and on that day he shall not
value them either at more or less; and there shall be no praising of any
goods, or oath taken about them.  If a person disobeys this command, any
citizen who is present, not being less than thirty years of age, may with
impunity chastise and beat the swearer, but if instead of obeying the laws
he takes no heed, he shall be liable to the charge of having betrayed them. 
If a man sells any adulterated goods and will not obey these regulations,
he who knows and can prove the fact, and does prove it in the presence of
the magistrates, if he be a slave or a metic, shall have the adulterated
goods; but if he be a citizen, and do not pursue the charge, he shall be
called a rogue, and deemed to have robbed the Gods of the agora; or if he
proves the charge, he shall dedicate the goods to the Gods of the agora. 
He who is proved to have sold any adulterated goods, in addition to losing
the goods themselves, shall be beaten with stripes,--a stripe for a
drachma, according to the price of the goods; and the herald shall proclaim
in the agora the offence for which he is going to be beaten.  The wardens
of the agora and the guardians of the law shall obtain information from
experienced persons about the rogueries and adulterations of the sellers,
and shall write up what the seller ought and ought not to do in each case;
and let them inscribe their laws on a column in front of the court of the
wardens of the agora, that they may be clear instructors of those who have
business in the agora.  Enough has been said in what has preceded about the
wardens of the city, and if anything seems to be wanting, let them
communicate with the guardians of the law, and write down the omission, and
place on a column in the court of the wardens of the city the primary and
secondary regulations which are laid down for them about their office.

After the practices of adulteration naturally follow the practices of
retail trade.  Concerning these, we will first of all give a word of
counsel and reason, and the law shall come afterwards.  Retail trade in a
city is not by nature intended to do any harm, but quite the contrary; for
is not he a benefactor who reduces the inequalities and
incommensurabilities of goods to equality and common measure?  And this is
what the power of money accomplishes, and the merchant may be said to be
appointed for this purpose.  The hireling and the tavern-keeper, and many
other occupations, some of them more and others less seemly--all alike have
this object;--they seek to satisfy our needs and equalize our possessions
(compare Arist. Pol.).  Let us then endeavour to see what has brought
retail trade into ill-odour, and wherein lies the dishonour and
unseemliness of it, in order that if not entirely, we may yet partially,
cure the evil by legislation.  To effect this is no easy matter, and
requires a great deal of virtue.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Dear Cleinias, the class of men is small--they must have been
rarely gifted by nature, and trained by education,--who, when assailed by
wants and desires, are able to hold out and observe moderation, and when
they might make a great deal of money are sober in their wishes, and prefer
a moderate to a large gain.  But the mass of mankind are the very opposite: 
their desires are unbounded, and when they might gain in moderation they
prefer gains without limit; wherefore all that relates to retail trade, and
merchandise, and the keeping of taverns, is denounced and numbered among
dishonourable things.  For if what I trust may never be and will not be, we
were to compel, if I may venture to say a ridiculous thing, the best men
everywhere to keep taverns for a time, or carry on retail trade, or do
anything of that sort; or if, in consequence of some fate or necessity, the
best women were compelled to follow similar callings, then we should know
how agreeable and pleasant all these things are; and if all such
occupations were managed on incorrupt principles, they would be honoured as
we honour a mother or a nurse.  But now that a man goes to desert places
and builds houses which can only be reached by long journeys, for the sake
of retail trade, and receives strangers who are in need at the welcome
resting-place, and gives them peace and calm when they are tossed by the
storm, or cool shade in the heat; and then instead of behaving to them as
friends, and showing the duties of hospitality to his guests, treats them
as enemies and captives who are at his mercy, and will not release them
until they have paid the most unjust, abominable, and extortionate ransom,
--these are the sort of practices, and foul evils they are, which cast a
reproach upon the succour of adversity.  And the legislator ought always to
be devising a remedy for evils of this nature.  There is an ancient saying,
which is also a true one--'To fight against two opponents is a difficult
thing,' as is seen in diseases and in many other cases.  And in this case
also the war is against two enemies--wealth and poverty; one of whom
corrupts the soul of man with luxury, while the other drives him by pain
into utter shamelessness.  What remedy can a city of sense find against
this disease?  In the first place, they must have as few retail traders as
possible; and in the second place, they must assign the occupation to that
class of men whose corruption will be the least injury to the state; and in
the third place, they must devise some way whereby the followers of these
occupations themselves will not readily fall into habits of unbridled
shamelessness and meanness.

After this preface let our law run as follows, and may fortune favour us:--
No landowner among the Magnetes, whose city the God is restoring and
resettling--no one, that is, of the 5040 families, shall become a retail
trader either voluntarily or involuntarily; neither shall he be a merchant,
or do any service for private persons unless they equally serve him, except
for his father or his mother, and their fathers and mothers; and in general
for his elders who are freemen, and whom he serves as a freeman.  Now it is
difficult to determine accurately the things which are worthy or unworthy
of a freeman, but let those who have obtained the prize of virtue give
judgment about them in accordance with their feelings of right and wrong. 
He who in any way shares in the illiberality of retail trades may be
indicted for dishonouring his race by any one who likes, before those who
have been judged to be the first in virtue; and if he appear to throw dirt
upon his father's house by an unworthy occupation, let him be imprisoned
for a year and abstain from that sort of thing; and if he repeat the
offence, for two years; and every time that he is convicted let the length
of his imprisonment be doubled.  This shall be the second law:--He who
engages in retail trade must be either a metic or a stranger.  And a third
law shall be:--In order that the retail trader who dwells in our city may
be as good or as little bad as possible, the guardians of the law shall
remember that they are not only guardians of those who may be easily
watched and prevented from becoming lawless or bad, because they are well-
born and bred; but still more should they have a watch over those who are
of another sort, and follow pursuits which have a very strong tendency to
make men bad.  And, therefore, in respect of the multifarious occupations
of retail trade, that is to say, in respect of such of them as are allowed
to remain, because they seem to be quite necessary in a state,--about these
the guardians of the law should meet and take counsel with those who have
experience of the several kinds of retail trade, as we before commanded
concerning adulteration (which is a matter akin to this), and when they
meet they shall consider what amount of receipts, after deducting expenses,
will produce a moderate gain to the retail trades, and they shall fix in
writing and strictly maintain what they find to be the right percentage of
profit; this shall be seen to by the wardens of the agora, and by the
wardens of the city, and by the wardens of the country.  And so retail
trade will benefit every one, and do the least possible injury to those in
the state who practise it.

When a man makes an agreement which he does not fulfil, unless the
agreement be of a nature which the law or a vote of the assembly does not
allow, or which he has made under the influence of some unjust compulsion,
or which he is prevented from fulfilling against his will by some
unexpected chance, the other party may go to law with him in the courts of
the tribes, for not having completed his agreement, if the parties are not
able previously to come to terms before arbiters or before their
neighbours.  The class of craftsmen who have furnished human life with the
arts is dedicated to Hephaestus and Athene; and there is a class of
craftsmen who preserve the works of all craftsmen by arts of defence, the
votaries of Ares and Athene, to which divinities they too are rightly
dedicated.  All these continue through life serving the country and the
people; some of them are leaders in battle; others make for hire implements
and works, and they ought not to deceive in such matters, out of respect to
the Gods who are their ancestors.  If any craftsman through indolence omit
to execute his work in a given time, not reverencing the God who gives him
the means of life, but considering, foolish fellow, that he is his own God
and will let him off easily, in the first place, he shall suffer at the
hands of the God, and in the second place, the law shall follow in a
similar spirit.  He shall owe to him who contracted with him the price of
the works which he has failed in performing, and he shall begin again and
execute them gratis in the given time.  When a man undertakes a work, the
law gives him the same advice which was given to the seller, that he should
not attempt to raise the price, but simply ask the value; this the law
enjoins also on the contractor; for the craftsman assuredly knows the value
of his work.  Wherefore, in free states the man of art ought not to attempt
to impose upon private individuals by the help of his art, which is by
nature a true thing; and he who is wronged in a matter of this sort, shall
have a right of action against the party who has wronged him.  And if any
one lets out work to a craftsman, and does not pay him duly according to
the lawful agreement, disregarding Zeus the guardian of the city and
Athene, who are the partners of the state, and overthrows the foundations
of society for the sake of a little gain, in his case let the law and the
Gods maintain the common bonds of the state.  And let him who, having
already received the work in exchange, does not pay the price in the time
agreed, pay double the price; and if a year has elapsed, although interest
is not to be taken on loans, yet for every drachma which he owes to the
contractor let him pay a monthly interest of an obol.  Suits about these
matters are to be decided by the courts of the tribes; and by the way,
since we have mentioned craftsmen at all, we must not forget that other
craft of war, in which generals and tacticians are the craftsmen, who
undertake voluntarily or involuntarily the work of our safety, as other
craftsmen undertake other public works;--if they execute their work well
the law will never tire of praising him who gives them those honours which
are the just rewards of the soldier; but if any one, having already
received the benefit of any noble service in war, does not make the due
return of honour, the law will blame him.  Let this then be the law, having
an ingredient of praise, not compelling but advising the great body of the
citizens to honour the brave men who are the saviours of the whole state,
whether by their courage or by their military skill;--they should honour
them, I say, in the second place; for the first and highest tribute of
respect is to be given to those who are able above other men to honour the
words of good legislators.

The greater part of the dealings between man and man have been now
regulated by us with the exception of those that relate to orphans and the
supervision of orphans by their guardians.  These follow next in order, and
must be regulated in some way.  But to arrive at them we must begin with
the testamentary wishes of the dying and the case of those who may have
happened to die intestate.  When I said, Cleinias, that we must regulate
them, I had in my mind the difficulty and perplexity in which all such
matters are involved.  You cannot leave them unregulated, for individuals
would make regulations at variance with one another, and repugnant to the
laws and habits of the living and to their own previous habits, if a person
were simply allowed to make any will which he pleased, and this were to
take effect in whatever state he may have been at the end of his life; for
most of us lose our senses in a manner, and feel crushed when we think that
we are about to die.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean, Stranger?

ATHENIAN:  O Cleinias, a man when he is about to die is an intractable
creature, and is apt to use language which causes a great deal of anxiety
and trouble to the legislator.

CLEINIAS:  In what way?

ATHENIAN:  He wants to have the entire control of all his property, and
will use angry words.

CLEINIAS:  Such as what?

ATHENIAN:  O ye Gods, he will say, how monstrous that I am not allowed to
give, or not to give, my own to whom I will--less to him who has been bad
to me, and more to him who has been good to me, and whose badness and
goodness have been tested by me in time of sickness or in old age and in
every other sort of fortune!

CLEINIAS:  Well Stranger, and may he not very fairly say so?

ATHENIAN:  In my opinion, Cleinias, the ancient legislators were too good-
natured, and made laws without sufficient observation or consideration of
human things.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean, my friend, that they were afraid of the testator's
reproaches, and so they passed a law to the effect that a man should be
allowed to dispose of his property in all respects as he liked; but you and
I, if I am not mistaken, will have something better to say to our departing
citizens.

CLEINIAS:  What?

ATHENIAN:  O my friends, we will say to them, hard is it for you, who are
creatures of a day, to know what is yours,--hard too, as the Delphic oracle
says, to know yourselves at this hour.  Now I, as the legislator, regard
you and your possessions, not as belonging to yourselves, but as belonging
to your whole family, both past and future, and yet more do I regard both
family and possessions as belonging to the state; wherefore, if some one
steals upon you with flattery, when you are tossed on the sea of disease or
old age, and persuades you to dispose of your property in a way that is not
for the best, I will not, if I can help, allow this; but I will legislate
with a view to the whole, considering what is best both for the state and
for the family, esteeming as I ought the feelings of an individual at a
lower rate; and I hope that you will depart in peace and kindness towards
us, as you are going the way of all mankind; and we will impartially take
care of all your concerns, not neglecting any of them, if we can possibly
help.  Let this be our prelude and consolation to the living and dying,
Cleinias, and let the law be as follows:--He who makes a disposition in a
testament, if he be the father of a family, shall first of all inscribe as
his heir any one of his sons whom he may think fit; and if he gives any of
his children to be adopted by another citizen, let the adoption be
inscribed.  And if he has a son remaining over and above who has not been
adopted upon any lot, and who may be expected to be sent out to a colony
according to law, to him his father may give as much as he pleases of the
rest of his property, with the exception of the paternal lot and the
fixtures on the lot.  And if there are other sons, let him distribute among
them what there is more than the lot in such portions as he pleases.  And
if one of the sons has already a house of his own, he shall not give him of
the money, nor shall he give money to a daughter who has been betrothed,
but if she is not betrothed he may give her money.  And if any of the sons
or daughters shall be found to have another lot of land in the country,
which has accrued after the testament has been made, they shall leave the
lot which they have inherited to the heir of the man who has made the will. 
If the testator has no sons, but only daughters, let him choose the husband
of any one of his daughters whom he pleases, and leave and inscribe him as
his son and heir.  And if a man have lost his son, when he was a child, and
before he could be reckoned among grown-up men, whether his own or an
adopted son, let the testator make mention of the circumstance and inscribe
whom he will to be his second son in hope of better fortune.  If the
testator has no children at all, he may select and give to any one whom he
pleases the tenth part of the property which he has acquired; but let him
not be blamed if he gives all the rest to his adopted son, and makes a
friend of him according to the law.  If the sons of a man require
guardians, and the father when he dies leaves a will appointing guardians,
those who have been named by him, whoever they are and whatever their
number be, if they are able and willing to take charge of the children,
shall be recognized according to the provisions of the will.  But if he
dies and has made no will, or a will in which he has appointed no
guardians, then the next of kin, two on the father's and two on the
mother's side, and one of the friends of the deceased, shall have the
authority of guardians, whom the guardians of the law shall appoint when
the orphans require guardians.  And the fifteen eldest guardians of the law
shall have the whole care and charge of the orphans, divided into threes
according to seniority,--a body of three for one year, and then another
body of three for the next year, until the cycle of the five periods is
complete; and this, as far as possible, is to continue always.  If a man
dies, having made no will at all, and leaves sons who require the care of
guardians, they shall share in the protection which is afforded by these
laws.  And if a man dying by some unexpected fate leaves daughters behind
him, let him pardon the legislator if he gives them in marriage, he have a
regard only to two out of three conditions,--nearness of kin and the
preservation of the lot, and omits the third condition, which a father
would naturally consider, for he would choose out of all the citizens a son
for himself, and a husband for his daughter, with a view to his character
and disposition--the father, say, shall forgive the legislator if he
disregards this, which to him is an impossible consideration.  Let the law
about these matters where practicable be as follows:--If a man dies without
making a will, and leaves behind him daughters, let his brother, being the
son of the same father or of the same mother, having no lot, marry the
daughter and have the lot of the dead man.  And if he have no brother, but
only a brother's son, in like manner let them marry, if they be of a
suitable age; and if there be not even a brother's son, but only the son of
a sister, let them do likewise, and so in the fourth degree, if there be
only the testator's father's brother, or in the fifth degree, his father's
brother's son, or in the sixth degree, the child of his father's sister. 
Let kindred be always reckoned in this way:  if a person leaves daughters
the relationship shall proceed upwards through brothers and sisters, and
brothers' and sisters' children, and first the males shall come, and after
them the females in the same family.  The judge shall consider and
determine the suitableness or unsuitableness of age in marriage; he shall
make an inspection of the males naked, and of the women naked down to the
navel.  And if there be a lack of kinsmen in a family extending to
grandchildren of a brother, or to the grandchildren of a grandfather's
children, the maiden may choose with the consent of her guardians any one
of the citizens who is willing and whom she wills, and he shall be the heir
of the dead man, and the husband of his daughter.  Circumstances vary, and
there may sometimes be a still greater lack of relations within the limits
of the state; and if any maiden has no kindred living in the city, and
there is some one who has been sent out to a colony, and she is disposed to
make him the heir of her father's possessions, if he be indeed of her
kindred, let him proceed to take the lot according to the regulation of the
law; but if he be not of her kindred, she having no kinsmen within the
city, and he be chosen by the daughter of the dead man, and empowered to
marry by the guardians, let him return home and take the lot of him who
died intestate.  And if a man has no children, either male or female, and
dies without making a will, let the previous law in general hold; and let a
man and a woman go forth from the family and share the deserted house, and
let the lot belong absolutely to them; and let the heiress in the first
degree be a sister, and in a second degree a daughter of a brother, and in
the third, a daughter of a sister, in the fourth degree the sister of a
father, and in the fifth degree the daughter of a father's brother, and in
a sixth degree of a father's sister; and these shall dwell with their male
kinsmen, according to the degree of relationship and right, as we enacted
before.  Now we must not conceal from ourselves that such laws are apt to
be oppressive and that there may sometimes be a hardship in the lawgiver
commanding the kinsman of the dead man to marry his relation; he may be
thought not to have considered the innumerable hindrances which may arise
among men in the execution of such ordinances; for there may be cases in
which the parties refuse to obey, and are ready to do anything rather than
marry, when there is some bodily or mental malady or defect among those who
are bidden to marry or be married.  Persons may fancy that the legislator
never thought of this, but they are mistaken; wherefore let us make a
common prelude on behalf of the lawgiver and of his subjects, the law
begging the latter to forgive the legislator, in that he, having to take
care of the common weal, cannot order at the same time the various
circumstances of individuals, and begging him to pardon them if naturally
they are sometimes unable to fulfil the act which he in his ignorance
imposes upon them.

CLEINIAS:  And how, Stranger, can we act most fairly under the
circumstances?

ATHENIAN:  There must be arbiters chosen to deal with such laws and the
subjects of them.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I mean to say, that a case may occur in which the nephew, having
a rich father, will be unwilling to marry the daughter of his uncle; he
will have a feeling of pride, and he will wish to look higher.  And there
are cases in which the legislator will be imposing upon him the greatest
calamity, and he will be compelled to disobey the law, if he is required,
for example, to take a wife who is mad, or has some other terrible malady
of soul or body, such as makes life intolerable to the sufferer.  Then let
what we are saying concerning these cases be embodied in a law:--If any one
finds fault with the established laws respecting testaments, both as to
other matters and especially in what relates to marriage, and asserts that
the legislator, if he were alive and present, would not compel him to obey,
--that is to say, would not compel those who are by our law required to
marry or be given in marriage, to do either,--and some kinsman or guardian
dispute this, the reply is that the legislator left fifteen of the
guardians of the law to be arbiters and fathers of orphans, male or female,
and to them let the disputants have recourse, and by their aid determine
any matters of the kind, admitting their decision to be final.  But if any
one thinks that too great power is thus given to the guardians of the law,
let him bring his adversaries into the court of the select judges, and
there have the points in dispute determined.  And he who loses the cause
shall have censure and blame from the legislator, which, by a man of sense,
is felt to be a penalty far heavier than a great loss of money.

Thus will orphan children have a second birth.  After their first birth we
spoke of their nurture and education, and after their second birth, when
they have lost their parents, we ought to take measures that the misfortune
of orphanhood may be as little sad to them as possible.  In the first
place, we say that the guardians of the law are lawgivers and fathers to
them, not inferior to their natural fathers.  Moreover, they shall take
charge of them year by year as of their own kindred; and we have given both
to them and to the children's own guardians a suitable admonition
concerning the nurture of orphans.  And we seem to have spoken opportunely
in our former discourse, when we said that the souls of the dead have the
power after death of taking an interest in human affairs, about which there
are many tales and traditions, long indeed, but true; and seeing that they
are so many and so ancient, we must believe them, and we must also believe
the lawgivers, who tell us that these things are true, if they are not to
be regarded as utter fools.  But if these things are really so, in the
first place men should have a fear of the Gods above, who regard the
loneliness of the orphans; and in the second place of the souls of the
departed, who by nature incline to take an especial care of their own
children, and are friendly to those who honour, and unfriendly to those who
dishonour them.  Men should also fear the souls of the living who are aged
and high in honour; wherever a city is well ordered and prosperous, their
descendants cherish them, and so live happily; old persons are quick to see
and hear all that relates to them, and are propitious to those who are just
in the fulfilment of such duties, and they punish those who wrong the
orphan and the desolate, considering that they are the greatest and most
sacred of trusts.  To all which matters the guardian and magistrate ought
to apply his mind, if he has any, and take heed of the nurture and
education of the orphans, seeking in every possible way to do them good,
for he is making a contribution to his own good and that of his children. 
He who obeys the tale which precedes the law, and does no wrong to an
orphan, will never experience the wrath of the legislator.  But he who is
disobedient, and wrongs any one who is bereft of father or mother, shall
pay twice the penalty which he would have paid if he had wronged one whose
parents had been alive.  As touching other legislation concerning guardians
in their relation to orphans, or concerning magistrates and their
superintendence of the guardians, if they did not possess examples of the
manner in which children of freemen should be brought up in the bringing up
of their own children, and of the care of their property in the care of
their own, or if they had not just laws fairly stated about these very
things,--there would have been reason in making laws for them, under the
idea that they were a peculiar class, and we might distinguish and make
separate rules for the life of those who are orphans and of those who are
not orphans.  But as the case stands, the condition of orphans with us is
not different from the case of those who have father, though in regard to
honour and dishonour, and the attention given to them, the two are not
usually placed upon a level.  Wherefore, touching the legislation about
orphans, the law speaks in serious accents, both of persuasion and
threatening, and such a threat as the following will be by no means out of
place:--He who is the guardian of an orphan of either sex, and he among the
guardians of the law to whom the superintendence of this guardian has been
assigned, shall love the unfortunate orphan as though he were his own
child, and he shall be as careful and diligent in the management of his
possessions as he would be if they were his own, or even more careful and
diligent.  Let every one who has the care of an orphan observe this law. 
But any one who acts contrary to the law on these matters, if he be a
guardian of the child, may be fined by a magistrate, or, if he be himself a
magistrate, the guardian may bring him before the court of select judges,
and punish him, if convicted, by exacting a fine of double the amount of
that inflicted by the court.  And if a guardian appears to the relations of
the orphan, or to any other citizen, to act negligently or dishonestly, let
them bring him before the same court, and whatever damages are given
against him, let him pay fourfold, and let half belong to the orphan and
half to him who procured the conviction.  If any orphan arrives at years of
discretion, and thinks that he has been ill-used by his guardians, let him
within five years of the expiration of the guardianship be allowed to bring
them to trial; and if any of them be convicted, the court shall determine
what he shall pay or suffer.  And if a magistrate shall appear to have
wronged the orphan by neglect, and he be convicted, let the court determine
what he shall suffer or pay to the orphan, and if there be dishonesty in
addition to neglect, besides paying the fine, let him be deposed from his
office of guardian of the law, and let the state appoint another guardian
of the law for the city and for the country in his room.

Greater differences than there ought to be sometimes arise between fathers
and sons, on the part either of fathers who will be of opinion that the
legislator should enact that they may, if they wish, lawfully renounce
their son by the proclamation of a herald in the face of the world, or of
sons who think that they should be allowed to indict their fathers on the
charge of imbecility when they are disabled by disease or old age.  These
things only happen, as a matter of fact, where the natures of men are
utterly bad; for where only half is bad, as, for example, if the father be
not bad, but the son be bad, or conversely, no great calamity is the result
of such an amount of hatred as this.  In another state, a son disowned by
his father would not of necessity cease to be a citizen, but in our state,
of which these are to be the laws, the disinherited must necessarily
emigrate into another country, for no addition can be made even of a single
family to the 5040 households; and, therefore, he who deserves to suffer
these things must be renounced not only by his father, who is a single
person, but by the whole family, and what is done in these cases must be
regulated by some such law as the following:--He who in the sad disorder of
his soul has a mind, justly or unjustly, to expel from his family a son
whom he has begotten and brought up, shall not lightly or at once execute
his purpose; but first of all he shall collect together his own kinsmen,
extending to cousins, and in like manner his son's kinsmen by the mother's
side, and in their presence he shall accuse his son, setting forth that he
deserves at the hands of them all to be dismissed from the family; and the
son shall be allowed to address them in a similar manner, and show that he
does not deserve to suffer any of these things.  And if the father
persuades them, and obtains the suffrages of more than half of his kindred,
exclusive of the father and mother and the offender himself--I say, if he
obtains more than half the suffrages of all the other grown-up members of
the family, of both sexes, the father shall be permitted to put away his
son, but not otherwise.  And if any other citizen is willing to adopt the
son who is put away, no law shall hinder him; for the characters of young
men are subject to many changes in the course of their lives.  And if he
has been put away, and in a period of ten years no one is willing to adopt
him, let those who have the care of the superabundant population which is
sent out into colonies, see to him, in order that he may be suitably
provided for in the colony.  And if disease or age or harshness of temper,
or all these together, makes a man to be more out of his mind than the rest
of the world are,--but this is not observable, except to those who live
with him,--and he, being master of his property, is the ruin of the house,
and his son doubts and hesitates about indicting his father for insanity,
let the law in that case ordain that he shall first of all go to the eldest
guardians of the law and tell them of his father's misfortune, and they
shall duly look into the matter, and take counsel as to whether he shall
indict him or not.  And if they advise him to proceed, they shall be both
his witnesses and his advocates; and if the father is cast, he shall
henceforth be incapable of ordering the least particular of his life; let
him be as a child dwelling in the house for the remainder of his days.  And
if a man and his wife have an unfortunate incompatibility of temper, ten of
the guardians of the law, who are impartial (or, 'who are intermediate in
age':--i.e. who are neither the youngest nor the oldest guardians of the
law), and ten of the women who regulate marriages, shall look to the
matter, and if they are able to reconcile them they shall be formally
reconciled; but if their souls are too much tossed with passion, they shall
endeavour to find other partners.  Now they are not likely to have very
gentle tempers; and, therefore, we must endeavour to associate with them
deeper and softer natures.  Those who have no children, or only a few, at
the time of their separation, should choose their new partners with a view
to the procreation of children; but those who have a sufficient number of
children should separate and marry again in order that they may have some
one to grow old with and that the pair may take care of one another in age. 
If a woman dies, leaving children, male or female, the law will advise
rather than compel the husband to bring up the children without introducing
into the house a stepmother.  But if he have no children, then he shall be
compelled to marry until he has begotten a sufficient number of sons to his
family and to the state.  And if a man dies leaving a sufficient number of
children, the mother of his children shall remain with them and bring them
up.  But if she appears to be too young to live virtuously without a
husband, let her relations communicate with the women who superintend
marriage, and let both together do what they think best in these matters;
if there is a lack of children, let the choice be made with a view to
having them; two children, one of either sex, shall be deemed sufficient in
the eye of the law.  When a child is admitted to be the offspring of
certain parents and is acknowledged by them, but there is need of a
decision as to which parent the child is to follow,--in case a female slave
have intercourse with a male slave, or with a freeman or freedman, the
offspring shall always belong to the master of the female slave.  Again, if
a free woman have intercourse with a male slave, the offspring shall belong
to the master of the slave; but if a child be born either of a slave by her
master, or of his mistress by a slave--and this be proven--the offspring of
the woman and its father shall be sent away by the women who superintend
marriage into another country, and the guardians of the law shall send away
the offspring of the man and its mother.

Neither God, nor a man who has understanding, will ever advise any one to
neglect his parents.  To a discourse concerning the honour and dishonour of
parents, a prelude such as the following, about the service of the Gods,
will be a suitable introduction:--There are ancient customs about the Gods
which are universal, and they are of two kinds:  some of the Gods we see
with our eyes and we honour them, of others we honour the images, raising
statues of them which we adore; and though they are lifeless, yet we
imagine that the living Gods have a good will and gratitude to us on this
account.  Now, if a man has a father or mother, or their fathers or mothers
treasured up in his house stricken in years, let him consider that no
statue can be more potent to grant his requests than they are, who are
sitting at his hearth, if only he knows how to show true service to them.

CLEINIAS:  And what do you call the true mode of service?

ATHENIAN:  I will tell you, O my friend, for such things are worth
listening to.

CLEINIAS:  Proceed.

ATHENIAN:  Oedipus, as tradition says, when dishonoured by his sons,
invoked on them curses which every one declares to have been heard and
ratified by the Gods, and Amyntor in his wrath invoked curses on his son
Phoenix, and Theseus upon Hippolytus, and innumerable others have also
called down wrath upon their children, whence it is clear that the Gods
listen to the imprecations of parents; for the curses of parents are, as
they ought to be, mighty against their children as no others are.  And
shall we suppose that the prayers of a father or mother who is specially
dishonoured by his or her children, are heard by the Gods in accordance
with nature; and that if a parent is honoured by them, and in the gladness
of his heart earnestly entreats the Gods in his prayers to do them good, he
is not equally heard, and that they do not minister to his request?  If
not, they would be very unjust ministers of good, and that we affirm to be
contrary to their nature.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  May we not think, as I was saying just now, that we can possess
no image which is more honoured by the Gods, than that of a father or
grandfather, or of a mother stricken in years? whom when a man honours, the
heart of the God rejoices, and he is ready to answer their prayers.  And,
truly, the figure of an ancestor is a wonderful thing, far higher than that
of a lifeless image.  For the living, when they are honoured by us, join in
our prayers, and when they are dishonoured, they utter imprecations against
us; but lifeless objects do neither.  And therefore, if a man makes a right
use of his father and grandfather and other aged relations, he will have
images which above all others will win him the favour of the Gods.

CLEINIAS:  Excellent.

ATHENIAN:  Every man of any understanding fears and respects the prayers of
parents, knowing well that many times and to many persons they have been
accomplished.  Now these things being thus ordered by nature, good men
think it a blessing from heaven if their parents live to old age and reach
the utmost limit of human life, or if taken away before their time they are
deeply regretted by them; but to bad men parents are always a cause of
terror.  Wherefore let every man honour with every sort of lawful honour
his own parents, agreeably to what has now been said.  But if this prelude
be an unmeaning sound in the ears of any one, let the law follow, which may
be rightly imposed in these terms:--If any one in this city be not
sufficiently careful of his parents, and do not regard and gratify in every
respect their wishes more than those of his sons and of his other offspring
or of himself,--let him who experiences this sort of treatment either come
himself, or send some one to inform the three eldest guardians of the law,
and three of the women who have the care of marriages; and let them look to
the matter and punish youthful evil-doers with stripes and bonds if they
are under thirty years of age, that is to say, if they be men, or if they
be women, let them undergo the same punishment up to forty years of age. 
But if, when they are still more advanced in years, they continue the same
neglect of their parents, and do any hurt to any of them, let them be
brought before a court in which every single one of the eldest citizens
shall be the judges, and if the offender be convicted, let the court
determine what he ought to pay or suffer, and any penalty may be imposed on
him which a man can pay or suffer.  If the person who has been wronged be
unable to inform the magistrates, let any freeman who hears of his case
inform, and if he do not, he shall be deemed base, and shall be liable to
have a suit for damage brought against him by any one who likes.  And if a
slave inform, he shall receive freedom; and if he be the slave of the
injurer or injured party, he shall be set free by the magistrates, or if he
belong to any other citizen, the public shall pay a price on his behalf to
the owner; and let the magistrates take heed that no one wrongs him out of
revenge, because he has given information.

Cases in which one man injures another by poisons, and which prove fatal,
have been already discussed (i.e. they are cases of murder); but about
other cases in which a person intentionally and of malice harms another
with meats, or drinks, or ointments, nothing has as yet been determined. 
For there are two kinds of poisons used among men, which cannot clearly be
distinguished.  There is the kind just now explicitly mentioned, which
injures bodies by the use of other bodies according to a natural law; there
is also another kind which persuades the more daring class that they can do
injury by sorceries, and incantations, and magic knots, as they are termed,
and makes others believe that they above all persons are injured by the
powers of the magician.  Now it is not easy to know the nature of all these
things; nor if a man do know can he readily persuade others to believe him. 
And when men are disturbed in their minds at the sight of waxen images
fixed either at their doors, or in a place where three ways meet, or on the
sepulchres of parents, there is no use in trying to persuade them that they
should despise all such things because they have no certain knowledge about
them.  But we must have a law in two parts, concerning poisoning, in
whichever of the two ways the attempt is made, and we must entreat, and
exhort, and advise men not to have recourse to such practices, by which
they scare the multitude out of their wits, as if they were children,
compelling the legislator and the judge to heal the fears which the
sorcerer arouses, and to tell them in the first place, that he who attempts
to poison or enchant others knows not what he is doing, either as regards
the body (unless he has a knowledge of medicine), or as regards his
enchantments (unless he happens to be a prophet or diviner).  Let the law,
then, run as follows about poisoning or witchcraft:--He who employs poison
to do any injury, not fatal, to a man himself, or to his servants, or any
injury, whether fatal or not, to his cattle or his bees, if he be a
physician, and be convicted of poisoning, shall be punished with death; or
if he be a private person, the court shall determine what he is to pay or
suffer.  But he who seems to be the sort of man who injures others by magic
knots, or enchantments, or incantations, or any of the like practices, if
he be a prophet or diviner, let him die; and if, not being a prophet, he be
convicted of witchcraft, as in the previous case, let the court fix what he
ought to pay or suffer.

When a man does another any injury by theft or violence, for the greater
injury let him pay greater damages to the injured man, and less for the
smaller injury; but in all cases, whatever the injury may have been, as
much as will compensate the loss.  And besides the compensation of the
wrong, let a man pay a further penalty for the chastisement of his offence: 
he who has done the wrong instigated by the folly of another, through the
lightheartedness of youth or the like, shall pay a lighter penalty; but he
who has injured another through his own folly, when overcome by pleasure or
pain, in cowardly fear, or lust, or envy, or implacable anger, shall endure
a heavier punishment.  Not that he is punished because he did wrong, for
that which is done can never be undone, but in order that in future times,
he, and those who see him corrected, may utterly hate injustice, or at any
rate abate much of their evil-doing.  Having an eye to all these things,
the law, like a good archer, should aim at the right measure of punishment,
and in all cases at the deserved punishment.  In the attainment of this the
judge shall be a fellow-worker with the legislator, whenever the law leaves
to him to determine what the offender shall suffer or pay; and the
legislator, like a painter, shall give a rough sketch of the cases in which
the law is to be applied.  This is what we must do, Megillus and Cleinias,
in the best and fairest manner that we can, saying what the punishments are
to be of all actions of theft and violence, and giving laws of such a kind
as the Gods and sons of Gods would have us give.

If a man is mad he shall not be at large in the city, but his relations
shall keep him at home in any way which they can; or if not, let them pay a
penalty,--he who is of the highest class shall pay a penalty of one hundred
drachmas, whether he be a slave or a freeman whom he neglects; and he of
the second class shall pay four-fifths of a mina; and he of the third class
three-fifths; and he of the fourth class two-fifths.  Now there are many
sorts of madness, some arising out of disease, which we have already
mentioned; and there are other kinds, which originate in an evil and
passionate temperament, and are increased by bad education; out of a slight
quarrel this class of madmen will often raise a storm of abuse against one
another, and nothing of that sort ought to be allowed to occur in a well-
ordered state.  Let this, then, be the law about abuse, which shall relate
to all cases:--No one shall speak evil of another; and when a man disputes
with another he shall teach and learn of the disputant and the company, but
he shall abstain from evil-speaking; for out of the imprecations which men
utter against one another, and the feminine habit of casting aspersions on
one another, and using foul names, out of words light as air, in very deed
the greatest enmities and hatreds spring up.  For the speaker gratifies his
anger, which is an ungracious element of his nature; and nursing up his
wrath by the entertainment of evil thoughts, and exacerbating that part of
his soul which was formerly civilized by education, he lives in a state of
savageness and moroseness, and pays a bitter penalty for his anger.  And in
such cases almost all men take to saying something ridiculous about their
opponent, and there is no man who is in the habit of laughing at another
who does not miss virtue and earnestness altogether, or lose the better
half of greatness.  Wherefore let no one utter any taunting word at a
temple, or at the public sacrifices, or at the games, or in the agora, or
in a court of justice, or in any public assembly.  And let the magistrate
who presides on these occasions chastise an offender, and he shall be
blameless; but if he fails in doing so, he shall not claim the prize of
virtue; for he is one who heeds not the laws, and does not do what the
legislator commands.  And if in any other place any one indulges in these
sort of revilings, whether he has begun the quarrel or is only retaliating,
let any elder who is present support the law, and control with blows those
who indulge in passion, which is another great evil; and if he do not, let
him be liable to pay the appointed penalty.  And we say now, that he who
deals in reproaches against others cannot reproach them without attempting
to ridicule them; and this, when done in a moment of anger, is what we make
matter of reproach against him.  But then, do we admit into our state the
comic writers (compare Republic; Arist. Pol.) who are so fond of making
mankind ridiculous, if they attempt in a good-natured manner to turn the
laugh against our citizens? or do we draw the distinction of jest and
earnest, and allow a man to make use of ridicule in jest and without anger
about any thing or person; though as we were saying, not if he be angry
have a set purpose?  We forbid earnest--that is unalterably fixed; but we
have still to say who are to be sanctioned or not to be sanctioned by the
law in the employment of innocent humour.  A comic poet, or maker of iambic
or satirical lyric verse, shall not be permitted to ridicule any of the
citizens, either by word or likeness, either in anger or without anger. 
And if any one is disobedient, the judges shall either at once expel him
from the country, or he shall pay a fine of three minae, which shall be
dedicated to the God who presides over the contests.  Those only who have
received permission shall be allowed to write verses at one another, but
they shall be without anger and in jest; in anger and in serious earnest
they shall not be allowed.  The decision of this matter shall be left to
the superintendent of the general education of the young, and whatever he
may license, the writer shall be allowed to produce, and whatever he
rejects let not the poet himself exhibit, or ever teach anybody else, slave
or freeman, under the penalty of being dishonoured, and held disobedient to
the laws.

Now he is not to be pitied who is hungry, or who suffers any bodily pain,
but he who is temperate, or has some other virtue, or part of a virtue, and
at the same time suffers from misfortune; it would be an extraordinary
thing if such an one, whether slave or freeman, were utterly forsaken and
fell into the extremes of poverty in any tolerably well-ordered city or
government.  Wherefore the legislator may safely make a law applicable to
such cases in the following terms:--Let there be no beggars in our state;
and if anybody begs, seeking to pick up a livelihood by unavailing prayers,
let the wardens of the agora turn him out of the agora, and the wardens of
the city out of the city, and the wardens of the country send him out of
any other parts of the land across the border, in order that the land may
be cleared of this sort of animal.

If a slave of either sex injure anything, which is not his or her own,
through inexperience, or some improper practice, and the person who suffers
damage be not himself in part to blame, the master of the slave who has
done the harm shall either make full satisfaction, or give up the slave who
has done the injury.  But if master argue that the charge has arisen by
collusion between the injured party and the injurer, with the view of
obtaining the slave, let him sue the person, who says that he has been
injured, for malpractices.  And if he gain a conviction, let him receive
double the value which the court fixes as the price of the slave; and if he
lose his suit, let him make amends for the injury, and give up the slave. 
And if a beast of burden, or horse, or dog, or any other animal, injure the
property of a neighbour, the owner shall in like manner pay for the injury.

If any man refuses to be a witness, he who wants him shall summon him, and
he who is summoned shall come to the trial; and if he knows and is willing
to bear witness, let him bear witness, but if he says he does not know let
him swear by the three divinities Zeus, and Apollo, and Themis, that he
does not, and have no more to do with the cause.  And he who is summoned to
give witness and does not answer to his summoner, shall be liable for the
harm which ensues according to law.  And if a person calls up as a witness
any one who is acting as a judge, let him give his witness, but he shall
not afterwards vote in the cause.  A free woman may give her witness and
plead, if she be more than forty years of age, and may bring an action if
she have no husband; but if her husband be alive she shall only be allowed
to bear witness.  A slave of either sex and a child shall be allowed to
give evidence and to plead, but only in cases of murder; and they must
produce sufficient sureties that they will certainly remain until the
trial, in case they should be charged with false witness.  And either of
the parties in a cause may bring an accusation of perjury against
witnesses, touching their evidence in whole or in part, if he asserts that
such evidence has been given; but the accusation must be brought previous
to the final decision of the cause.  The magistrates shall preserve the
accusations of false witness, and have them kept under the seal of both
parties, and produce them on the day when the trial for false witness takes
place.  If a man be twice convicted of false witness, he shall not be
required, and if thrice, he shall not be allowed to bear witness; and if he
dare to witness after he has been convicted three times, let any one who
pleases inform against him to the magistrates, and let the magistrates hand
him over to the court, and if he be convicted he shall be punished with
death.  And in any case in which the evidence is rightly found to be false,
and yet to have given the victory to him who wins the suit, and more than
half the witnesses are condemned, the decision which was gained by these
means shall be rescinded, and there shall be a discussion and a decision as
to whether the suit was determined by that false evidence or not; and in
whichever way the decision may be given, the previous suit shall be
determined accordingly.

There are many noble things in human life, but to most of them attach evils
which are fated to corrupt and spoil them.  Is not justice noble, which has
been the civilizer of humanity?  How then can the advocate of justice be
other than noble?  And yet upon this profession which is presented to us
under the fair name of art has come an evil reputation (the text is
probably corrupt).  In the first place, we are told that by ingenious pleas
and the help of an advocate the law enables a man to win a particular
cause, whether just or unjust; and that both the art, and the power of
speech which is thereby imparted, are at the service of him who is willing
to pay for them.  Now in our state this so-called art, whether really an
art (compare Gorg.) or only an experience and practice destitute of any
art, ought if possible never to come into existence, or if existing among
us should listen to the request of the legislator and go away into another
land, and not speak contrary to justice.  If the offenders obey we say no
more; but for those who disobey, the voice of the law is as follows:--If
any one thinks that he will pervert the power of justice in the minds of
the judges, and unseasonably litigate or advocate, let any one who likes
indict him for malpractices of law and dishonest advocacy, and let him be
judged in the court of select judges; and if he be convicted, let the court
determine whether he may be supposed to act from a love of money or from
contentiousness.  And if he is supposed to act from contentiousness, the
court shall fix a time during which he shall not be allowed to institute or
plead a cause; and if he is supposed to act as he does from love of money,
in case he be a stranger, he shall leave the country, and never return
under penalty of death; but if he be a citizen, he shall die, because he is
a lover of money, in whatever manner gained; and equally, if he be judged
to have acted more than once from contentiousness, he shall die.


BOOK XII.

If a herald or an ambassador carry a false message from our city to any
other, or bring back a false message from the city to which he is sent, or
be proved to have brought back, whether from friends or enemies, in his
capacity of herald or ambassador, what they have never said, let him be
indicted for having violated, contrary to the law, the commands and duties
imposed upon him by Hermes and Zeus, and let there be a penalty fixed,
which he shall suffer or pay if he be convicted.

Theft is a mean, and robbery a shameless thing; and none of the sons of
Zeus delight in fraud and violence, or ever practised either.  Wherefore
let no one be deluded by poets or mythologers into a mistaken belief of
such things, nor let him suppose, when he thieves or is guilty of violence,
that he is doing nothing base, but only what the Gods themselves do.  For
such tales are untrue and improbable; and he who steals or robs contrary to
the law, is never either a God or the son of a God; of this the legislator
ought to be better informed than all the poets put together (compare
Republic).  Happy is he and may he be forever happy, who is persuaded and
listens to our words; but he who disobeys shall have to contend against the
following law:--If a man steal anything belonging to the public, whether
that which he steals be much or little, he shall have the same punishment. 
For he who steals a little steals with the same wish as he who steals much,
but with less power, and he who takes up a greater amount, not having
deposited it, is wholly unjust.  Wherefore the law is not disposed to
inflict a less penalty on the one than on the other because his theft is
less, but on the ground that the thief may possibly be in one case still
curable, and may in another case be incurable.  If any one convict in a
court of law a stranger or a slave of a theft of public property, let the
court determine what punishment he shall suffer, or what penalty he shall
pay, bearing in mind that he is probably not incurable.  But the citizen
who has been brought up as our citizens will have been, if he be found
guilty of robbing his country by fraud or violence, whether he be caught in
the act or not, shall be punished with death; for he is incurable.  (This
passage is not consistent with Chapter ix., where theft of public property
is punished by imprisonment.)

Now for expeditions of war much consideration and many laws are required;
the great principle of all is that no one of either sex should be without a
commander (compare Thucyd.); nor should the mind of any one be accustomed
to do anything, either in jest or earnest, of his own motion, but in war
and in peace he should look to and follow his leader, even in the least
things being under his guidance; for example, he should stand or move, or
exercise, or wash, or take his meals, or get up in the night to keep guard
and deliver messages when he is bidden; and in the hour of danger he should
not pursue and not retreat except by order of his superior; and in a word,
not teach the soul or accustom her to know or understand how to do anything
apart from others.  Of all soldiers the life should be always and in all
things as far as possible in common and together; there neither is nor ever
will be a higher, or better, or more scientific principle than this for the
attainment of salvation and victory in war.  And we ought in time of peace
from youth upwards to practise this habit of commanding others, and of
being commanded by others; anarchy should have no place in the life of man
or of the beasts who are subject to man.  I may add that all dances ought
to be performed with a view to military excellence; and agility and ease
should be cultivated for the same object, and also endurance of the want of
meats and drinks, and of winter cold and summer heat, and of hard couches;
and, above all, care should be taken not to destroy the peculiar qualities
of the head and the feet by surrounding them with extraneous coverings, and
so hindering their natural growth of hair and soles.  For these are the
extremities, and of all the parts of the body, whether they are preserved
or not is of the greatest consequence; the one is the servant of the whole
body, and the other the master, in whom all the ruling senses are by nature
set.  Let the young man imagine that he hears in what has preceded the
praises of the military life; the law shall be as follows:--He shall serve
in war who is on the roll or appointed to some special service, and if any
one is absent from cowardice, and without the leave of the generals; he
shall be indicted before the military commanders for failure of service
when the army comes home; and the soldiers shall be his judges; the heavy-
armed, and the cavalry, and the other arms of the service shall form
separate courts; and they shall bring the heavy-armed before the heavy-
armed, and the horsemen before the horsemen, and the others in like manner
before their peers; and he who is found guilty shall never be allowed to
compete for any prize of valour, or indict another for not serving on an
expedition, or be an accuser at all in any military matters.  Moreover, the
court shall further determine what punishment he shall suffer, or what
penalty he shall pay.  When the suits for failure of service are completed,
the leaders of the several kinds of troops shall again hold an assembly,
and they shall adjudge the prizes of valour; and he who likes shall give
judgment in his own branch of the service, saying nothing about any former
expedition, nor producing any proof or witnesses to confirm his statement,
but speaking only of the present occasion.  The crown of victory shall be
an olive wreath which the victor shall offer up the temple of any war-god
whom he likes, adding an inscription for a testimony to last during life,
that such an one has received the first, the second, or the third prize. 
If any one goes on an expedition, and returns home before the appointed
time, when the generals have not withdrawn the army, be shall be indicted
for desertion before the same persons who took cognizance of failure of
service, and if he be found guilty, the same punishment shall be inflicted
on him.

Now every man who is engaged in any suit ought to be very careful of
bringing false witness against any one, either intentionally or
unintentionally, if he can help; for justice is truly said to be an
honourable maiden, and falsehood is naturally repugnant to honour and
justice.  A witness ought to be very careful not to sin against justice, as
for example in what relates to the throwing away of arms--he must
distinguish the throwing them away when necessary, and not make that a
reproach, or bring in action against some innocent person on that account. 
To make the distinction may be difficult; but still the law must attempt to
define the different kinds in some way.  Let me endeavour to explain my
meaning by an ancient tale:--If Patroclus had been brought to the tent
still alive but without his arms (and this has happened to innumerable
persons), the original arms, which the poet says were presented to Peleus
by the Gods as a nuptial gift when he married Thetis, remaining in the
hands of Hector, then the base spirits of that day might have reproached
the son of Menoetius with having cast away his arms.  Again, there is the
case of those who have been thrown down precipices and lost their arms; and
of those who at sea, and in stormy places, have been suddenly overwhelmed
by floods of water; and there are numberless things of this kind which one
might adduce by way of extenuation, and with the view of justifying a
misfortune which is easily misrepresented.  We must, therefore, endeavour
to divide to the best of our power the greater and more serious evil from
the lesser.  And a distinction may be drawn in the use of terms of
reproach.  A man does not always deserve to be called the thrower away of
his shield; he may be only the loser of his arms.  For there is a great or
rather absolute difference between him who is deprived of his arms by a
sufficient force, and him who voluntarily lets his shield go.  Let the law
then be as follows:--If a person having arms is overtaken by the enemy and
does not turn round and defend himself, but lets them go voluntarily or
throws them away, choosing a base life and a swift escape rather than a
courageous and noble and blessed death--in such a case of the throwing away
of arms let justice be done, but the judge need take no note of the case
just now mentioned; for the bad man ought always to be punished, in the
hope that he may be improved, but not the unfortunate, for there is no
advantage in that.  And what shall be the punishment suited to him who has
thrown away his weapons of defence?  Tradition says that Caeneus, the
Thessalian, was changed by a God from a woman into a man; but the converse
miracle cannot now be wrought, or no punishment would be more proper than
that the man who throws away his shield should be changed into a woman
(compare Timaeus).  This however is impossible, and therefore let us make a
law as nearly like this as we can--that he who loves his life too well
shall be in no danger for the remainder of his days, but shall live for
ever under the stigma of cowardice.  And let the law be in the following
terms:--When a man is found guilty of disgracefully throwing away his arms
in war, no general or military officer shall allow him to serve as a
soldier, or give him any place at all in the ranks of soldiers; and the
officer who gives the coward any place, shall suffer a penalty which the
public examiner shall exact of him; and if he be of the highest class, he
shall pay a thousand drachmae; or if he be of the second class, five minae;
or if he be of the third, three minae; or if he be of the fourth class, one
mina.  And he who is found guilty of cowardice, shall not only be dismissed
from manly dangers, which is a disgrace appropriate to his nature, but he
shall pay a thousand drachmae, if he be of the highest class, and five
minae if he be of the second class, and three if he be of the third class,
and a mina, like the preceding, if he be of the fourth class.

What regulations will be proper about examiners, seeing that some of our
magistrates are elected by lot, and for a year, and some for a longer time
and from selected persons?  Of such magistrates, who will be a sufficient
censor or examiner, if any of them, weighed down by the pressure of office
or his own inability to support the dignity of his office, be guilty of any
crooked practice?  It is by no means easy to find a magistrate who excels
other magistrates in virtue, but still we must endeavour to discover some
censor or examiner who is more than man.  For the truth is, that there are
many elements of dissolution in a state, as there are also in a ship, or in
an animal; they all have their cords, and girders, and sinews,--one nature
diffused in many places, and called by many names; and the office of
examiner is a most important element in the preservation and dissolution of
states.  For if the examiners are better than the magistrates, and their
duty is fulfilled justly and without blame, then the whole state and
country flourishes and is happy; but if the examination of the magistrates
is carried on in a wrong way, then, by the relaxation of that justice which
is the uniting principle of all constitutions, every power in the state is
rent asunder from every other; they no longer incline in the same
direction, but fill the city with faction, and make many cities out of one
(compare Republic), and soon bring all to destruction.  Wherefore the
examiners ought to be admirable in every sort of virtue.  Let us invent a
mode of creating them, which shall be as follows:--Every year, after the
summer solstice, the whole city shall meet in the common precincts of
Helios and Apollo, and shall present to the God three men out of their own
number in the manner following:--Each citizen shall select, not himself,
but some other citizen whom he deems in every way the best, and who is not
less than fifty years of age.  And out of the selected persons who have the
greatest number of votes, they shall make a further selection until they
reduce them to one-half, if they are an even number; but if they are not an
even number, they shall subtract the one who has the smallest number of
votes, and make them an even number, and then leave the half which have the
greater number of votes.  And if two persons have an equal number of votes,
and thus increase the number beyond one-half, they shall withdraw the
younger of the two and do away with the excess; and then including all the
rest they shall again vote, until there are left three having an unequal
number of votes.  But if all the three, or two out of the three, have equal
votes, let them commit the election to good fate and fortune, and separate
off by lot the first, and the second, and the third; these they shall crown
with an olive wreath and give them the prize of excellence, at the same
time proclaiming to all the world that the city of the Magnetes, by
providence of the Gods, is again preserved, and presents to the Sun and to
Apollo her three best men as first-fruits, to be a common offering to them,
according to the ancient law, as long as their lives answer to the judgment
formed of them.  And these shall appoint in their first year twelve
examiners, to continue until each has completed seventy-five years, to whom
three shall afterwards be added yearly; and let these divide all the
magistracies into twelve parts, and prove the holders of them by every sort
of test to which a freeman may be subjected; and let them live while they
hold office in the precinct of Helios and Apollo, in which they were
chosen, and let each one form a judgment of some things individually, and
of others in company with his colleagues; and let him place a writing in
the agora about each magistracy, and what the magistrate ought to suffer or
pay, according to the decision of the examiners.  And if a magistrate does
not admit that he has been justly judged, let him bring the examiners
before the select judges, and if he be acquitted by their decision, let
him, if he will, accuse the examiners themselves; if, however, he be
convicted, and have been condemned to death by the examiners, let him die
(and of course he can only die once):--but any other penalties which admit
of being doubled let him suffer twice over.

And now let us pass under review the examiners themselves; what will their
examination be, and how conducted?  During the life of these men, whom the
whole state counts worthy of the rewards of virtue, they shall have the
first seat at all public assemblies, and at all Hellenic sacrifices and
sacred missions, and other public and holy ceremonies in which they share. 
The chiefs of each sacred mission shall be selected from them, and they
only of all the citizens shall be adorned with a crown of laurel; they
shall all be priests of Apollo and Helios; and one of them, who is judged
first of the priests created in that year, shall be high priest; and they
shall write up his name in each year to be a measure of time as long as the
city lasts; and after their death they shall be laid out and carried to the
grave and entombed in a manner different from the other citizens.  They
shall be decked in a robe all of white, and there shall be no crying or
lamentation over them; but a chorus of fifteen maidens, and another of
boys, shall stand around the bier on either side, hymning the praises of
the departed priests in alternate responses, declaring their blessedness in
song all day long; and at dawn a hundred of the youths who practise
gymnastic exercises, and whom the relations of the departed shall choose,
shall carry the bier to the sepulchre, the young men marching first,
dressed in the garb of warriors,--the cavalry with their horses, the heavy-
armed with their arms, and the others in like manner.  And boys near the
bier and in front of it shall sing their national hymn, and maidens shall
follow behind, and with them the women who have passed the age of child-
bearing; next, although they are interdicted from other burials, let
priests and priestesses follow, unless the Pythian oracle forbid them; for
this burial is free from pollution.  The place of burial shall be an oblong
vaulted chamber underground, constructed of tufa, which will last for ever,
having stone couches placed side by side.  And here they will lay the
blessed person, and cover the sepulchre with a circular mound of earth and
plant a grove of trees around on every side but one; and on that side the
sepulchre shall be allowed to extend for ever, and a new mound will not be
required.  Every year they shall have contests in music and gymnastics, and
in horsemanship, in honour of the dead.  These are the honours which shall
be given to those who at the examination are found blameless; but if any of
them, trusting to the scrutiny being over, should, after the judgment has
been given, manifest the wickedness of human nature, let the law ordain
that he who pleases shall indict him, and let the cause be tried in the
following manner.  In the first place, the court shall be composed of the
guardians of the law, and to them the surviving examiners shall be added,
as well as the court of select judges; and let the pursuer lay his
indictment in this form--he shall say that so-and-so is unworthy of the
prize of virtue and of his office; and if the defendant be convicted let
him be deprived of his office, and of the burial, and of the other honours
given him.  But if the prosecutor do not obtain the fifth part of the
votes, let him, if he be of the first class, pay twelve minae, and eight if
he be of the second class, and six if he be of the third class, and two
minae if he be of the fourth class.

The so-called decision of Rhadamanthus is worthy of all admiration.  He
knew that the men of his own time believed and had no doubt that there were
Gods, which was a reasonable belief in those days, because most men were
the sons of Gods (compare Timaeus), and according to tradition he was one
himself.  He appears to have thought that he ought to commit judgment to no
man, but to the Gods only, and in this way suits were simply and speedily
decided by him.  For he made the two parties take an oath respecting the
points in dispute, and so got rid of the matter speedily and safely.  But
now that a certain portion of mankind do not believe at all in the
existence of the Gods, and others imagine that they have no care of us, and
the opinion of most men, and of the worst men, is that in return for a
small sacrifice and a few flattering words they will be their accomplices
in purloining large sums and save them from many terrible punishments, the
way of Rhadamanthus is no longer suited to the needs of justice; for as the
opinions of men about the Gods are changed, the laws should also be
changed;--in the granting of suits a rational legislation ought to do away
with the oaths of the parties on either side--he who obtains leave to bring
an action should write down the charges, but should not add an oath; and
the defendant in like manner should give his denial to the magistrates in
writing, and not swear; for it is a dreadful thing to know, when many
lawsuits are going on in a state, that almost half the people who meet one
another quite unconcernedly at the public meals and in other companies and
relations of private life are perjured.  Let the law, then, be as follows:
--A judge who is about to give judgment shall take an oath, and he who is
choosing magistrates for the state shall either vote on oath or with a
voting tablet which he brings from a temple; so too the judge of dances and
of all music, and the superintendents and umpires of gymnastic and
equestrian contests, and any matters in which, as far as men can judge,
there is nothing to be gained by a false oath; but all cases in which a
denial confirmed by an oath clearly results in a great advantage to the
taker of the oath, shall be decided without the oath of the parties to the
suit, and the presiding judges shall not permit either of them to use an
oath for the sake of persuading, nor to call down curses on himself and his
race, nor to use unseemly supplications or womanish laments.  But they
shall ever be teaching and learning what is just in auspicious words; and
he who does otherwise shall be supposed to speak beside the point, and the
judges shall again bring him back to the question at issue.  On the other
hand, strangers in their dealings with strangers shall as at present have
power to give and receive oaths, for they will not often grow old in the
city or leave a fry of young ones like themselves to be the sons and heirs
of the land.

As to the initiation of private suits, let the manner of deciding causes
between all citizens be the same as in cases in which any freeman is
disobedient to the state in minor matters, of which the penalty is not
stripes, imprisonment, or death.  But as regards attendance at choruses or
processions or other shows, and as regards public services, whether the
celebration of sacrifice in peace, or the payment of contributions in war--
in all these cases, first comes the necessity of providing a remedy for the
loss; and by those who will not obey, there shall be security given to the
officers whom the city and the law empower to exact the sum due; and if
they forfeit their security, let the goods which they have pledged be sold
and the money given to the city; but if they ought to pay a larger sum, the
several magistrates shall impose upon the disobedient a suitable penalty,
and bring them before the court, until they are willing to do what they are
ordered.

Now a state which makes money from the cultivation of the soil only, and
has no foreign trade, must consider what it will do about the emigration of
its own people to other countries, and the reception of strangers from
elsewhere.  About these matters the legislator has to consider, and he will
begin by trying to persuade men as far as he can.  The intercourse of
cities with one another is apt to create a confusion of manners; strangers
are always suggesting novelties to strangers.  When states are well
governed by good laws the mixture causes the greatest possible injury; but
seeing that most cities are the reverse of well-ordered, the confusion
which arises in them from the reception of strangers, and from the citizens
themselves rushing off into other cities, when any one either young or old
desires to travel anywhere abroad at whatever time, is of no consequence. 
On the other hand, the refusal of states to receive others, and for their
own citizens never to go to other places, is an utter impossibility, and to
the rest of the world is likely to appear ruthless and uncivilized; it is a
practise adopted by people who use harsh words, such as xenelasia or
banishment of strangers, and who have harsh and morose ways, as men think. 
And to be thought or not to be thought well of by the rest of the world is
no light matter; for the many are not so far wrong in their judgment of who
are bad and who are good, as they are removed from the nature of virtue in
themselves.  Even bad men have a divine instinct which guesses rightly, and
very many who are utterly depraved form correct notions and judgments of
the differences between the good and bad.  And the generality of cities are
quite right in exhorting us to value a good reputation in the world, for
there is no truth greater and more important than this--that he who is
really good (I am speaking of the man who would be perfect) seeks for
reputation with, but not without, the reality of goodness.  And our Cretan
colony ought also to acquire the fairest and noblest reputation for virtue
from other men; and there is every reason to expect that, if the reality
answers to the idea, she will be one of the few well-ordered cities which
the sun and the other Gods behold.  Wherefore, in the matter of journeys to
other countries and the reception of strangers, we enact as follows:--In
the first place, let no one be allowed to go anywhere at all into a foreign
country who is less than forty years of age; and no one shall go in a
private capacity, but only in some public one, as a herald, or on an
embassy; or on a sacred mission.  Going abroad on an expedition or in war
is not to be included among travels of the class authorized by the state. 
To Apollo at Delphi and to Zeus at Olympia and to Nemea and to the Isthmus,
citizens should be sent to take part in the sacrifices and games there
dedicated to the Gods; and they should send as many as possible, and the
best and fairest that can be found, and they will make the city renowned at
holy meetings in time of peace, procuring a glory which shall be the
converse of that which is gained in war; and when they come home they shall
teach the young that the institutions of other states are inferior to their
own.  And they shall send spectators of another sort, if they have the
consent of the guardians, being such citizens as desire to look a little
more at leisure at the doings of other men; and these no law shall hinder. 
For a city which has no experience of good and bad men or intercourse with
them, can never be thoroughly and perfectly civilized, nor, again, can the
citizens of a city properly observe the laws by habit only, and without an
intelligent understanding of them (compare Republic).  And there always are
in the world a few inspired men whose acquaintance is beyond price, and who
spring up quite as much in ill-ordered as in well-ordered cities.  These
are they whom the citizens of a well-ordered city should be ever seeking
out, going forth over sea and over land to find him who is incorruptible--
that he may establish more firmly institutions in his own state which are
good already; and amend what is deficient; for without this examination and
enquiry a city will never continue perfect any more than if the examination
is ill-conducted.

CLEINIAS:  How can we have an examination and also a good one?

ATHENIAN:  In this way:--In the first place, our spectator shall be of not
less than fifty years of age; he must be a man of reputation, especially in
war, if he is to exhibit to other cities a model of the guardians of the
law, but when he is more than sixty years of age he shall no longer
continue in his office of spectator.  And when he has carried on his
inspection during as many out of the ten years of his office as he pleases,
on his return home let him go to the assembly of those who review the laws. 
This shall be a mixed body of young and old men, who shall be required to
meet daily between the hour of dawn and the rising of the sun.  They shall
consist, in the first place, of the priests who have obtained the rewards
of virtue; and in the second place, of guardians of the law, the ten eldest
being chosen; the general superintendent of education shall also be a
member, as well the last appointed as those who have been released from the
office; and each of them shall take with him as his companion a young man,
whomsoever he chooses, between the ages of thirty and forty.  These shall
be always holding conversation and discourse about the laws of their own
city or about any specially good ones which they may hear to be existing
elsewhere; also about kinds of knowledge which may appear to be of use and
will throw light upon the examination, or of which the want will make the
subject of laws dark and uncertain to them.  Any knowledge of this sort
which the elders approve, the younger men shall learn with all diligence;
and if any one of those who have been invited appear to be unworthy, the
whole assembly shall blame him who invited him.  The rest of the city shall
watch over those among the young men who distinguish themselves, having an
eye upon them, and especially honouring them if they succeed, but
dishonouring them above the rest if they turn out to be inferior.  This is
the assembly to which he who has visited the institutions of other men, on
his return home shall straightway go, and if he have discovered any one who
has anything to say about the enactment of laws or education or nurture, or
if he have himself made any observations, let him communicate his
discoveries to the whole assembly.  And if he be seen to have come home
neither better nor worse, let him be praised at any rate for his
enthusiasm; and if he be much better, let him be praised so much the more;
and not only while he lives but after his death let the assembly honour him
with fitting honours.  But if on his return home he appear to have been
corrupted, pretending to be wise when he is not, let him hold no
communication with any one, whether young or old; and if he will hearken to
the rulers, then he shall be permitted to live as a private individual; but
if he will not, let him die, if he be convicted in a court of law of
interfering about education and the laws.  And if he deserve to be
indicted, and none of the magistrates indict him, let that be counted as a
disgrace to them when the rewards of virtue are decided.

Let such be the character of the person who goes abroad, and let him go
abroad under these conditions.  In the next place, the stranger who comes
from abroad should be received in a friendly spirit.  Now there are four
kinds of strangers, of whom we must make some mention--the first is he who
comes and stays throughout the summer; this class are like birds of
passage, taking wing in pursuit of commerce, and flying over the sea to
other cities, while the season lasts; he shall be received in market-places
and harbours and public buildings, near the city but outside (compare
Arist. Pol.), by those magistrates who are appointed to superintend these
matters; and they shall take care that a stranger, whoever he be, duly
receives justice; but he shall not be allowed to make any innovation.  They
shall hold the intercourse with him which is necessary, and this shall be
as little as possible.  The second kind is just a spectator who comes to
see with his eyes and hear with his ears the festivals of the Muses; such
ought to have entertainment provided them at the temples by hospitable
persons, and the priests and ministers of the temples should see and attend
to them.  But they should not remain more than a reasonable time; let them
see and hear that for the sake of which they came, and then go away,
neither having suffered nor done any harm.  The priests shall be their
judges, if any of them receive or do any wrong up to the sum of fifty
drachmae, but if any greater charge be brought, in such cases the suit
shall come before the wardens of the agora.  The third kind of stranger is
he who comes on some public business from another land, and is to be
received with public honours.  He is to be received only by the generals
and commanders of horse and foot, and the host by whom he is entertained,
in conjunction with the Prytanes, shall have the sole charge of what
concerns him.  There is a fourth class of persons answering to our
spectators, who come from another land to look at ours.  In the first
place, such visits will be rare, and the visitor should be at least fifty
years of age; he may possibly be wanting to see something that is rich and
rare in other states, or himself to show something in like manner to
another city.  Let such an one, then, go unbidden to the doors of the wise
and rich, being one of them himself:  let him go, for example, to the house
of the superintendent of education, confident that he is a fitting guest of
such a host, or let him go to the house of some of those who have gained
the prize of virtue and hold discourse with them, both learning from them,
and also teaching them; and when he has seen and heard all, he shall
depart, as a friend taking leave of friends, and be honoured by them with
gifts and suitable tributes of respect.  These are the customs, according
to which our city should receive all strangers of either sex who come from
other countries, and should send forth her own citizens, showing respect to
Zeus, the God of hospitality, not forbidding strangers at meals and
sacrifices, as is the manner which prevails among the children of the Nile,
nor driving them away by savage proclamations.

When a man becomes surety, let him give the security in a distinct form,
acknowledging the whole transaction in a written document, and in the
presence of not less than three witnesses if the sum be under a thousand
drachmae, and of not less than five witnesses if the sum be above a
thousand drachmae.  The agent of a dishonest or untrustworthy seller shall
himself be responsible; both the agent and the principal shall be equally
liable.  If a person wishes to find anything in the house of another, he
shall enter naked, or wearing only a short tunic and without a girdle,
having first taken an oath by the customary Gods that he expects to find it
there; he shall then make his search, and the other shall throw open his
house and allow him to search things both sealed and unsealed.  And if a
person will not allow the searcher to make his search, he who is prevented
shall go to law with him, estimating the value of the goods after which he
is searching, and if the other be convicted he shall pay twice the value of
the article.  If the master be absent from home, the dwellers in the house
shall let him search the unsealed property, and on the sealed property the
searcher shall set another seal, and shall appoint any one whom he likes to
guard them during five days; and if the master of the house be absent
during a longer time, he shall take with him the wardens of the city, and
so make his search, opening the sealed property as well as the unsealed,
and then, together with the members of the family and the wardens of the
city, he shall seal them up again as they were before.  There shall be a
limit of time in the case of disputed things, and he who has had possession
of them during a certain time shall no longer be liable to be disturbed. 
As to houses and lands there can be no dispute in this state of ours; but
if a man has any other possessions which he has used and openly shown in
the city and in the agora and in the temples, and no one has put in a claim
to them, and some one says that he was looking for them during this time,
and the possessor is proved to have made no concealment, if they have
continued for a year, the one having the goods and the other looking for
them, the claim of the seeker shall not be allowed after the expiration of
the year; or if he does not use or show the lost property in the market or
in the city, but only in the country, and no one offers himself as the
owner during five years, at the expiration of the five years the claim
shall be barred for ever after; or if he uses them in the city but within
the house, then the appointed time of claiming the goods shall be three
years, or ten years if he has them in the country in private.  And if he
has them in another land, there shall be no limit of time or prescription,
but whenever the owner finds them he may claim them.

If any one prevents another by force from being present at a trial, whether
a principal party or his witnesses; if the person prevented be a slave,
whether his own or belonging to another, the suit shall be incomplete and
invalid; but if he who is prevented be a freeman, besides the suit being
incomplete, the other who has prevented him shall be imprisoned for a year,
and shall be prosecuted for kidnapping by any one who pleases.  And if any
one hinders by force a rival competitor in gymnastic or music, or any other
sort of contest, from being present at the contest, let him who has a mind
inform the presiding judges, and they shall liberate him who is desirous of
competing; and if they are not able, and he who hinders the other from
competing wins the prize, then they shall give the prize of victory to him
who is prevented, and inscribe him as the conqueror in any temples which he
pleases; and he who hinders the other shall not be permitted to make any
offering or inscription having reference to that contest, and in any case
he shall be liable for damages, whether he be defeated or whether he
conquer.

If any one knowingly receives anything which has been stolen, he shall
undergo the same punishment as the thief, and if a man receives an exile he
shall be punished with death.  Every man should regard the friend and enemy
of the state as his own friend and enemy; and if any one makes peace or war
with another on his own account, and without the authority of the state,
he, like the receiver of the exile, shall undergo the penalty of death. 
And if any fraction of the city declare war or peace against any, the
generals shall indict the authors of this proceeding, and if they are
convicted death shall be the penalty.  Those who serve their country ought
to serve without receiving gifts, and there ought to be no excusing or
approving the saying, 'Men should receive gifts as the reward of good, but
not of evil deeds'; for to know which we are doing, and to stand fast by
our knowledge, is no easy matter.  The safest course is to obey the law
which says, 'Do no service for a bribe,' and let him who disobeys, if he be
convicted, simply die.  With a view to taxation, for various reasons, every
man ought to have had his property valued:  and the tribesmen should
likewise bring a register of the yearly produce to the wardens of the
country, that in this way there may be two valuations; and the public
officers may use annually whichever on consideration they deem the best,
whether they prefer to take a certain portion of the whole value, or of the
annual revenue, after subtracting what is paid to the common tables.

Touching offerings to the Gods, a moderate man should observe moderation in
what he offers.  Now the land and the hearth of the house of all men is
sacred to all Gods; wherefore let no man dedicate them a second time to the
Gods.  Gold and silver, whether possessed by private persons or in temples,
are in other cities provocative of envy, and ivory, the product of a dead
body, is not a proper offering; brass and iron, again, are instruments of
war; but of wood let a man bring what offering he likes, provided it be a
single block, and in like manner of stone, to the public temples; of woven
work let him not offer more than one woman can execute in a month.  White
is a colour suitable to the Gods, especially in woven works, but dyes
should only be used for the adornments of war.  The most divine of gifts
are birds and images, and they should be such as one painter can execute in
a single day.  And let all other offerings follow a similar rule.

Now that the whole city has been divided into parts of which the nature and
number have been described, and laws have been given about all the most
important contracts as far as this was possible, the next thing will be to
have justice done.  The first of the courts shall consist of elected
judges, who shall be chosen by the plaintiff and the defendant in common: 
these shall be called arbiters rather than judges.  And in the second court
there shall be judges of the villages and tribes corresponding to the
twelvefold division of the land, and before these the litigants shall go to
contend for greater damages, if the suit be not decided before the first
judges; the defendant, if he be defeated the second time, shall pay a fifth
more than the damages mentioned in the indictment; and if he find fault
with his judges and would try a third time, let him carry the suit before
the select judges, and if he be again defeated, let him pay the whole of
the damages and half as much again.  And the plaintiff, if when defeated
before the first judges he persist in going on to the second, shall if he
wins receive in addition to the damages a fifth part more, and if defeated
he shall pay a like sum; but if he is not satisfied with the previous
decision, and will insist on proceeding to a third court, then if he win he
shall receive from the defendant the amount of the damages and, as I said
before, half as much again, and the plaintiff, if he lose, shall pay half
of the damages claimed.  Now the assignment by lot of judges to courts and
the completion of the number of them, and the appointment of servants to
the different magistrates, and the times at which the several causes should
be heard, and the votings and delays, and all the things that necessarily
concern suits, and the order of causes, and the time in which answers have
to be put in and parties are to appear--of these and other things akin to
these we have indeed already spoken, but there is no harm in repeating what
is right twice or thrice:--All lesser and easier matters which the elder
legislator has omitted may be supplied by the younger one.  Private courts
will be sufficiently regulated in this way, and the public and state
courts, and those which the magistrates must use in the administration of
their several offices, exist in many other states.  Many very respectable
institutions of this sort have been framed by good men, and from them the
guardians of the law may by reflection derive what is necessary for the
order of our new state, considering and correcting them, and bringing them
to the test of experience, until every detail appears to be satisfactorily
determined; and then putting the final seal upon them, and making them
irreversible, they shall use them for ever afterwards.  As to what relates
to the silence of judges and the abstinence from words of evil omen and the
reverse, and the different notions of the just and good and honourable
which exist in our own as compared with other states, they have been partly
mentioned already, and another part of them will be mentioned hereafter as
we draw near the end.  To all these matters he who would be an equal judge
shall justly look, and he shall possess writings about them that he may
learn them.  For of all kinds of knowledge the knowledge of good laws has
the greatest power of improving the learner; otherwise there would be no
meaning the divine and admirable law possessing a name akin to mind (nous,
nomos).  And of all other words, such as the praises and censures of
individuals which occur in poetry and also in prose, whether written down
or uttered in daily conversation, whether men dispute about them in the
spirit of contention or weakly assent to them, as is often the case--of all
these the one sure test is the writings of the legislator, which the
righteous judge ought to have in his mind as the antidote of all other
words, and thus make himself and the city stand upright, procuring for the
good the continuance and increase of justice, and for the bad, on the other
hand, a conversion from ignorance and intemperance, and in general from all
unrighteousness, as far as their evil minds can be healed, but to those
whose web of life is in reality finished, giving death, which is the only
remedy for souls in their condition, as I may say truly again and again. 
And such judges and chiefs of judges will be worthy of receiving praise
from the whole city.

When the suits of the year are completed the following laws shall regulate
their execution:--In the first place, the judge shall assign to the party
who wins the suit the whole property of him who loses, with the exception
of mere necessaries, and the assignment shall be made through the herald
immediately after each decision in the hearing of the judges; and when the
month arrives following the month in which the courts are sitting, (unless
the gainer of the suit has been previously satisfied,) the court shall
follow up the case, and hand over to the winner the goods of the loser; but
if they find that he has not the means of paying, and the sum deficient is
not less than a drachma, the insolvent person shall not have any right of
going to law with any other man until he have satisfied the debt of the
winning party; but other persons shall still have the right of bringing
suits against him.  And if any one after he is condemned refuses to
acknowledge the authority which condemned him, let the magistrates who are
thus deprived of their authority bring him before the court of the
guardians of the law, and if he be cast, let him be punished with death, as
a subverter of the whole state and of the laws.

Thus a man is born and brought up, and after this manner he begets and
brings up his own children, and has his share of dealings with other men,
and suffers if he has done wrong to any one, and receives satisfaction if
he has been wronged, and so at length in due time he grows old under the
protection of the laws, and his end comes in the order of nature. 
Concerning the dead of either sex, the religious ceremonies which may
fittingly be performed, whether appertaining to the Gods of the under-world
or of this, shall be decided by the interpreters with absolute authority. 
Their sepulchres are not to be in places which are fit for cultivation, and
there shall be no monuments in such spots, either large or small, but they
shall occupy that part of the country which is naturally adapted for
receiving and concealing the bodies of the dead with as little hurt as
possible to the living.  No man, living or dead, shall deprive the living
of the sustenance which the earth, their foster-parent, is naturally
inclined to provide for them.  And let not the mound be piled higher than
would be the work of five men completed in five days; nor shall the stone
which is placed over the spot be larger than would be sufficient to receive
the praises of the dead included in four heroic lines.  Nor shall the
laying out of the dead in the house continue for a longer time than is
sufficient to distinguish between him who is in a trance only and him who
is really dead, and speaking generally, the third day after death will be a
fair time for carrying out the body to the sepulchre.  Now we must believe
the legislator when he tells us that the soul is in all respects superior
to the body, and that even in life what makes each one us to be what we are
is only the soul; and that the body follows us about in the likeness of
each of us, and therefore, when we are dead, the bodies of the dead are
quite rightly said to be our shades or images; for the true and immortal
being of each one of us which is called the soul goes on her way to other
Gods (compare Phaedo), before them to give an account--which is an
inspiring hope to the good, but very terrible to the bad, as the laws of
our fathers tell us; and they also say that not much can be done in the way
of helping a man after he is dead.  But the living--he should be helped by
all his kindred, that while in life he may be the holiest and justest of
men, and after death may have no great sins to be punished in the world
below.  If this be true, a man ought not to waste his substance under the
idea that all this lifeless mass of flesh which is in process of burial is
connected with him; he should consider that the son, or brother, or the
beloved one, whoever he may be, whom he thinks he is laying in the earth,
has gone away to complete and fulfil his own destiny, and that his duty is
rightly to order the present, and to spend moderately on the lifeless altar
of the Gods below.  But the legislator does not intend moderation to be
taken in the sense of meanness.  Let the law, then, be as follows:--The
expenditure on the entire funeral of him who is of the highest class, shall
not exceed five minae; and for him who is of the second class, three minae,
and for him who is of the third class, two minae, and for him who is of the
fourth class, one mina, will be a fair limit of expense.  The guardians of
the law ought to take especial care of the different ages of life, whether
childhood, or manhood, or any other age.  And at the end of all, let there
be some one guardian of the law presiding, who shall be chosen by the
friends of the deceased to superintend, and let it be glory to him to
manage with fairness and moderation what relates to the dead, and a
discredit to him if they are not well managed.  Let the laying out and
other ceremonies be in accordance with custom, but to the statesman who
adopts custom as his law we must give way in certain particulars.  It would
be monstrous for example that he should command any man to weep or abstain
from weeping over the dead; but he may forbid cries of lamentation, and not
allow the voice of the mourner to be heard outside the house; also, he may
forbid the bringing of the dead body into the open streets, or the
processions of mourners in the streets, and may require that before
daybreak they should be outside the city.  Let these, then, be our laws
relating to such matters, and let him who obeys be free from penalty; but
he who disobeys even a single guardian of the law shall be punished by them
all with a fitting penalty.  Other modes of burial, or again the denial of
burial, which is to be refused in the case of robbers of temples and
parricides and the like, have been devised and are embodied in the
preceding laws, so that now our work of legislation is pretty nearly at an
end; but in all cases the end does not consist in doing something or
acquiring something or establishing something,--the end will be attained
and finally accomplished, when we have provided for the perfect and lasting
continuance of our institutions; until then our creation is incomplete.

CLEINIAS:  That is very good Stranger; but I wish you would tell me more
clearly what you mean.

ATHENIAN:  O Cleinias, many things of old time were well said and sung; and
the saying about the Fates was one of them.

CLEINIAS:  What is it?

ATHENIAN:  The saying that Lachesis or the giver of the lots is the first
of them, and that Clotho or the spinster is the second of them, and that
Atropos or the unchanging one is the third of them (compare Republic); and
that she is the preserver of the things which we have spoken, and which
have been compared in a figure to things woven by fire, they both (i.e.
Atropos and the fire) producing the quality of unchangeableness.  I am
speaking of the things which in a state and government give not only health
and salvation to the body, but law, or rather preservation of the law, in
the soul; and, if I am not mistaken, this seems to be still wanting in our
laws:  we have still to see how we can implant in them this irreversible
nature.

CLEINIAS:  It will be no small matter if we can only discover how such a
nature can be implanted in anything.

ATHENIAN:  But it certainly can be; so much I clearly see.

CLEINIAS:  Then let us not think of desisting until we have imparted this
quality to our laws; for it is ridiculous, after a great deal of labour has
been spent, to place a thing at last on an insecure foundation.

MEGILLUS:  I approve of your suggestion, and am quite of the same mind with
you.

CLEINIAS:  Very good:  And now what, according to you, is to be the
salvation of our government and of our laws, and how is it to be effected?

ATHENIAN:  Were we not saying that there must be in our city a council
which was to be of this sort:--The ten oldest guardians of the law, and all
those who have obtained prizes of virtue, were to meet in the same
assembly, and the council was also to include those who had visited foreign
countries in the hope of hearing something that might be of use in the
preservation of the laws, and who, having come safely home, and having been
tested in these same matters, had proved themselves to be worthy to take
part in the assembly;--each of the members was to select some young man of
not less than thirty years of age, he himself judging in the first instance
whether the young man was worthy by nature and education, and then
suggesting him to the others, and if he seemed to them also to be worthy
they were to adopt him; but if not, the decision at which they arrived was
to be kept a secret from the citizens at large; and, more especially, from
the rejected candidate.  The meeting of the council was to be held early in
the morning, when everybody was most at leisure from all other business,
whether public or private--was not something of this sort said by us
before?

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  Then, returning to the council, I would say further, that if we
let it down to be the anchor of the state, our city, having everything
which is suitable to her, will preserve all that we wish to preserve.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Now is the time for me to speak the truth in all earnestness.

CLEINIAS:  Well said, and I hope that you will fulfil your intention.

ATHENIAN:  Know, Cleinias, that everything, in all that it does, has a
natural saviour, as of an animal the soul and the head are the chief
saviours.

CLEINIAS:  Once more, what do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  The well-being of those two is obviously the preservation of
every living thing.

CLEINIAS:  How is that?

ATHENIAN:  The soul, besides other things, contains mind, and the head,
besides other things, contains sight and hearing; and the mind, mingling
with the noblest of the senses, and becoming one with them, may be truly
called the salvation of all.

CLEINIAS:  Yes, quite so.

ATHENIAN:  Yes, indeed; but with what is that intellect concerned which,
mingling with the senses, is the salvation of ships in storms as well as in
fair weather?  In a ship, when the pilot and the sailors unite their
perceptions with the piloting mind, do they not save both themselves and
their craft?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  We do not want many illustrations about such matters:--What aim
would the general of an army, or what aim would a physician propose to
himself, if he were seeking to attain salvation?

CLEINIAS:  Very good.

ATHENIAN:  Does not the general aim at victory and superiority in war, and
do not the physician and his assistants aim at producing health in the
body?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And a physician who is ignorant about the body, that is to say,
who knows not that which we just now called health, or a general who knows
not victory, or any others who are ignorant of the particulars of the arts
which we mentioned, cannot be said to have understanding about any of these
matters.

CLEINIAS:  They cannot.

ATHENIAN:  And what would you say of the state?  If a person proves to be
ignorant of the aim to which the statesman should look, ought he, in the
first place, to be called a ruler at all; further, will he ever be able to
preserve that of which he does not even know the aim?

CLEINIAS:  Impossible.

ATHENIAN:  And therefore, if our settlement of the country is to be
perfect, we ought to have some institution, which, as I was saying, will
tell what is the aim of the state, and will inform us how we are to attain
this, and what law or what man will advise us to that end.  Any state which
has no such institution is likely to be devoid of mind and sense, and in
all her actions will proceed by mere chance.

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  In which, then, of the parts or institutions of the state is any
such guardian power to be found?  Can we say?

CLEINIAS:  I am not quite certain, Stranger; but I have a suspicion that
you are referring to the assembly which you just now said was to meet at
night.

ATHENIAN:  You understand me perfectly, Cleinias; and we must assume, as
the argument implies, that this council possesses all virtue; and the
beginning of virtue is not to make mistakes by guessing many things, but to
look steadily at one thing, and on this to fix all our aims.

CLEINIAS:  Quite true.

ATHENIAN:  Then now we shall see why there is nothing wonderful in states
going astray--the reason is that their legislators have such different
aims; nor is there anything wonderful in some laying down as their rule of
justice, that certain individuals should bear rule in the state, whether
they be good or bad, and others that the citizens should be rich, not
caring whether they are the slaves of other men or not.  The tendency of
others, again, is towards freedom; and some legislate with a view to two
things at once,--they want to be at the same time free and the lords of
other states; but the wisest men, as they deem themselves to be, look to
all these and similar aims, and there is no one of them which they
exclusively honour, and to which they would have all things look.

CLEINIAS:  Then, Stranger, our former assertion will hold, for we were
saying that laws generally should look to one thing only; and this, as we
admitted, was rightly said to be virtue.

ATHENIAN:  Yes.

CLEINIAS:  And we said that virtue was of four kinds?

ATHENIAN:  Quite true.

CLEINIAS:  And that mind was the leader of the four, and that to her the
three other virtues and all other things ought to have regard?

ATHENIAN:  You follow me capitally, Cleinias, and I would ask you to follow
me to the end, for we have already said that the mind of the pilot, the
mind of the physician and of the general look to that one thing to which
they ought to look; and now we may turn to mind political, of which, as of
a human creature, we will ask a question:--O wonderful being, and to what
are you looking?  The physician is able to tell his single aim in life, but
you, the superior, as you declare yourself to be, of all intelligent
beings, when you are asked are not able to tell.  Can you, Megillus, and
you, Cleinias, say distinctly what is the aim of mind political, in return
for the many explanations of things which I have given you?

CLEINIAS:  We cannot, Stranger.

ATHENIAN:  Well, but ought we not to desire to see it, and to see where it
is to be found?

CLEINIAS:  For example, where?

ATHENIAN:  For example, we were saying that there are four kinds of virtue,
and as there are four of them, each of them must be one.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And further, all four of them we call one; for we say that
courage is virtue, and that prudence is virtue, and the same of the two
others, as if they were in reality not many but one, that is, virtue.

CLEINIAS:  Quite so.

ATHENIAN:  There is no difficulty in seeing in what way the two differ from
one another, and have received two names, and so of the rest.  But there is
more difficulty in explaining why we call these two and the rest of them by
the single name of virtue.

CLEINIAS:  How do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  I have no difficulty in explaining what I mean.  Let us
distribute the subject into questions and answers.

CLEINIAS:  Once more, what do you mean?

ATHENIAN:  Ask me what is that one thing which call virtue, and then again
speak of as two, one part being courage and the other wisdom.  I will tell
you how that occurs:--One of them has to do with fear; in this the beasts
also participate (compare Laches), and quite young children,--I mean
courage; for a courageous temper is a gift of nature and not of reason. 
But without reason there never has been, or is, or will be a wise and
understanding soul; it is of a different nature.

CLEINIAS:  That is true.

ATHENIAN:  I have now told you in what way the two are different, and do
you in return tell me in what way they are one and the same.  Suppose that
I ask you in what way the four are one, and when you have answered me, you
will have a right to ask of me in return in what way they are four; and
then let us proceed to enquire whether in the case of things which have a
name and also a definition to them, true knowledge consists in knowing the
name only and not the definition.  Can he who is good for anything be
ignorant of all this without discredit where great and glorious truths are
concerned?

CLEINIAS:  I suppose not.

ATHENIAN:  And is there anything greater to the legislator and the guardian
of the law, and to him who thinks that he excels all other men in virtue,
and has won the palm of excellence, than these very qualities of which we
are now speaking,--courage, temperance, wisdom, justice?

CLEINIAS:  How can there be anything greater?

ATHENIAN:  And ought not the interpreters, the teachers, the lawgivers, the
guardians of the other citizens, to excel the rest of mankind, and
perfectly to show him who desires to learn and know or whose evil actions
require to be punished and reproved, what is the nature of virtue and vice? 
Or shall some poet who has found his way into the city, or some chance
person who pretends to be an instructor of youth, show himself to be better
than him who has won the prize for every virtue?  And can we wonder that
when the guardians are not adequate in speech or action, and have no
adequate knowledge of virtue, the city being unguarded should experience
the common fate of cities in our day?

CLEINIAS:  Wonder! no.

ATHENIAN:  Well, then, must we do as we said?  Or can we give our guardians
a more precise knowledge of virtue in speech and action than the many have?
or is there any way in which our city can be made to resemble the head and
senses of rational beings because possessing such a guardian power?

CLEINIAS:  What, Stranger, is the drift of your comparison?

ATHENIAN:  Do we not see that the city is the trunk, and are not the
younger guardians, who are chosen for their natural gifts, placed in the
head of the state, having their souls all full of eyes, with which they
look about the whole city?  They keep watch and hand over their perceptions
to the memory, and inform the elders of all that happens in the city; and
those whom we compared to the mind, because they have many wise thoughts--
that is to say, the old men--take counsel, and making use of the younger
men as their ministers, and advising with them,--in this way both together
truly preserve the whole state:--Shall this or some other be the order of
our state?  Are all our citizens to be equal in acquirements, or shall
there be special persons among them who have received a more careful
training and education?

CLEINIAS:  That they should be equal, my good sir, is impossible.

ATHENIAN:  Then we ought to proceed to some more exact training than any
which has preceded.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  And must not that of which we are in need be the one to which we
were just now alluding?

CLEINIAS:  Very true.

ATHENIAN:  Did we not say that the workman or guardian, if he be perfect in
every respect, ought not only to be able to see the many aims, but he
should press onward to the one (compare Republic)? this he should know, and
knowing, order all things with a view to it.

CLEINIAS:  True.

ATHENIAN:  And can any one have a more exact way of considering or
contemplating anything, than the being able to look at one idea gathered
from many different things?

CLEINIAS:  Perhaps not.

ATHENIAN:  Not 'Perhaps not,' but 'Certainly not,' my good sir, is the
right answer.  There never has been a truer method than this discovered by
any man.

CLEINIAS:  I bow to your authority, Stranger; let us proceed in the way
which you propose.

ATHENIAN:  Then, as would appear, we must compel the guardians of our
divine state to perceive, in the first place, what that principle is which
is the same in all the four--the same, as we affirm, in courage and in
temperance, and in justice and in prudence, and which, being one, we call
as we ought, by the single name of virtue.  To this, my friends, we will,
if you please, hold fast, and not let go until we have sufficiently
explained what that is to which we are to look, whether to be regarded as
one, or as a whole, or as both, or in whatever way.  Are we likely ever to
be in a virtuous condition, if we cannot tell whether virtue is many, or
four, or one?  Certainly, if we take counsel among ourselves, we shall in
some way contrive that this principle has a place amongst us; but if you
have made up your mind that we should let the matter alone, we will.

CLEINIAS:  We must not, Stranger, by the God of strangers I swear that we
must not, for in our opinion you speak most truly; but we should like to
know how you will accomplish your purpose.

ATHENIAN:  Wait a little before you ask; and let us, first of all, be quite
agreed with one another that the purpose has to be accomplished.

CLEINIAS:  Certainly, it ought to be, if it can be.

ATHENIAN:  Well, and about the good and the honourable, are we to take the
same view?  Are our guardians only to know that each of them is many, or
also how and in what way they are one?

CLEINIAS:  They must consider also in what sense they are one.

ATHENIAN:  And are they to consider only, and to be unable to set forth
what they think?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly not; that would be the state of a slave.

ATHENIAN:  And may not the same be said of all good things--that the true
guardians of the laws ought to know the truth about them, and to be able to
interpret them in words, and carry them out in action, judging of what is
and what is not well, according to nature?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly.

ATHENIAN:  Is not the knowledge of the Gods which we have set forth with so
much zeal one of the noblest sorts of knowledge;--to know that they are,
and know how great is their power, as far as in man lies?  We do indeed
excuse the mass of the citizens, who only follow the voice of the laws, but
we refuse to admit as guardians any who do not labour to obtain every
possible evidence that there is respecting the Gods; our city is forbidden
and not allowed to choose as a guardian of the law, or to place in the
select order of virtue, him who is not an inspired man, and has not
laboured at these things.

CLEINIAS:  It is certainly just, as you say, that he who is indolent about
such matters or incapable should be rejected, and that things honourable
should be put away from him.

ATHENIAN:  Are we assured that there are two things which lead men to
believe in the Gods, as we have already stated?

CLEINIAS:  What are they?

ATHENIAN:  One is the argument about the soul, which has been already
mentioned--that it is the eldest, and most divine of all things, to which
motion attaining generation gives perpetual existence; the other was an
argument from the order of the motion of the stars, and of all things under
the dominion of the mind which ordered the universe.  If a man look upon
the world not lightly or ignorantly, there was never any one so godless who
did not experience an effect opposite to that which the many imagine.  For
they think that those who handle these matters by the help of astronomy,
and the accompanying arts of demonstration, may become godless, because
they see, as far as they can see, things happening by necessity, and not by
an intelligent will accomplishing good.

CLEINIAS:  But what is the fact?

ATHENIAN:  Just the opposite, as I said, of the opinion which once
prevailed among men, that the sun and stars are without soul.  Even in
those days men wondered about them, and that which is now ascertained was
then conjectured by some who had a more exact knowledge of them--that if
they had been things without soul, and had no mind, they could never have
moved with numerical exactness so wonderful; and even at that time some
ventured to hazard the conjecture that mind was the orderer of the
universe.  But these same persons again mistaking the nature of the soul,
which they conceived to be younger and not older than the body, once more
overturned the world, or rather, I should say, themselves; for the bodies
which they saw moving in heaven all appeared to be full of stones, and
earth, and many other lifeless substances, and to these they assigned the
causes of all things.  Such studies gave rise to much atheism and
perplexity, and the poets took occasion to be abusive,--comparing the
philosophers to she-dogs uttering vain howlings, and talking other nonsense
of the same sort.  But now, as I said, the case is reversed.  (Compare
Republic.)

CLEINIAS:  How so?

ATHENIAN:  No man can be a true worshipper of the Gods who does not know
these two principles--that the soul is the eldest of all things which are
born, and is immortal and rules over all bodies; moreover, as I have now
said several times, he who has not contemplated the mind of nature which is
said to exist in the stars, and gone through the previous training, and
seen the connexion of music with these things, and harmonized them all with
laws and institutions, is not able to give a reason of such things as have
a reason (compare Republic).  And he who is unable to acquire this in
addition to the ordinary virtues of a citizen, can hardly be a good ruler
of a whole state; but he should be the subordinate of other rulers. 
Wherefore, Cleinias and Megillus, let us consider whether we may not add to
all the other laws which we have discussed this further one,--that the
nocturnal assembly of the magistrates, which has also shared in the whole
scheme of education proposed by us, shall be a guard set according to law
for the salvation of the state.  Shall we propose this?

CLEINIAS:  Certainly, my good friend, we will if the thing is in any degree
possible.

ATHENIAN:  Let us make a common effort to gain such an object; for I too
will gladly share in the attempt.  Of these matters I have had much
experience, and have often considered them, and I dare say that I shall be
able to find others who will also help.

CLEINIAS:  I agree, Stranger, that we should proceed along the road in
which God is guiding us; and how we can proceed rightly has now to be
investigated and explained.

ATHENIAN:  O Megillus and Cleinias, about these matters we cannot legislate
further until the council is constituted; when that is done, then we will
determine what authority they shall have of their own; but the explanation
of how this is all to be ordered would only be given rightly in a long
discourse.

CLEINIAS:  What do you mean, and what new thing is this?

ATHENIAN:  In the first place, a list would have to be made out of those
who by their ages and studies and dispositions and habits are well fitted
for the duty of a guardian.  In the next place, it will not be easy for
them to discover themselves what they ought to learn, or become the
disciple of one who has already made the discovery.  Furthermore, to write
down the times at which, and during which, they ought to receive the
several kinds of instruction, would be a vain thing; for the learners
themselves do not know what is learned to advantage until the knowledge
which is the result of learning has found a place in the soul of each.  And
so these details, although they could not be truly said to be secret, might
be said to be incapable of being stated beforehand, because when stated
they would have no meaning.

CLEINIAS:  What then are we to do, Stranger, under these circumstances?

ATHENIAN:  As the proverb says, the answer is no secret, but open to all of
us:--We must risk the whole on the chance of throwing, as they say, thrice
six or thrice ace, and I am willing to share with you the danger by stating
and explaining to you my views about education and nurture, which is the
question coming to the surface again.  The danger is not a slight or
ordinary one, and I would advise you, Cleinias, in particular, to see to
the matter; for if you order rightly the city of the Magnetes, or whatever
name God may give it, you will obtain the greatest glory; or at any rate
you will be thought the most courageous of men in the estimation of
posterity.  Dear companions, if this our divine assembly can only be
established, to them we will hand over the city; none of the present
company of legislators, as I may call them, would hesitate about that.  And
the state will be perfected and become a waking reality, which a little
while ago we attempted to create as a dream (compare Republic) and in idea
only, mingling together reason and mind in one image, in the hope that our
citizens might be duly mingled and rightly educated; and being educated,
and dwelling in the citadel of the land, might become perfect guardians,
such as we have never seen in all our previous life, by reason of the
saving virtue which is in them.

MEGILLUS:  Dear Cleinias, after all that has been said, either we must
detain the Stranger, and by supplications and in all manner of ways make
him share in the foundation of the city, or we must give up the
undertaking.

CLEINIAS:  Very true, Megillus; and you must join with me in detaining him.

MEGILLUS:  I will.